Abstract

This article examines contingencies and constraints in problem-solving processes underlying technological change and industry evolution. It shows how learning through practice can help drive technical change but, when this is impeded, the ability to make use of models and engage in experimental learning becomes even more pertinent for explaining variation in the rate and direction of technical change. The article explores HIV as an example of vaccine innovation, and vaccines as an example of medical innovation. I find the absence of these two variables (ability to learn directly in humans, and ability to learn vicariously through animal models) not only make up a large part of how I would characterize “difficulty” in the HIV R&D process, but they also seem to go a long way toward explaining why 33 other diseases have—or have not—had vaccines developed for them. Implications for theory and policy are discussed.

1. The uneven effect of research on practice

Why have we been able to put a man on the moon but not improve the plight of those in the ghetto? That question, posed nearly 40 years ago, remains as troubling today as it was then (Nelson, 2011). Some sectors of the economy yield extremely rapid change (e.g., transportation and telecommunications) compared to others (e.g., education and crime) (von Tunzelmann et al., 2008). Part of the variation is political and sociological in nature. However, a good deal of the variation we see in improvements in practice is related to the uneven growth of knowledge (Nelson, 2003, 2008).

The ability to learn from experiment has played an increasingly important role in economic growth and technical change over the past 150 years or so1 (Mokyr, 1990; Nightingale, 2014: 13). Among industries experiencing particularly rapid change, we see deliberate and designed experiment feature prominently. It allows for car crashes without cars, and aircraft flight without takeoff. Simulators and wind tunnels are complex learning technologies in themselves, highly prized by engineers (a car crash dummy can cost $500,000).2

This article explores how R&D and its technologies can lead to highly uneven effects on practice and how the cognitive and organizational conditions of knowledge growth can give rise to strikingly heterogeneous innovation outcomes. It examines contingencies and constraints in the problem-solving processes underlying technological change. The nature of these problem-solving processes, and the ability to incorporate them into organizational routines, have profound effects on industrial dynamics. They shape the contours of technological paradigms and help define the technological trajectories within them, as highlighted carefully in a special issue of this journal (Dosi, 1982; von Tunzelmann et al., 2008). Why some technological paradigms are more fruitful than others is an issue of central concern for policymakers and managers who make R&D resource allocations (Nelson, 2008; Teece, 2008).

Biomedical research commands a high degree of shared appreciation for the role it plays in bringing about new medicines and their subsequent impact on medical practice and health (Sampat, 2012). However, there is dissonance between the broad sociopolitical consensus for supporting biomedical research, and the unevenness in its outputs. For example, treatments for cardiovascular disease have improved quicker than for cancer (Lim et al., 2012). Looking within cancer also reveals large disparities in morbidity and mortality.3 In short, medicine exhibits variation (Consoli et al., 2016).

One might disregard some of the heterogeneity in medical innovation simply by labeling some problems as technically more difficult, but this does not make the question disappear; it merely pushes the analysis further back to what makes R&D problems more or less tractable. The central question of this article might also be put forth as: How do constraints and contingencies in R&D affect the performance of R&D trajectories?

What sets medicine apart from most other sectors of economic activity is not only that it is research intensive, or that is it is widely appreciated as being so, but that safety plays a paramount role. Defective technology in this domain can be harmful or lethal. This is of consequential importance because the ability to engage in experimental learning, where safety is not placed in jeopardy, becomes an even more salient variable in explaining variation.

Nowhere is safety more pivotal than in vaccines, a subsector of medicine that together with sanitation has been responsible for perhaps “the greatest benefit to mankind” (Porter, 1997). Vaccination is a technology which is mostly given to healthy people as a preventive, and often people who have extremely low tolerance for anything that might be seen as jeopardizing their safety (Yaqub et al., 2014).4

As to be expected, vaccines display heterogeneity too, some are developed quickly and others not at all. A number of explanations have been put forward to explain variation in vaccine innovation, ranging from market failure to sociopolitical neglect. However, the political economy of vaccine R&D investment explains only part of the observed variation. Advocates of increased research funding (Archibugi and Bizzarri, 2004) do not explain why poorly funded programs can succeed, while well-funded programs sometimes fail. Economists often assume demand constrains supply (Esparza et al., 2003; Pauly et al., 1995) and propose advanced market commitments (Kremer et al., 2006), intellectual property incentives (Lanjouw, 2003), and public–private partnerships (PPPs) (Buse & Waxman, 2001) as solutions.5 Sociologists, in contrast, focus on anti-vaccination movements (Nichter, 1995; Poltorak et al., 2005; Blume, 2006) and social processes for selecting between different technical options for a given vaccine (Blume and Zanders, 2006; Blume and Tump, 2010).

These explanations are all relatively silent on why vaccine innovation can be so difficult. Certainly, some diseases have been subject to market failure, sociopolitical neglect, and woeful underinvestment, but other diseases have not. HIV, for example, has benefited from a lucrative potential market, a high social profile and almost $1 billion a year in R&D; yet an effective HIV vaccine is not anywhere on the horizon of most scientists.

Using theory presented in the next section, I shall argue that the technical difficulty of R&D tasks is sharply influenced by a combination of the ability to learn in practice, and the ability to learn vicariously. In the context of medical innovation, these two variables transmute as follows: first, the extent to which it is safe to experiment on humans, and second, whether good animal models can be identified and used, with the latter especially important if there are strong constraints on experimenting with humans. Together they make up a large part of how I would define “difficulty” in medical innovation. If such a definition is to serve even tentatively as a way to understand difficult R&D domains, the distribution of innovation outcomes across a given sector should reveal systematic differences according to these variables. Across HIV vaccines, and vaccines generally, I find that they do.

The two variables, and their consequences for R&D trajectories, come into view when we adopt a framework that exposes learning in practice and testing in models (presented in Section 2). The first empirical section shows how HIV vaccine development in humans is extremely precarious, placing greater necessity and emphasis on animal models (Section 4). The second empirical section shows how R&D difficulty constrains the array of trajectories available within HIV vaccines, and explains why persistence in the only trajectory remaining will have costly implications (Section 5). Finally, I discuss the extent to which variation in vaccines against other diseases can be explained using these two variables (Section 6).

2. Testing regimes and their effects on innovation

Medical innovation, perhaps more than any other sector of industrial activity, holds dearly the notion that science is “translated” into technology. This downplays the critical and underappreciated role of learning from other sources (Nelson et al., 2011; Gittleman, 2016). Technology can precede the scientific theories that explain why they work. Steam engines preceded thermodynamics, airplanes flew before aerodynamics, and transistors antedate solid-state physics (Yaqub and Nightingale, 2012, Nightingale, 2014). This is possible because technologies are not merely applications of science. They are more usefully understood as emerging from a search for “operational principles” (Vincenti, 1990: 209), which define how technologies work and imbue them with a purpose, a process that is distinct from the goals of scientific endeavor. It is possible, after all, “to know how to produce an effect without knowing how an effect is produced” (Nightingale, 2004: 1271).

Technological knowledge, as distinct from applied science, has been described in engineering contexts such as aeronautics, chemicals, and electronics (Constant, 1980, Vincenti, 1990; Mowery and Rosenberg, 1998; Rosenberg and Steinmueller, 2013). There seems to be a similar corpus of knowledge for medical innovation, but this remains relatively underexplored (Consoli et al., 2016; Yaqub, 2017).

The presence of such bodies of knowledge is important for industrial organization because it serves to increase the endogeneity of science, as well as redefine the productivity of the technological paradigm. The growth of technological knowledge enhances the possibility of turning scientific research into marketable products and services and inspires confidence that future scientific research can be commercialized. So it strengthens the incentives for private actors to invest in basic research (Rosenberg, 1990).6

It is worth considering the other direction too and what happens when the accumulation of technological knowledge is hampered. Subsequent private investment in basic research may not be justifiable and, in such situations, efforts to shore up market demand would not help matters.7 These features of technological knowledge accumulation alter the appropriability of basic research and the endogeneity of science, and serve to redefine the productivity of the technological paradigm.

What this process involves deserves closer examination. Accumulating technological knowledge will typically involve the costly and time-consuming exploration of various dead ends to discover which uncertain operational principles work.

An important dimension of innovation therefore lies in deciding how far initial attempts should deviate from established operational principles that are already known to work. In most cases, this is a strategic decision that trades off the potential added value of an innovative design against the increased uncertainty and cost implications of redesign (Nightingale, 2014: 12). However, unlike many other sectors of the economy, safety plays a paramount role in medical practice, where malfunctioning technology can be harmful or lethal. So deviations from existing traditions of practice are constrained and redesign cycles are permeated with safety considerations throughout.

Even after operational principles have been found, considerable further development is often needed to establish safety under varying conditions. As such, safety and efficacy concerns overlap and interact throughout development. Many innovation processes now involve testing not only to trial the feasibility of inventions before going into full-scale operation but also to actively develop their products “off-line” (Nelson, 2008; Sarewitz and Nelson, 2008). Though in medical innovation, the scope for improvements through actual practice is often severely constrained, so off-line development (in animal models and in humans under highly controlled conditions) serves first and foremost as a way to vicariously explore the safety of putative operational principles. Consequently, learning through off-line testing becomes an even more important factor shaping the difficulty of medical innovation.

During off-line testing, we effectively move away from passive trial-and-error validation to active experimental intervention (Yaqub and Nightingale, 2012: 2144; Nightingale, 2014: 13–14). In “testing as validation,” testing is quicker, but, because it is atheoretical, it offers little guidance about what to do if the technology does not work. As Dougherty (2007: 267) put it, “people working on drug discovery are figuring out the limits to blind search the hard way.” Such testing might tell us about the safety and efficacy of a product quickly, but it tells us less about how to redesign and improve the product.8

In contrast, “testing as experimental intervention” is used to build artificial conditions in models, which can range from the highly purified to the more realistic. Simplifying assumptions can be gradually relaxed across a series of model organisms such as yeast and nematode worms through to zebra fish and mice. This generates a series of experimental stepping-stones, which trade-off ease of learning (simplicity) against clinical relevance (complexity) (Yaqub and Nightingale, 2012: 2144; Nightingale, 2014: 13–14). The way such conditions are measured and controlled is an important part of the invisible organizational infrastructure that allows learning to emerge from abductive reasoning (Dougherty, 2016).

Experimental models mediate between theory and practice (Morgan and Morrison, 1999), and have at least two other important characteristics that help form what Dougherty (2016) refers to as an infrastructure for emergence. First, models are heterogeneous; their variety is useful in that they allow for smaller leaps between stepping-stones. However, this very heterogeneity poses a challenge for coordination and management of the research effort (Yaqub and Nightingale, 2012; Yaqub, 2017). Comparing vaccines using virus types of differing pathogenicity, different delivery routes, in different doses, with different endpoints, might be meaningless. So models need to be standardized to a certain extent and may serve as gatekeepers before development can progress.9 Second, models are autonomous bodies of knowledge, that is to say, models are not necessarily given—they are created using instrumentalities (instruments, tools, and techniques, Price, 1984). Testing communities build up around practicing old techniques for doing something, produce a new technique by tinkering and fiddling with tools, and then deploy them on everything in sight (Baird, 2004).10

The virtues of being able to disconnect technical change from its environment need to be set against an important disadvantage. As I shall show in the empirical sections, formalized testing regimes can lock us into trajectories with less desirable performance characteristics (Dosi, 1982; David, 1985,Stirling, 2008). Perhaps, the analytical silver lining to being locked in is that we can look ahead along certain trajectories to glimpse into their future.

3. Study design and limitations

The theory section above suggests that innovation relies heavily on learning through actual practice, and where that option is not viable, innovation relies heavily on being able to move off-line and across a series of stepping-stones before going into practice. I explore situations where the pathogen is dangerous (limiting learning in practice) and where stepping-stones are missing (limiting ability to move learning off-line). I infer about their importance from the extensive management processes that attempt to “substitute for the missing prerequisites” (Gerschenkron, 1962: 359), as well as by comparing with other situations.11

I strengthen within-case validity by considering how these two key variables affect different trajectories of development (variation within HIV vaccines), and also cross-case validity by considering how HIV vaccine efforts are different to other diseases (variation between vaccines). The HIV case was selected due to its high profile and R&D funding to help control for prominent rival explanations.12 It is a deviant counter-theoretical case where key elements in the theory are missing, hampering the ability to accumulate technological knowledge. The case of vaccines was selected on the assumption that this is a sector whose innovation patterns will readily exhibit the effects of safety concerns. The pathogens sampled for cross-case analysis were selected using two-stage stratified sampling (theoretical then random sampling).13

The study design is nested, such that I explore HIV as an example of vaccine innovation, and I then discuss vaccines as an example of medical innovation. The article follows in a tradition of appreciative theorizing, using cases to illustrate and provide context to an explanation (Nelson and Winter, 1982: 46). Weakness of generalizability can be mitigated if cases are linked with a theoretical framework. The analysis in this article is therefore not based on extrapolating a pattern from cases. Instead, the cases are used to conjecture a falsifiable explanation about two specific and significant sources of variation in medical innovation outcomes.

An important limitation of this article’s approach is that it does not attempt to model the entirety of vaccine innovation. The aim was to develop an explanation of parsimony and utility, one that follows the aphorism, “all models are wrong but some are useful,” alert to what is importantly wrong, “it is inappropriate to be concerned about mice when there are tigers” (Box, 1976: 792). As such, this should only be considered an initial positioning article and a tentative first step toward understanding the role of these two variables in vaccine and medical innovation.

The data draw predominantly on scientific reviews and journals, as well as a range of historical sources, practitioners’ accounts, biographies, policy reports, newspaper articles, and publications by NGOs such as advocacy groups, charities, and foundations. The data were collected as part of a larger multiyear study into variation in vaccines and their R&D trajectories (Yaqub, 2008; Yaqub and Nightingale, 2012; Yaqub et al., 2014; Yaqub, 2017).

A particular strength of secondary data is the high reliability that comes from being able to revisit stable sources and interrogate them repeatedly while theory is being developed. Construct validity was strengthened using a triangulation approach with a varied range of sources, and technical accuracy was corroborated with immunologists, biochemists, physicians, and others in the scientific community. My training in biochemistry served well for navigating the technical literature.

The synthesized data were analyzed using two forms of pattern matching to strengthen internal validity. In the first (HIV vaccines specifically), I took the outcome as given but focused on how and why the outcome occurred. In the second (vaccines in general), I sought to find a variety of outcomes that are consistent with an argument.

4. The HIV vaccine trajectory as an archetypal example of difficult R&D

This section explains why HIV vaccine innovation fits our theoretically informed concept of difficult R&D. It explains why previous successes in vaccine innovation cannot be emulated against HIV. We see why learning online in humans is not possible, and how off-line development is hampered by the absence of animal models that offer suitable stepping-stones. The objective here is not to trace the exploration of various dead ends (which have been the source of much consternation and frustration) for the sake of historical record. Rather, by revealing the extensive efforts to substitute for missing stepping-stones, we can learn much about how models and experiments are used in the innovation process more generally.

4.1 Difficult to explore HIV vaccines in humans safely

“People have been talking vaccine, vaccine, vaccine for public consumption, and I have said it too. But I always scratch my head and say this [AIDS] is not the kind of situation where it is going to be easy to do the testing” (Unnamed US public health official, quoted in Altman, 1986).

As with all diseases, when a causative agent is definitively established, hopes for a vaccine flourish. When the pathogen causing AIDS was first discovered in 1985, hopes for an HIV vaccine ran so high that the US secretary of health declared that one would be ready in 2 years (Shilts, 1987: 451). Ideas for how a vaccine could work, operational principles, were initially plentiful. But after HIV was examined more closely, it became apparent that it would be extremely difficult to explore the feasibility of these ideas in humans safely. The virus has two important characteristics: its ability to evade “natural sterilizing immunity” and its extreme variation.

People who recover from a general infection are often able to clear it completely from their bodies and are immune from subsequent attack by the same pathogen. This is not so for HIV (McMichael and Hanke, 2003; Garber et al., 2004; Girard et al., 2006). “Natural infection with HIV does not result in virus clearance by the host immune system and the development of natural immunity to re-infection” (Girard et al., 2006: 4065). Humans can therefore be said to lack natural sterilizing immunity to HIV, with at least two implications.

First, this makes HIV vaccine development unforgiving in the sense that, should a vaccine designer’s attempted vaccination mistakenly infect the vaccinated, it cannot be cleared by the body afterward. Second, natural sterilizing immunity has previously provided clues in the development of vaccines. Its absence means that “the potential correlates of protection are not known, leaving us without a definite model of protective HIV immunity to emulate through vaccination” (Garber et al., 2004: 398). Historically, and with few exceptions, vaccine work begins with an empirical observation about natural protection, followed by attempts to copy or elicit the same type of protection by identifying markers of protection. With HIV, there is little for vaccine designers to mimic.14

HIV is the most variable virus discovered to date (Klein and Ho, 2000: 304). Influenza is also considered highly variable, but the variation in a single individual 6 years after HIV infection can be as great as the global variation for an influenza outbreak (Weiss, 2003: 12). Mutations at every possible (single nucleotide) point in HIV’s genome occur thousands of times per day (Johnson and Desrosiers, 2002). The longer HIV replicates in the host, the more diverse variants evolve, which may then allow the virus to escape immune responses. This serves to reduce the window of opportunity such that, “the success of vaccination may hinge on altering events that occur in the early hours following HIV exposure” (Graham, 2002: 209). In other words, the vaccine needs to clear the infection very quickly—unprecedented in vaccine history.

Suffice to say the two factors alone, lack of sterilizing immunity and extreme variation of HIV make HIV dangerous enough to rely heavily on animal models for vicarious development.15 However, the next section shows that animal models are not given—and nor are they inevitable. Their creation and use are contingent on the development of instrumentalities and management.

4.2 Difficult to learn about HIV vaccines from animal models

“When it comes to testing HIV vaccines, only humans will do” (British Medical Journal, Tonks, 2007).

The drive for animal-led HIV vaccine R&D has been problematic for a number of reasons. Foremost is that HIV is a primate virus capable of infecting only few animal species. Although HIV infects chimpanzees, it does not culminate in disease (AIDS) (Klein and Ho, 2000; Nath et al., 2000).16

Reviews readily acknowledge that “we have no truly useful small animal model” and “the lack of a truly representative animal model” for HIV vaccine development (Gallo, 1991: 1894; Klein and Ho, 2000: 304). Yet, much of the HIV literature discusses data derived from animals. The inconsistency originates partly from passive observations on the state of animals as they exist naturally, and partly from the considerable effort expended in creating new effects through experimental intervention. Thus, Girard et al. (2006: 4066) intone more actively, “the difficulty [lies] in developing an appropriate animal model [our italics].”17

For HIV, many researchers think animal models will never be predictive of overall human effects (Greek, 2012) or, at least, express extreme uncertainty about our understanding of what these testing conditions represent, “Even a vaccine that has 100% efficacy in all three challenge models might still be ineffective in humans. Conversely, a proficient vaccine developed in humans might never show benefit in the animal models” (Nath et al., 2000: 430).

Unrealistic models remain useful to researchers provided they know what aspects of the vaccine they are testing. For example, chimpanzees do not readily progress to AIDS in a human-like way (Klein and Ho, 2000), so the chimpanzee model is not helpful for studying how a vaccine might ameliorate disease progression. Instead, the model is more helpful for testing vaccines that aim to prevent infection outright because chimpanzees can be infected by HIV. So the usefulness of a model depends both on our understanding of the conditions that the model presents us with and on our ability to standardize what function is being tested for.

It is evident that researchers do not simply “make the best of what they’ve got.” They intervene by tinkering and creating new effects. This can be illustrated by the two main models used in HIV vaccine development, SIV and SHIV in monkeys, which involve changing both the virus and the animal.

SIV, the causative agent of simian AIDS (in macaque monkeys), is a close genetic relation to HIV. Smith says that “ … several different, but closely related, strains of SIV were developed for research purposes” (Smith, 2002: 101 [our italics]). Simian AIDS was quickly recognized as providing, “the flexibility to test not only potential vaccines but also to test and verify theories of pathogenesis or immunological correlations with disease. Accordingly, there are a multitude of pathogenic and nonpathogenic viral strains that can be used in therapeutic and challenge studies” (Nath et al., 2000: 429).

The SIV model was developed further when an SIV genome was engineered to carry a gene from an HIV isolate. These SIV/HIV chimera (hybrid viruses) became instruments known as SHIVs (Johnston, 2000). SHIVs can replicate in macaques and can become highly pathogenic, capable of generating a lethal AIDS-like syndrome within a year (rather than the 10 or so years often needed for HIV) (Girard et al., 2006). The use of multiple SIV “strains of differing virulence” (Feinberg and Moore, 2002: 207) allows for a series of simplified testing conditions that can gradually become more complex.

The sheer variety of animal models that have been developed allows researchers to, first, adjust testing conditions for iterating between learning and relevance (e.g., by varying virulence, routes, dosages, and similarity between vaccination and challenge) and, second, examine different aspects of infection in turn (e.g., “R5” and “X4” tropisms).18 When primate models are used without coordination between research groups, commensurability between the results of testing becomes problematic. For example, since “no macaque/SIV model was clearly more relevant than another, researchers chose to study different SIV strains in different species of macaques. The resulting experiments, of course, often make direct comparison impossible” (Smith, 2002: 101).

To ensure that results between different groups are comparable requires a concomitant increase in coordination and management demands. The very factors that provide researchers with flexibility and the ability to adjust testing conditions incrementally would then need to be standardized and agreed for cumulative learning.

5. Variation within HIV vaccines

It is of course possible to persist with inventive effort in difficult domains, where pathogens are dangerous and animal models are not available. Under such conditions, the paths of development that can be taken are severely constrained.

For HIV, the direction of inventive effort was forced away from the most common, tried-and-tested approaches to vaccine innovation as a direct result of the two variables highlighted in this article. One consequence, as we shall see, is lower-quality vaccines—which, counterintuitively, are harder and costlier to develop through a testing regime. Any efficacy trial requires many volunteers, but if the vaccine is of a low efficacy, then only very large studies will carry sufficient statistical power to be sensitive enough to detect efficacy of such vaccines. Similarly, if the vaccine does not have an immediate effect but may confer longer-term benefits, like limiting disease progression, then trials will need to track participants for that much longer.

Live and killed vaccines present a modified version of the whole virus to the immune system. Prior to 1980, all vaccines were made this way. A new approach was to present proteins, or subunits, from the virus. The subunit approach dominated HIV vaccine R&D (Gallo, 2005: 178; Johnston and Fauci, 2007). Since these vaccines feature only a small part of the virus, and crucially none of its genetic material, they can never cause the disease they are trying to prevent. Intuitively, they are safer, but they are also less likely to be effective because they present less of the virus to the immune system.

For most vaccine designers, killed and live trajectories were not viable, and the subunit approach was the only one left standing (Gallo, 2005: 1894; Klein and Ho, 2000: 309; see also Gittleman, 2016 for a discussion of the general affinity for the “genetic research paradigm”). Concerns about killed-inactivated vaccines centered around the possibility that, as happened in the Cutter incident of 1955, the whole virus may not be killed properly during manufacture. Concerns about the live-attenuated approach were even more serious (Fischinger et al., 1985). First, with such extreme variation, the weakened HIV could revert back to virulence. Designing a definitive test for measuring live vaccine safety is virtually impossible.19 Second, the weakened HIV virus might cause AIDS at a slower pace than the wild-type virus with vaccines developing AIDS 30 years after infection rather than 10 years. To respond effectively to such a criticism would require testing for 30 years, and even, then there is a good chance the result would be inconclusive.

Limits to the subunit approach, and their cost implications, have become increasingly evident over the past 20 years. After gp12020 went to major clinical trials in 1999, its failure was clear, “The complete lack of efficacy … has been proven beyond any doubt” (Girard et al., 2006: 4064). Another vaccine candidate underwent clinical trial but was abruptly halted in 2007, when it became clear that more people were being infected in the vaccine arm than in the placebo arm of the trial. The biggest clinical trial so far, involving about 16,000 people and costing $119 million, tested a vaccine candidate that is essentially a combination of the two failed vaccine preparations discussed above, in a so-called prime–boost approach. In 2009, the results suggested some efficacy, but the effect was limited and transient.

The underwhelming clinical trial results give rise to three possible responses. First, improve animal models and create new conditions for “testing as experimental intervention.”21 However, “different groups are challenging with different viruses making it problematic to compare the relative efficacy of the vectors and immunization strategies” (Sekaly, 2008: 10). The increase in varieties of models and techniques for using them puts more stress on research management.

Second, consider initiating trials in humans more readily, in the “testing as validation” tradition. However, this carries stubborn safety and cost implications. Less safe approaches (such as killed and live HIV vaccines) have not come anywhere near clinical trials, most likely because situations where such a risk would be tolerable are rare or nonexistent. Situations where risky technologies are given as a last resort to the dying are not afforded to vaccines because vaccines are usually given to the healthy. The safer subunit approach could be sent into clinical trials for every variant that results in the prospect of even a moderately effective vaccine, but this would become very expensive very quickly.

Third, aim for lower quality. Since the early 2000s, expectations of an HIV vaccine started to get downgraded to a new perspective. “It is unlikely that vaccine-induced immune responses will be able to prevent the establishment of [HIV] latency … A more realistic initial goal for HIV vaccine development is to dampen the initial viremia in an infected individual, maintain a low virus load, and prevent progression to AIDS” (Graham, 2002: 208). Smith crystallizes the shift, “vaccination, which may not affect the infection rate, may prevent disease” (Smith, 2002: 107). Preventing progression to disease, reducing transmission within the population, diminishing the spread of the epidemic; these fringe benefits become re-framed as more central virtues.

If an AIDS vaccine (rather than an HIV vaccine) was to reach clinical efficacy trials, then there would be difficulties in setting an endpoint to the trial. The often long incubation period (decades) between infection and disease means that staging a trial with disease as the clinical endpoint would require more years and more people for the testing to be persuasive. Participant retention would be challenging and costly. Few tests exist to detect subtle but important changes in patients that may occur, so setting these endpoints may not be obvious. The complexities of the testing regime seem to shape the characteristics of the technology being tested, in this case prevention, delayed onset of disease, symptom alleviation and reduced transmission.

For HIV/AIDS, it is becoming apparent that antiviral cocktail drugs are extremely effective in reducing viral loads to undetectable levels, allowing patients to resume normal lives (Fauci et al., 2014). Participants who become infected during a vaccine trial would need to be offered antiretroviral therapy according to most ethical interpretations, but these therapies are expensive and would add to the cost of vaccine trials.

There are also important analytical consequences to such provision. If everyone who became infected during a vaccine trial quickly began taking antiretroviral drugs, then it would be much trickier to tell whether the vaccine had delayed the disease. In such a setting, some of the vaccine’s potential benefits may go undetected. Even increasing the length or size of the trial may not clear up that kind of analytical problem. The development of highly active antiretroviral therapy (HAART) has served to increase the difference between ethical treatment conditions and effective learning conditions.

The development of HAART itself went through its own testing regime. Its trajectory may have suffered from a similar lack of animal models, but crucially, it was able to access online clinical learning much more easily. AZT, for example, was one of the early antiretrovirals that carried highly toxic side effects. It was possible to develop and improve such drugs online in patients who were desperately ill, had few alternatives and were willing to tolerate nonefficacy as well as bouts of nausea, fatigue, kidney malfunctioning, and lactic acid accumulation. In vaccine development, such symptoms would most likely prompt litigation. It was not long before the treatment trajectory was developed into HAART and hailed as a “game changer” (Gallagher, 2015).22

6. Variation between vaccines

It is not my intention for readers to interpret this article as an a priori technical exposition of whether an HIV vaccine will be possible. The question of why it has been so hard to develop a vaccine against HIV AIDS, I have argued, can be answered in large part due to two variables: first, a combination of the lack of natural sterilizing immunity and extreme variation, two factors which make the virus extremely dangerous; and second, the lack of suitable animal models. Moreover, these two variables have consigned vaccine efforts into a high-cost and low-quality trajectory. One might predict that an HIV vaccine either will not be developed in the near future, or if one is developed, it is likely to be a weak vaccine (which can of course still be useful). The implication is that alternative trajectories to vaccines may offer a more effective means for dealing with HIV.

When taken together with our theory, the evidence in Sections 4 and 5 allows one to posit that these key variables influence the difficulty of vaccine innovation against a range of other pathogens too. This is a useful proposition to explore because systematic variation would suggest that vaccines may not offer an equally effective vehicle for social and technical change for all diseases. The pursuit of diverse trajectories that include nonvaccine options is needed not least because, for some diseases, nonvaccine trajectories can be turn out to be vital when it becomes evident that the vaccine trajectory is heavily constrained.23

This section also serves as a robustness check, providing reassurance that the case has not been cherry-picked to suit our argument. The counter-theoretical case is a way of dealing with the unobserved nature of the counterfactual. A world where HIV is safe to explore in humans or where HIV can be modeled easily in animals does not exist, so we cannot use more traditional methods. To evaluate potential outcomes (the difference between what happens and what would have happened regardless), I compare to other diseases.

6.1 Explaining variation in vaccine innovation

If the pathogen is too dangerous to learn online in humans, then we can still learn off-line in animal models before progressing to humans. But if animal models are unavailable, and the pathogen is dangerous, then we would expect vaccine innovation to be constrained. Figure 1 displays the two key variables in a matrix, and plots pathogen-caused diseases for which vaccines have been developed and not yet developed. The diseases were selected theoretically (to ensure coverage across all four quadrants) and then randomly (from a list of pathogens).24

Explaining variation in vaccine innovation through scope for learning.
Figure 1

Explaining variation in vaccine innovation through scope for learning.

We see that Quadrant 1, which our theory predicts as being a “difficult” quadrant, includes diseases for which vaccines have not been developed yet (e.g., HIV and dengue fever), as well as other diseases where vaccines are poor quality [e.g., tuberculosis (TB) and malaria).25

In Quadrant 2, meaningful animal models were unavailable for measles, mumps, rubella, varicella and others. But online testing of vaccines could be undertaken in humans by a “guts and judgment” approach and with less reliance on animal models because these diseases are not usually life-threatening in their natural occurrence.

In Quadrant 3, our theory suggests vaccine innovation proceeds “tentatively,” because it is highly reliant on off-line testing in animal models. Poliomyelitis and Hepatitis A and B are potentially very dangerous, but it was possible to develop in vitro markers and correlates of immunity, and then develop through stepping-stones for safety before initiating clinical investigations. The use of such animal models as stepping-stones requires strong research management because there are a variety of ways in which they can be used and interpreted, as well as a variety of models themselves (Yaqub and Nightingale, 2012; Yaqub, 2017).26

Moreover, I have highlighted that animal models are not given and need to be actively developed. Diphtheria, poliomyelitis, and yellow fever are all notable for transferring from the first difficult quadrant to the third tentative quadrant following the advent of new techniques and development of better animal models. Remarkably, upon transfer into the third quadrant, vaccines were developed for each of the respective diseases. Together with our theory, this provides additional reason to think that the technical difficulty of innovation is not necessarily fixed.

Finally, Quadrant 4 is perhaps most responsive to demand, or “supply-elastic.” The SARS and H1N1 influenza vaccines were developed extremely quickly, under auspicious circumstances, namely, the fear of a global pandemic with potentially disastrous economic consequences. In contrast, typhoid vaccine remained largely undeveloped from its first iteration through to 1989, nearly 100 years, presumably because rich countries had improved their sanitation systems. And it is tempting to think that a vaccine against Streptococcus pyogenes might have been developed shortly after it was discovered in the 1930s, were it not for the fact that it is remarkably sensitive to penicillin and other antibiotics. Similarly, antibiotics and strong diagnostics have probably dampened vaccine innovation efforts for syphilis and chlamydia in Quadrant 3.

The safety and animal-model variables appear to be important for explaining the variation observed in vaccine innovation, which has been ignored or unnoticed by most economists and policymakers. They have tended to focus on incentives, conceding that technical opportunity may play a role, with little articulation of what that technological opportunity might look like and reflection on whether it is important for theory and practice. The emphasis on incentives has given rise to some important classes of medical innovation that have attracted attention. Neglected diseases and vaccines, to name two such classes, attract concerns that market incentives are too weak. No doubt this is true for some within these classes (say, in the supply–elastic quadrant), but there exists vast variation in the difficulty of respective R&D tasks for others (say, across all four quadrants).27

The evidence in this article suggests that rationales for funding vaccine R&D compared to other options bear rethinking. More strategic allocations for a given set of R&D resources might be made in cases like HIV AIDS and dengue where 64 and 71% of their entire respective R&D budgets are spent on vaccines; this compares to 19 and 20% for other “difficult” diseases like malaria and TB (Moran et al., 2009: 141–3). There also appears to be potential to harvest lower-hanging fruits in other cases. R&D for typhoid and cholera vaccines, diseases in the “supply-elastic” quadrant, are only 10 and 11% of their total R&D budgets (Moran et al., 2013: 38).

Similarly, medical innovation in treatments is widely assumed to benefit from stronger incentives than in preventives (Dranove, 1998; Kremer and Snyder, 2015). This is essentially where the rather cynical view—that pills are developed more readily than vaccines because they sell better—originates.28 But this article has suggested that incentives alone are not a sufficient and complete explanation; treatments can often benefit from online clinical learning because patients are more willing to tolerate side effects and nonefficacy. With HAART treatment and HIV vaccine preventives, we found the ability for their respective testing regimes to access online learning to have critical and contrasting effects on their innovation outcomes.

6.2 Implications for theory and practice

In medical innovation, difficult R&D is when there is a risk to safety and a lack of animal models, which, together, substantially hampers knowledge accumulation. This makes innovation processes qualitatively distinct by increasing the number of “redesign cycles” that must be explored. Our expectations about how easy it will be to develop products in difficult domains should be tempered, or our efforts increased, or both. Persisting with R&D in difficult domains, where trajectories are substantially constrained, may mean lower quality (in the case of HIV vaccine R&D, this could mean a vaccine of low-efficacy, low-durability, or low-breadth, if one at all). Moreover, and counterintuitively, low-quality vaccines are more expensive to test and develop.

The main messages of the article are more upbeat. First, the difficulty of R&D is not fixed, it can be shifted through the development of models, instrumentalities, and management. A fruitful line of enquiry would be to combine analysis of how instrumentalities and models develop, together with an examination of how cognitive learning processes (Tripsas and Gavetti, 2000; Kaplan and Tripsas, 2008) interact with experimental design (Nightingale, 2014; Dougherty, 2016). To this end, the article has shown that broad units of analysis that focus on learning capabilities and knowledge accumulation are helpful additions to approaches that take an exclusive focus on market positioning (see Kremer and Snyder’s (2006) explanation of why there is no AIDS vaccine).

Second, being able to better identify difficult R&D domains might allow R&D strategy (in terms of R&D resource allocations) to consider alternatives more readily. For diseases in the “difficult” quadrant of Figure 1, there are a number of nonpharmaceutical trajectories that could be pursued. None of these approaches are mutually exclusive, and they may need adaptation and development, so that they work in concert with one another as part of a sociotechnical system (e.g., HIV vaccine plus a microbicide, alongside preventive drugs for at risk populations). But for all of them, it seems worth exploring to what extent it will be possible to learn online and off-line to better assess opportunity costs, as part of a broader portfolio approach (Wallace and Rafols, 2015).

Third, the article brings into question the nature of the categories we use to describe and analyze industrial organization. Even in science-intensive innovation, we see hierarchies that are not reductive through Order, Family, Genus, and so on (Pavitt, 1984; Nightingale, 2008). There is little common essence between vaccine development and orthopedic surgery, yet both are loosely coupled together under the heading of medical innovation. This has important implications about how fine a level of industrial aggregation would be most useful for technology policy and analysis. As shown by seminal studies of the typewriter, the dynamo, and the Britannia Bridge (Rosenberg and Vincenti, 1978; David, 1985, 1990), we should not shy away from “dirtying one’s hands” with the details of technologies (Rosenberg, 1976: 2), if one wants to develop an appreciation for their particular sources and consequences.

The evidence in this article is consistent with the idea that formal R&D is not equally effective across all quarters. A research agenda that distinguishes where it is that R&D might have its most powerful effects could turn out to be extremely useful for decision makers.

Acknowledgement

I am deeply indebted to Richard Nelson and Paul Nightingale. I am grateful to Ronnie Ramlogan, Bhaven Sampat, three anonymous reviewers and many others over the years for their encouragement and thoughtful comments. I thank participants of the Neglected Diseases workshop in Brazil in November 2015 and the Workshop on Medical Innovation in December 2016. All remaining shortcomings lie solely with me. I acknowledge ESRC funding ES/L011409/1 and PTA-030-2003-01279.

Footnotes

1

This ability seems to have temporal coincidence with the kink in von Tunzelmann’s Hockey Stick. Economic growth was roughly a flat handle of unchanging real income per capita until around 1800 when a rising blade of growth kicked in. McCloskey (2013) notes that neither historians studying the handle nor economists studying the blade provide a theory that fits both pieces of the hockey stick.

2

Their effect is appreciated by engineers, “About half of the Institution of Electrical and Electronic Engineers annual list of the 200 top innovations is devoted to testing equipment” (Constant, 1980: 276).

3

Again, some variation is ostensibly political and sociological, for example, lung cancer tends to affect poorer segments of the population than does breast cancer (Anand et al., 2004). However, such explanations become harder to sustain when we consider that some lung cancer types (non-small cell) and some breast cancer types (T1) are easier to treat than others, or when we consider variation across, say, the 137 types of blood cancer.

4

A vaccine is a substance sufficiently like the disease-causing organism to generate a specific response in the immune system, but sufficiently different that the vaccine itself does not cause the infectious disease. The immune response that is most sought after is one that will protect from future infections, known as acquired immunity.

5

Brusoni et al. (2007) argue persuasively that PPPs should be seen less as corrections for market failure, and more as solutions to knowledge coordination challenges where a broker is needed to replace the role that large pharmaceutical firms often play (Brusoni and Geuna, 2003). In the case of vaccines, this seems plausible and complementary to the explanation put forward here.

6

As such, a fifth of all basic research in the United States is conducted by industry, and Rosenberg and Steinmueller (2013: 1152–5) go so far as to say that more basic research is what a discerning economist would expect following the successful accumulation of engineering knowledge.

7

Overlooking the role of technological knowledge may have contributed to unrealistic expectations of a biotechnology revolution; and now, the manifest failure of the revolution to materialize is prompting structural changes in the industry anew (Hopkins et al., 2007; Hopkins et al., 2013).

8

See Brodie-Kolmer failures in Yaqub (2017).

9

For example, the SHIV–macaque model quickly gained currency and acquired the status of “gatekeeper” for progression to clinical trials (Shedlock et al., 2009).

10

For example, Price noted how the telescope provided the conditions in which Galileo made his contributions, an experience which Price delightfully termed “artificial revelation” (1984: 9). This was not the validation of theories, but rather the trying out of new practices and techniques to create new conditions, hoping for learning opportunities, and then relating them to the world outside of these “unnatural conditions” (1984: 9).

11

Hence, the fact that HIV is an extreme outlier case with respect to both of these variables merely made them more salient, and facilitated their identification and characterization.

12

Our case selection also addresses a paucity of empirical study of failure (Staudenmaier, 1985; Denrell, 2003), which exists despite abundant theoretical evidence indicating that the majority of innovation attempts result in failure (Pavitt, 1999, or see any handful of the references cited in Section 2). While some may consider it premature to describe HIV as a failure case, it is difficult to regard it as anything more than “not yet successful” when prominent AIDS researchers remark, “the virus is winning” and “HIV is currently beating the crap out of us” (Hilleman, 1992: 1052).

13

Cases were selected to ensure coverage across our variables of interest, but then randomly from a list of pathogens published by the UK’s Health and Safety Executive (HSE, 2013) (see Section 7).

14

Some rare individuals offer ways forward. A small cohort of sex workers in Nairobi was found to be exposed but uninfected; however, their immunity was dependent on continued exposure (Nabel, 2001: 1002; McMichael and Hanke, 2003: 875). There are also some infected people who have managed to fend off the onset of AIDS for more than a decade, known as long-term nonprogressors or elite controllers (Johnston, 2000: 268). More recently, in Berlin, an HIV-positive patient, who took a bone marrow transplant from a patient with rare gene differences for their CCR5 receptor, was able to bring his viral count to nondetectable levels; however, efforts to repeat the effect in six other transplants all failed (Cox, 2015).

15

There are other technical obstacles that create formidable design specifications for HIV vaccine developers (e.g., HIV targets the immune system itself and infection can be transmitted by virus hidden inside cells as well as by free virus).

16

It replicates slower and does not gather in (and destroy) the lymph node architecture as quickly.

17

Monkeys were used to guide the way to poliomyelitis vaccines, despite the fact that they did not closely mimic what happened in humans (Yaqub and Nightingale, 2012). Monkeys do not normally become infected with poliomyelitis, but when injected directly into their brains, the virus is infectious and able to paralyze, giving rise to an animal model with clearly visible test results. Isabel Morgan’s experiments therefore facilitated the development of monkey models such that they could become incorporated into an effective testing regime.

18

For example, one notable difference between SIV and HIV is when and which of the CCR5 and CXCR4 chemokine receptors the virus binds with (Nath et al., 2000; Girard et al., 2006). In about half of the HIV-infected humans, HIV that binds to CCR5 predominates early and throughout the asymptomatic phase, but a shift toward binding to CXCR4 is observed, as these humans progress to AIDS. This shift in tropism to CXCR4 has not been reported in SIV-infected macaques (Johnston, 2000). SHIVs provide an opportunity to take a controlled look at each of these tropisms in turn.

19

If virus recovered from the victim resembled the wild type, one could suppose that it had replicated aggressively and driven away the vaccine virus (wild-type-induced disease). Alternatively, one could decide that the vaccine virus had changed to resemble the wild type and become virulent, thereby causing vaccine-induced disease. Either way, testing primary isolates would be unlikely to prove a vaccine guilty.

20

It was guessed that a large glycoprotein on HIV’s surface, gp120, would be the most immunogenic part of the virus on which to base the subunit approach upon. It showed some early success in animal models, but these successes needed to be interpreted with substantial caveats (e.g., weak strains and unusual routes were used for challenge).

21

Cats can now be infected with feline versions of the virus. Mice can now be engineered to contain human lymphoid cells and receptor proteins, so-called humanized mice (Denton and Garcia, 2011).

22

Now that HAART conveys vaccine-like properties—preventing transmission and infection—preexposure prophylaxis HAART attracts the hopes and excitement normally associated with vaccine innovation (Volk et al., 2015).

23

For HIV, significant impact might be achieved through behavioral changes that reduce risk of exposure, including condoms, and needle exchange programs, together with broader changes in women’s rights and sex work. For malaria, antimalarial drug development running alongside vaccine development echoes the case of HIV, but here again, there are alternative trajectories in vector control, such as bed nets and sanitation, that could be pursued. For TB, antibiotics, together with governance over how they are used, could offer hope beyond the existing low efficacy BCG vaccine—but for multidrug-resistant TB, one suspects that this strategy has run into diminishing returns and general changes in poverty conditions are required (Farmer, 1999).

24

I used the list of biological agents compiled by the UK’s Health and Safety Executive’s advisory committee (HSE, 2013). There are a number of international classification schemes for microorganisms based on their biological risks. The UK was the first to propose such a classification and, having been revised several times since 1975, is one of the most well established. I eschew their risk classifications because part of their consideration emerges from whether a vaccine exists, which would introduce endogeneity into our explanation. For our purposes, safe pathogens are ones that cause symptoms which normally clear (perhaps with routine treatment), and pathogens that model well in animals are ones that exhibit a similar disease pattern in humans and the animal(s).

25

Recent malaria vaccine trials have been encouraging but deploying a low-efficacy vaccine that requires three or four doses and whose effect wears off to nil after 7 years is an expensive option (Olutu et al., 2016). Moreover, there is the daunting prospect that after those 7 years, the malaria pathogen may have adapted to the vaccine, so a simple revaccination routine may not suffice. Vaccinated communities may even end up with higher infection rates than nonvaccinated communities, and be stuck with them indefinitely (Olutu et al., 2016).

26

While some might consider Ebola a difficult disease, given its recent high-profile coverage, it should be noted that several candidates had been found effective in animal primate models as early as 2000 (Jones et al., 2005).

27

There is now a plethora of PPPs focused on product innovation which seem well situated to address market failures and weak incentives but also seem to downplay the difficulty of the R&D tasks that lie ahead for some of them (Chataway et al., 2010). One might view their presence in developing countries either as capacity-building programs that benefit the broader health R&D landscape (Chataway et al., 2010: 1282) or, less charitably, as large distortions that draw resources away from other priorities whose combined burden and supply elasticity profile may make better investments (Moran et al., 2009: 145).

28

“Private companies find vaccines less financially rewarding than drugs. In 2001, the global marketplace for therapeutic drugs exceeded $300 billion, whereas worldwide vaccine sales were only about $5 billion … It is not hard to understand why major pharmaceutical companies, capable of developing drugs and preventive vaccines, generally invest in drugs that patients must take every day rather than shots given only occasionally. Drug company executives have investors to answer to, after all.” (Thomas, cited in Kremer and Snyder, 2006: 1).

References

Altman
L.
(
1986
),
Who will volunteer for an AIDS vaccine?
New York Times
15th April, C1.

Anand
S.
,
Peter
F.
,
Sen
A.
. (
2004
),
Public Health, Ethics, and Equity
.
Oxford University Press
:
Oxford, UK
.

Archibugi
Bizzari
2004
in
Research Policy
33
,
1657
1671
.

Baird
D.
(
2004
),
Thing Knowledge: A Philosophy of Scientific Instruments
.
University of California Press
:
Berkeley, CA
.

Box
G.
(
1976
), ‘
Science and statistics
,’
Journal of the American Statistical Association
,
71
(
356
),
791
799
.

Blume
S.
(
2006
), ‘
Anti-vaccination movements and their interpretations
,’
Social Science and Medicine
,
62
,
628
642
.

Blume
S.
,
Tump
J.
(
2010
), ‘
Evidence and policymaking: the introduction of MMR vaccine in the Netherlands
,’
Social Science and Medicine
,
71
,
1049
1055
.

Blume
S.
,
Zanders
M.
(
2006
), ‘
Vaccine independence, local competences and globalisation
,’
Social Science and Medicine
,
63
,
1825
1835
.

Brusoni
S.
,
Chataway
J.
,
Cacciatori
E.
,
Hanlin
R.
,
Orsenigo
L.
. (
2007
), ‘
The International AIDS Vaccine Initiative in a changing landscape of vaccine development: a public/private partnership as knowledge broker and integrator
,’
The European Journal of Development Research
,
19
(
1
),
100
117
.

Brusoni
S.
,
Geuna
A.
(
2003
), ‘
An international comparison of sectoral knowledge bases: persistence and integration in the pharmaceutical industry
,’
Research Policy
,
32
(
10
),
1897
1912
.

Buse
K.
,
Waxman
A.
(
2001
), ‘
Public-private health partnerships
,’
Bulletin of the World Health Organization
,
79
,
748
754
.

Chataway
J.
,
Hanlin
R.
,
Mugwagwa
J.
,
Muraguri
L.
. (
2010
), ‘
Global health social technologies: reflections on evolving theories and landscapes
,’
Research Policy
,
39
(
10
),
1277
1288
.

Consoli
D.
,
Mina
A.
,
Nelson
R. R.
,
Ramlogan
R.
. (
2016
),
Medical Innovation
.
Routledge
:
Oxford, UK
.

Constant
E.
(
1980
),
The Origins of the Turbojet Revolution
.
Johns Hopkins University Press
:
Baltimore, MD
.

Cox
D.
(
2015
),
HIV Immunity: rare gene differences offer hope for treatment
.
The Guardian
12th May.

David
P.
(
1985
), ‘
Clio and the Economics of QWERTY
,’
American Economic Review
,
75
(
2
),
332
337
.

David
P.
(
1990
), ‘
The dynamo and the computer
,’
American Economic Review
,
80
(
2
),
355
361
.

Denrell
J.
(
2003
), ‘
Vicarious learning, undersampling of failure, and the myths of management
,’
Organization Science
,
14
(
3
),
227
243
.

Denton
P.
,
Garcia
J.
(
2011
), ‘
Humanized mouse models of HIV infection
,’
AIDS Reviews
,
13
(
3
),
135
148
.

Dosi
G.
(
1982
), ‘
Technological paradigms and technological trajectories
,’
Research Policy
,
11
(
3
),
147
162
.

Dougherty
D.
(
2007
), ‘
Trapped in the 20th century: why models of organizational learning, knowledge and capabilities do not fit bio-pharmaceuticals, and what to do about that
,’
Management Learning
,
38
(
3
),
265
270
.

Dougherty
D.
(
2016
),
Taking Advantage of Emergence
.
Oxford University Press
:
Oxford, UK
.

Dranove
D.
(
1998
), ‘
Is there underinvestment in R&D about prevention?,
Journal of Health Economics
,
17
,
117
127
.

Esparza
J.
,
Chang
M. L.
,
Widdus
R.
,
Madrid
Y.
,
Walker
N.
,
Ghys
P. D.
. (
2003
), ‘
Estimation of needs and probable uptake for HIV/AIDS vaccines based on possible policies and likely acceptance (a WHO/UNAIDS/IAVI study)
,’
Vaccine
,
21
,
2032
2041
.

Fauci
A. S.
,
Marston
H. D.
,
Folkers
G. K.
. (
2014
), ‘
An HIV cure: feasibility, discovery, and implementation
,’
JAMA
,
312
(
4
),
335
336
.

Farmer
P.
(
1999
),
Infections and Inequalities
.
University of California Press
:
Berkeley, CA
.

Feinberg
M.
,
Moore
J.
(
2002
), ‘
AIDS vaccine models: challenging challenge viruses
,’
Nature Medicine
,
8
(
3
),
207
210
.

Fischinger
P.
,
Robey
W. G.
,
Koprowski
H.
,
Gallo
R. C.
,
Bolognesi
D. P.
. (
1985
), ‘
Current Status and Strategies for Vaccines against Diseases Induced by Human T-Cell Lymphotropic Retroviruses (HTLV-I, -II, -III)
,’
Cancer Research
,
45
(
9
),
4694
4699
.

Gallagher
J.
(
2015
),
An HIV ‘game changer’?
BBC Health
25th February.

Gallo
R.
(
1991
),
Virus Hunting
.
Basic Books
:
New York, NY
.

Gallo
R. C.
(
2005
), ‘
The end or the beginning of the drive to an HIV-preventive vaccine?,
Lancet
,
366
(
9500
),
1894
1898
.

Garber
D.
,
Silvestri
G.
,
Feinberg
M. B.
. (
2004
), ‘
Prospects for an AIDS vaccine
,’
Lancet Infectious Diseases
,
4
(
7
),
397
413
.

Gerschenkron
A.
(
1962
),
Economic Backwardness in Historical Perspective
.
Harvard University Press
:
Cambridge, MA
.

Girard
M.
,
Osmanov
S. K.
,
Kieny
M. P.
. (
2006
), ‘
A review of vaccine research and development: the Human Immunodeficiency Virus (HIV)
,’
Vaccine
,
24
(
19
),
4062
4081
.

Graham
B.
(
2002
), ‘
Clinical trials of HIV vaccines
,’
Annual Review of Medicine
,
53
,
207
221
.

Greek
R.
(
2012
), ‘
Animal models and the development of an HIV vaccine
,’
Journal of AIDS and Clinical Research
,
1
(
S8
),
1
11
.

Gittleman
2016
in
Research Policy
45
,
1499
1511
.

Hilleman
M.
(
1992
), ‘
Impediments, imponderables and alternatives in the attempt to develop an effective vaccine against AIDS
,’
Vaccine
,
10
(
14
),
1053
1058
.

Hopkins
M.
,
Martin
P. A.
,
Nightingale
P.
,
Kraft
A.
,
Mahdi
S.
. (
2007
), ‘
The myth of the biotech revolution: an assessment of technological, clinical and organisational change
,’
Research Policy
,
36
(
4
),
566
589
.

Hopkins
M.
,
Crane
P. A.
,
Nightingale
P.
,
Baden-Fuller
C.
. (
2013
), ‘
Buying big into biotech: scale, financing, and the industrial dynamics of UK biotech, 1980–2009,
Industrial and Corporate Change
,
22
(
4
),
903
952
.

HSE
(
2013
),
Approved List of Biological Agents
.
UK Health and Safety Executive
.

Johnson
W.
,
Desrosiers
R.
(
2002
), ‘
Viral persistence: HIV's strategies of immune system evasion
,’
Annual Review of Medicine
,
53
,
499
518
.

Johnston
M.
(
2000
), ‘
The role of nonhuman primate models in AIDS vaccine development
,’
Molecular Medicine Today
,
6
(
7
),
267
270
.

Johnston
M.
,
Fauci
A.
(
2007
), ‘
An HIV vaccine: evolving concepts
,’
New England Journal of Medicine
,
356
(
20
),
2073
2081
.

Jones
S.
,
Feldmann
H.
,
Ströher
U.
,
Geisbert
J. B.
,
Fernando
L.
,
Grolla
A.
,
Klenk
H. D.
,
Sullivan
N. J.
,
Volchkov
V. E.
,
Fritz
E. A.
,
Daddario
K. M.
,
Hensley
L. E.
,
Jahrling
P. B.
,
Geisbert
T. W.
. (
2005
), ‘
Live attenuated recombinant vaccine protects nonhuman primates against Ebola and Marburg viruses
,’
Nature Medicine
,
11
,
786
790
.

Kaplan
S.
,
Tripsas
M.
(
2008
), ‘
Thinking about Technology: Applying a Cognitive Lens to Technical Change
,’
Research Policy
,
37
(
5
),
790
805
.

Klein
E.
,
Ho
R.
(
2000
), ‘
Challenges in the development of an effective HIV Vaccine
,’
Clinical Therapeutics
,
22
(
3
),
295
314
.

Kremer
M.
,
Glennerster
R.
,
Williams
H.
. (
2006
), ‘
Creating markets for vaccines
,’
Innovations
,
1
,
67
79
.

Kremer
M.
,
Snyder
C.
(
2006
),
Why is there no AIDS vaccine?
Brookings Institute Paper
June 2006.

Kremer
M.
,
Snyder
C.
(
2015
), ‘Preventives versus treatments,’ NBER Working Paper 21012.

Lanjouw
2003
in
Innovation Policy and the Economy
3
,
91
129
.

Lim
S
, et al. (
2012
), ‘
A comparative risk assessment of burden of disease and injury: a systematic analysis for the Global Burden of Disease Study
,’
Lancet
,
380
(
9859
),
2224
2260
.

McCloskey
D.
(
2013
), ‘
Tunzelmann, schumpeter, and the hockey stick
,’
Research Policy
,
42
(
10
),
1706
1715
.

McMichael
A.
,
Hanke
T.
(
2003
), ‘
HIV vaccines
,’
Nature Medicine
,
9
(
7
),
874
880
.

Mokyr
J.
(
1990
),
Lever of Riches
.
Oxford University Press
:
Oxford, UK
.

Moran
M
,
Guzman
J.
,
Ropars
A. L.
,
McDonald
A.
,
Jameson
N.
,
Omune
B.
,
Ryan
S.
,
Wu
L.
. (
2009
), ‘
Neglected Disease R&D: How Much Are We Really Spending?,
PLoS Medicine
,
6
(
2
),
e1000030.

Moran
M
,
Guzman
J.
,
Chapman
N.
, et al. (
2013
),
G-Finder: Neglected Disease R&D
.

Morgan
M.
,
Morrison
M.
(
1999
),
Models as Mediators
.
Cambridge University Press
:
Cambridge, UK
.

Mowery
D.
,
Rosenberg
N.
(
1998
),
Paths of Innovation
.
Cambridge University Press
:
Cambridge, UK

Nabel
G.
(
2001
), ‘
Challenges and opportunities for development of an AIDS vaccine
,’
Nature
,
410
(
6831
),
1002
1007
.

Nath
B
,
Schumann
K. E.
,
Boyer
J. D.
. (
2000
), ‘
The chimpanzee and other non-human-primate models in HIV-1 vaccine research
,’
Trends in Microbiology
,
8
(
9
),
426
431
.

Nelson
R.
(
2003
), ‘
On the uneven evolution of human know-how
,’
Research Policy
,
32
(
6
),
909
922
.

Nelson
R.
(
2008
), ‘
Factors affecting the power of technological paradigms
,’
Industrial and Corporate Change
,
17
(
3
),
485
497
.

Nelson
R.
(
2011
), ‘
The moon and the ghetto revisited
,’
Science and Public Policy
,
38
(
9
),
666
668
.

Nelson
R.
,
Winter
S.
(
1982
),
An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change
.
Harvard University Press
:
Cambridge, MA
.

Nelson
R
,
Buterbaughb
K.
,
Perlb
M.
,
Gelijnsc
A.
. (
2011
), ‘
How medical know-how progresses
,’
Research Policy
,
40
(
10
),
1339
1344
.

Nichter
M.
(
1995
), ‘
Vaccinations in the third world: a consideration of community demand
,’
Social Science & Medicine
,
41
(
5
),
617
632
.

Nightingale
P.
(
2004
), ‘
Technological capabilities, invisible infrastructure and the un-social construction of predictability
,’
Research Policy
,
33
(
9
),
1259
1284
.

Nightingale
2008
in
Industrial and Corporate Change
17
,
533
583
.

Nightingale
P.
(
2014
), ‘What Is Technology? Six Definitions and Two Pathologies,’ SPRU Working Paper Series 2014-19.

Olutu
A.
,
Fegan
G.
,
Wambua
J.
,
Nyangweso
G.
,
Leach
A.
,
Lievens
M.
,
Kaslow
D. C.
,
Njuguna
P.
,
Bejon
P.
. (
2016
), ‘
Seven-year efficacy of RTS,S/AS01 malaria vaccine
,’
New England Journal of Medicine
,
374
,
2519
2529
.

Pauly
M
. et al. (
1995
),
Supplying Vaccine: An Economic Analysis of Critical Issues
.
IOS Press Amsterdam
:
Netherlands
.

Pavitt
K.
(
1984
), ‘
Sectoral patterns of technical change: towards a taxonomy and a theory
,’
Research Policy
,
13
(
6
),
343
373
.

Pavitt
K.
(
1999
),
Technology, Management and Systems of Innovation
.
Edward Elgar
:
Cheltenham, UK
.

Poltorak
M.
,
Leach
M.
,
Fairhead
J.
,
Cassell
J.
. (
2005
), ‘
MMR talk’ and vaccination choices: an ethnographic study in Brighton
,’
Social Science and Medicine
,
61
(
3
),
709
719
.

Porter
R.
(
1997
),
The Greatest Benefit to Mankind
.
Norton
:
New York, NY
.

Price
D.
(
1984
), ‘
The science/technology relationship, the craft of experimental science, and policy for the improvement of high technology innovation
,’
Research Policy
,
13
(
1
),
3
20
.

Rosenberg
N.
(
1976
),
Perspectives on Technology
Cambridge University Press
:
Cambridge, UK
.

Rosenberg
N.
,
Steinmueller
W.
(
2013
), ‘
Engineering knowledge
,’
Industrial and Corporate Change
,
22
(
5
),
1129
1158
.

Rosenberg
N.
,
Vincenti
W.
(
1978
),
The Britannia Bridge: The Generation and Diffusion of Technological Knowledge
MIT Press
:
Cambridge, MA
.

Rosenberg
1990
in
Research Policy
19
,
165
174
.

Sampat
B.
(
2012
), ‘
Mission-oriented biomedical research at the NIH
,’
Research Policy
,
41
(
10
),
1729
1741
.

Sarewitz
D.
,
Nelson
R.
(
2008
), ‘
Three rules for technological fixes
,’
Nature
,
456
(
7224
),
871
872
.

Sekaly
R.
(
2008
), ‘
The failed HIV Merck vaccine study
,’
Journal of Experimental and Clinical Medicine
,
205
,
7
12
.

Shedlock
D.
,
Silvestry
G.
,
Weiner
D. B.
. (
2009
), ‘
Monkeying around with HIV vaccines: using rhesus macaques to define ‘gatekeepers’ for clinical trials
,’
Nature Reviews Immunology
,
9
(
10
),
717
728
.

Shilts
R.
(
1987
),
And the Band Played On
.
St. Martin's Press
:
New York, NY
.

Smith
S.
(
2002
), ‘
HIV vaccine development in the nonhuman primate model of AIDS
,’
Journal of Biomedical Science
,
9
(
2
),
100
111
.

Staudenmaier
J.
(
1985
),
Technology's Storytellers
.
MIT Press
:
Cambridge, MA
.

Stirling
A.
(
2008
), ‘
Opening up” and “closing down” power, participation, and pluralism in the social appraisal of,
Technology. Science Technology Human Values
,
33
(
2
),
262
294
.

Teece
D.
(
2008
), ‘
Dosi’s technological paradigms and trajectories: insights for economics and management
,’
Industrial and Corporate Change
,
17
(
3
),
507
512
.

Tonks
A.
(
2007
), ‘
Quest for the AIDS vaccine
,’
British Medical Journal
,
334
,
1336
1348
.

Tripsas
M.
,
Gavetti
G.
(
2000
), ‘
Capabilities, cognition, and inertia
,’
Strategic Management Journal
,
21
(
10
),
1147
1161
.

Vincenti
W. G.
(
1990
),
What Engineers Know and How They Know It
.
Johns Hopkins University Press
:
Baltimore, MD
.

Volk
J.
,
Marcus
J. L.
,
Phengrasamy
T.
,
Blechinger
D.
,
Nguyen
D. P.
,
Follansbee
S.
,
Hare
C. B.
. (
2015
), ‘
No new HIV infections with increasing use of HIV preexposure prophylaxis
,’
Clinical Infectious Diseases
,
61
(
10
),
1601
1603
.

von Tunzelmann
N.
,
Malerba
F.
,
Nightingale
P.
,
Metcalfe
S.
. (
2008
), ‘
Technological paradigms: past, present and future
,’
Industrial and Corporate Change
,
17
(
3
),
467
484
.

Wallace
M.
,
Rafols
I.
(
2015
), ‘
Research portfolio analysis in science policy
,’
Minerva
,
53
,
89
115
.

Weiss
R.
(
2003
), ‘
HIV and AIDS in relation to other pandemics
,’
European Molecular Biology Organization
,
4
,
S10
S14
.

Yaqub
O.
(
2008
),
Knowledge Accumulation and Vaccine Innovation: Lessons from Polio and HIV AIDS
.
SPRU, University of Sussex
.

Yaqub
O.
,
Nightingale
P.
(
2012
), ‘
Vaccine innovation, translational research and the management of knowledge accumulation
,’
Social Science and Medicine
,
75
(
12
),
2143
2150
.

Yaqub
O.
,
Castle-Clarke
S.
,
Sevdalis
N.
,
Chataway
J.
. (
2014
), ‘
Attitudes to vaccination: a critical review
,’
Social Science and Medicine
,
112
,
1
11
.

Yaqub
O.
(
2017
), ‘
Testing regimes in clinical trials: Evidence from four polio vaccine trajectories
,’
Research Policy
,
46
,
475
484
.

This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted reuse, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.