Abstract

This paper explores connections between theories of morality and theories of properties. It argues that (1) moral realism is in tension with predicate, class and mereological nominalism; (2) moral non-naturalism is incompatible with standard versions of resemblance nominalism, immanent realism and trope theory; and (3) the standard semantic arguments for property realism do not support moral realism. I also raise doubts about trope-theoretic explanations of moral supervenience and argue against one version of the principle that we should accept theories that maintain neutrality.

I

Wilfrid Sellars claimed that ‘The aim of philosophy, abstractly formulated, is to understand how things in the broadest possible sense of the term hang together in the broadest possible sense of the term’ (1963, p. 1). My aim here is to consider how two particular things hang together: our understanding of morality and our understanding of properties.

To begin, distinguish two questions. First: what are the logical and pseudo-logical connections between theories of morality (M1, M2, …) and theories of properties (P1, P2, …)? Here logical connections include entailment and consistency. By ‘pseudo-logical connections’ I mean those weaker relations—such as coherence, evidential support and explanatoriness—that are often considered relevant to assessing the plausibility of collections of claims. This first question most obviously concerns connections between theories but extends easily to arguments. So, for example, we can ask whether the standard arguments in favour of P1 support M1. I consider this question in §iv.

Second, supposing that we have established some logical or pseudo-logical connections between theories and arguments in one area and another, how should we assess the bundles thus connected? For example, suppose there are reasonable arguments in favour of P1 and M1, but we have established that P1 entails the falsity of M1. How should we proceed? Modus ponens or modus tollens? A third option is to remain agnostic, accepting only that the combination has been ruled out. Another example: suppose there are plausible arguments in favour of two incompatible theories in some area, M1 and M2. And suppose that, in a distinct yet related area, there is only one theory—P1—that is consistent with both M1 and M2. Should we accept P1? Jussi Suikkanen’s (2024) paper offers a positive answer to this question, at least where P1 is the trope theory of properties and M1 and M2 are metaethical naturalism and non-naturalism, respectively. I offer an alternative view in §v.

What follows addresses these two questions in order. My approach is piecemeal, highlighting a few threads that others might later hang together more comprehensively.

II

It will help to know the content of some theories of morality and properties. Let us begin with the latter.

Here is my mug, next to my glasses. Both are blue, solid, and part of my office. What is going on? The aim of ontology is to give an account of the fundamental constituents of a real situation like this, ideally one that will be generalizable to all parts of the universe (Campbell 1990, p. 1).

It is natural to distinguish concrete objects, such as my mug or my glasses, from their features, such as blueness, solidity and parthood.1 The former are particulars, the latter properties.2 The first part of the job description for properties, therefore, is to furnish the natures of things.3 A second role concerns similarities: properties seem to be ways in which things can be genuinely resembling. For instance, my mug and my glasses share a genuine similarity: they are both blue. A third role concerns predication. Some predicates—such as ‘blue’—seem to attribute genuine features to objects. Properties are good candidates to be the things denoted by such predicates. On this view, just as singular terms like ‘Neil’s mug’ denote particular objects, predicates like ‘blue’ denote properties, with the copula ‘is’ enabling us to say that the latter characterizes the former.

These roles for properties are presented in order of increasing controversy. Not all parties accept that there are fundamental constituents of reality, or any thing at all, that plays these roles. Nevertheless, the phenomena here—natures, similarities, predication—are undeniable. An account of properties is an account of the nature of what, if anything, is the best candidate to play these roles and of the phenomena that underlie them.

On to the theories. The first—ostrich nominalism—denies that properties exist. On this view objects, like my mug, have natures such as being blue, however this state of affairs does not require the existence of an entity—blueness—that somehow inheres in the mug. Rather, the fact that my mug is blue can be taken as a basic fact about the world, requiring only the existence of the mug. Ostrich nominalists thus understand predication as follows:

(g) The sentence ‘a is F’ is true if and only if there exists an x such that ‘a’ designates x and ‘F’ applies to x.

The fact that ‘F’ applies to x is explained by the fact that x is F, which requires no existent corresponding to ‘F’ (Devitt 1997, p. 96). Extending the account, ostrich nominalists hold that all that is required to make claims like ‘a and b are both F’ true is the truth of the claims that ‘a is F’ and ‘b is F’. And, given (g), neither of these commits us to the existence of properties. One underlying principle here is the Quinean standard of ontological commitment: we are committed to the existence of all and only those entities required to make the sentences we affirm true (Quine 1997, pp. 82–5). Since properties are not required for the truth of claims like ‘Neil’s mug is blue’ and ‘Neil’s mug and glasses are both blue’, we are not ontologically committed to them.

A second view—predicate (or concept) nominalism—accepts that properties exist but holds that they are merely the ‘semantic shadows’ of predicates (or concepts). So, for an object to possess a property is for it to fall under the corresponding predicate. For two objects to be similar is for them to fall under the same predicate. The relation of ‘falling under’ is taken as primitive (Armstrong 1978, vol. I, pp. 11–27; Schiffer 2003).

A third view—class nominalism—takes properties to be sets or classes of particulars (Lewis 1997a).4 So, for an object to possess a property, for example, blueness, is for it to be a member of the class of blue things. For two objects to be similar in respect of some property is for them to be members of the same class. On this view, a sentence of the form ‘a is F’ is true if and only if a is a member of the class of things that are F. Possessing a property is explained in terms of class membership, not vice versa. Class membership is primitive, that is, requires no further existents in order to obtain. Class nominalists typically take classes to be mind- and language-independent, abstract (that is, non-spatio-temporal), and generated without restriction: any collection of particular things forms a class. Properties are therefore abundant: there are as many as there are classes of things, and many will not mark genuine similarities between their possessors. There is, for example, a property corresponding to the class of objects whose sole members are David Bowie, Averroes’ last meal, and the number seven. If we stipulate that ‘a is BAS’ is true if and only if a is a member of this class, then this property—BASness—is shared exclusively by Bowie, Averroes’ last meal, and the number seven, despite a lack of genuine similarity between them. Class nominalists typically take properties to be classes of actual and possible particulars, where the latter are understood as genuine existents, inhabiting non-actual yet concrete possible worlds (that is, class nominalists are typically modal realists). This is to allow for the possibility of properties without any actual instances, and to explain the distinctness of properties that, in the actual world, have exactly the same instances (Lewis 1997a, p. 173).

A fourth view—mereological nominalism—claims that properties are mereological wholes or fusions of particulars (Effingham 2018). Whereas a class of concrete particulars is abstract, and particulars are members, a mereological whole of concrete particulars is concrete, and particulars are parts. Mereological wholes are therefore located where all of their parts are located. On this view, for an object to possess a property is for it to be part of a mereological whole. For two objects to possess the same property is for them to be parts of the same whole. A sentence of the form ‘a is F’ is true if and only if a is a part of the mereological whole of F things. Possession of properties is explained in terms of parthood of wholes, not vice versa, and parthood is primitive. Mereological nominalists also typically accept unrestricted mereological composition: any two objects compose a further whole. Thus, as with class nominalism, they take properties to be abundant: there are as many as there are mereological wholes, and most will mark no genuine similarity between particulars. Again, as with class nominalism, mereological nominalists typically take properties to be constructions from actual and possible particulars, and for the same reasons.

A fifth view is resemblance nominalism. On this view a particular object, such as my mug, possesses the property of blueness just in case and because it resembles all other blue things (Rodriguez-Pereyra 2001). Objects share a property in virtue of resembling each other, and resemblance facts are primitive. A sentence of the form ‘a is F’ is true if and only if a resembles all other F things. Resemblance nominalism can (but need not) be understood as a form of class nominalism, according to which properties are classes of resembling particulars. Unlike other versions of class nominalism, this restriction allows resemblance class nominalists to hold that only some classes of particulars correspond to properties, maintaining the link between sharing a property and genuine similarity.

All nominalists deny the existence of universals. Property realists, on the other hand, identify properties with universals. A universal is an entity that can have multiple instances, remaining identical between them (Daly 1997, p. 140).5 Universals also mark genuine similarities between their instances. The universal blue, for instance, has one instance in my mug and one in my glasses, and this explains the similarity between them. Objects possess properties in virtue of instantiating the related universal. A sentence of the form ‘a is F’ is true if and only if there is a particular, x, such that ‘a’ designates x, a universal ɸ such that ‘F’ designates ɸ, and x instantiates ɸ. Varieties of realism are distinguished by their account of the nature of universals and instantiation. On one view—transcendental realism—universals are abstract, mind-independent entities that particulars partake in or imperfectly resemble (Russell 1912, ch. 9). Transcendental universals themselves are causally inert (because abstract) but their instances can be causally efficacious. On another view—immanent realism—universals are wholly located at each of their instances, which can be causally efficacious (Armstrong 1978, vol. II). On this view, to say that a particular instantiates a universal is to say that they are bound together in a state of affairs (such as my mug being blue). Such states are the basic furniture of the world, and particulars and universals are their co-dependent constituents (thus there are no bare particulars or uninstantiated properties). On both versions of realism, instantiation is taken as primitive (Edwards 2014, pp. 24–6).

Trope theory is an alternative to both nominalism and realism. According to it, the fundamental constituents of reality are tropes. A trope is a particular (that is, unrepeatable) entity of a specific nature, such as being blue. We can pick out tropes by using phrases such as ‘the blueness of my mug’, so long as we are not misled by this to suppose that the trope is a concatenation of two types of thing, universal and particular (Schaffer 2001, p. 249). Rather, tropes are simple (not made up of other types of thing) and fundamental (other categories are constructions of them). Tropes are also abstract, not in the sense of being non-spatio-temporal, but in the sense that ‘they (ordinarily) occur in conjunction with many other instances of qualities … and that, therefore, they can be brought before the mind only by a process of selection’ (Campbell 1990, p. 3). Tropes can also resemble each other (or fall into resembling classes) with this resemblance (or membership) taken as primitive (Williams 1997, p. 116; Campbell 1990, pp. 30–40; Ehring 2011).

According to trope theory, concrete particulars and properties are constructions of tropes. A concrete particular is a concurrent sum of tropes, for example, a blueness trope, a solidity trope, a mug-shape trope and so on, all bundled together. A property is a set of resembling tropes. Blueness, for instance, is the set of resembling blue tropes. For an object to possess a property, F-ness, is for a member of the set of resembling F tropes to be part of the concurrent bundle of tropes that constitute that object. For two objects to share a property is for a trope that is part of one concurrent sum of tropes to resemble a trope that is part of a second concurrent sum of tropes. And the sentence ‘a is F’ is true if and only if the concurrent sum of tropes, a, includes a trope which is a member of the resembling set of F tropes (Williams 1997, p. 119; Campbell 1990, p. 41).

These, then, are some of the options we have for an ontology of properties.6 In the next section, I turn to metaethics, to consider which of these views best fits moral realism.

III

Our moral practice involves the phenomena of thinking and speaking in distinctively moral terms, terms like ‘morally wrong’, ‘morally good’ and ‘morally virtuous’. The aim of metaethics is to give a systematic account of these kinds of phenomena, ideally one that will be generalizable without theoretical stress to all elements and types of moral practice.

The most popular metaethical theory is moral realism. Moral realists hold that moral judgements cognize mind-independent moral reality. On this view, moral thoughts are beliefs with moral representational contents. Indicative moral sentences represent reality in moral ways. Sincere utterances of such sentences serve to express such beliefs, thereby offering moral descriptions of the world. Moreover, some of these beliefs are true and made true by a mind-independent moral reality. The denizens of this reality are typically taken to include moral properties.7 The standard view, therefore, is that a moral predicate like ‘wrong’ denotes the moral property of wrongness, and to assert that ‘murder is wrong’ is to offer a representation of the world as one in which that property is possessed by the object denoted by the term ‘murder’. Moral predicates therefore have a property-ascribing function (Cuneo 2014, p. 241; Shafer-Landau 2003, p. 83 n. 36). Realists disagree amongst themselves about the nature of moral properties, for example, whether they are natural, supernatural or non-natural (which, for present purposes, I take to mean at least non-causal), and whether they are reducible to other types of property. They agree, though, that we need to postulate moral properties to explain the truth of moral predications, and to function as the referents of moral predicates.

Which theory of properties best coheres with the property-invoking claims of moral realism?

First, the properties moral realists invoke cannot be properties as conceived by predicate, class or mereological nominalists. The quickest way to see this is to note that properties as conceived by these theories need not mark genuine similarities between particulars, whereas moral realists hold that moral properties do mark such similarities. For example, according to class nominalism, BASness is a property, but there is no genuine similarity between all and only the three objects that are BAS. Realists hold, though, that there is a genuine similarity between all and only wrong actions: they are not-to-be-done. So realists will reject any theory of properties that treats wrongness and BASness equivalently.8,9 Similar arguments can be constructed, mutatis mutandis, for predicate and mereological nominalism. There is also a more particular reason moral realists should not accept predicate nominalism. According to moral realism, objects fall under moral predicates because they possess moral properties. According to predicate nominalism, objects possess moral properties because they fall under moral predicates. Combining these views generates explanatory circularity.

That leaves resemblance nominalism, transcendent realism, immanent realism and trope theory.10 All these views take possession of properties to mark genuine similarities between objects, which the moral realist will want to extend to the case of wrongness. However, moral realists seeking a companion here should choose carefully. One issue involves causation. Several of these theories of properties give a key role to causation in determining which similarities are genuine, and hence which properties exist.11 According to the immanent realist D. M. Armstrong (1997b), for example, we have reason to postulate universals in so far as their instances are involved in true singular causal statements. For example, it is the fire’s hotness, not the fire itself, that causes the water to boil. Relatedly, D. H. Mellor (1997) has argued that the strongest case for the existence of universals concerns causation: singular causation requires the truth of causal laws, which in turn quantify over properties. Which properties exist, on these views, is a matter of a posteriori investigation, with the properties winning an existence ticket being all and only those that feature in the laws of nature thus discovered. Armstrong and Mellor argue, further, that we cannot assume that the properties of everyday experience, such as blueness, are genuine, since there may be many different types of property (distinguished by causal powers) whose instances cause sensations of blue in ordinary observers. Trope theorists also typically take which tropes there are to be closely tied to causation. A standard argument in favour of tropes, for instance, is that they are required to be the relata in causal statements: the hotness of the fire causes the water to boil, where this hotness is at once particular and nature-furnishing, that is, a trope. ‘Tropes are the levers of the world’ (Schaffer 2001, p. 248). Resemblance nominalism has fewer direct connections to the notion of causation, but is still a risky partner for some moral realists. Resemblance nominalists typically take resemblance facts to be primitive and definitive only of the so-called ‘sparse’ or natural properties, so BASness is excluded (for example, Rodriguez-Pereyra 2002, pp. 50–1, 62–5). Resemblance nominalism is therefore an uneasy partner for moral realists who seek to deny the naturalness of moral properties, whether or not that notion is directly tied to causation.

Amongst immanent realists, trope theorists and resemblance nominalists, therefore, there is a common view that genuine properties are those whose instances can be causally efficacious or are otherwise natural. Applying such views to the moral case suggests that if moral realists accept any of these theories of properties, at least as traditionally presented, they are under pressure to accept that moral properties can have causally efficacious instances, or are otherwise natural. In short, these theories of properties best fit with naturalistic versions of moral realism (for example, Railton 1986).

For realists who deny the causal efficacy of moral properties—that is, non-naturalists—but who (being realists) accept that moral predicates have a property-ascribing function, there are two remaining options. The first is to adopt non-standard versions of resemblance nominalism, immanent realism or trope theory that reject the connection between genuine similarity and causation or naturalness. For realists who take this path one task will be to offer an alternative account of the type of similarity that makes for property-hood, one that allows for causally inefficacious yet genuine properties.12 There seem several options for non-naturalist realists here. They could argue, for instance, that genuine similarities are those that we need to deploy in explanation, where this is not limited to the causal case.13 Or they could argue that genuine similarities (hence properties) are those that we need to recognize for any intellectually indispensable project, where such projects include practical deliberation as well as (scientific) explanation (for example, Enoch 2011; FitzPatrick 2019).

The final option for non-naturalist realists is transcendental realism. At least as traditionally conceived, transcendental realism does not limit properties to those whose instances can be causally efficacious, so within this framework moral non-naturalists can take moral properties to be similarity-defining yet non-causal. However, it seems likely that the dialectic just rehearsed will also play out for this combination of views. This is because transcendental realists who are moral realists will want to claim that not every predicate that correctly applies to some object corresponds to a universal (consider ‘grue’ and ‘BAS’).14 So they too will need to offer a general account of which similarities are genuine and which are not, and non-naturalism rules out appealing to causation. Either way, therefore, moral non-naturalists require an account of genuine similarity that goes beyond the causal and naturalist accounts popular amongst property realists.

To sum up this section, I have argued for two claims. First, that moral realism is in theoretical tension with predicate, class and mereological nominalism. Second, that if non-naturalist moral realists adopt resemblance nominalism, immanent realism, transcendental realism or trope theory, they had best adopt non-standard versions of these views that reject the connection between genuine similarity and causation or naturalness.

IV

In this section, I consider connections between moral realism and some standard arguments for the existence of properties. It is noteworthy that in both ontology and metaethics, one type of argument is semantic: we need to postulate the existence of properties in order to make sense of our language (for example, Russell 1912, ch. 9; Shafer-Landau 2003, p. 24; Brink 1989, pp. 25–9). I argue that the standard semantic arguments for the existence of properties do not support moral realism.

According to the reference argument, there are some sentences that are true and involve terms that apparently refer to properties. Hence properties exist (Armstrong 1978, vol. I, pp. 58–63; 1997a, pp. 105–8; Lewis 1997b, pp. 194–6). Consider, for instance, predicates, and the simple sentence ‘a is F’. A tempting semantic analysis, revealing ontological commitment, is as follows:

(s) ‘a is F’ is true if and only if there is an x such that ‘a’ refers to x and there is a Y such that ‘F’ refers to Y, and Y is possessed by x.

On this view, predicates refer to properties. Hence, accepting that some sentences correctly apply predicates, we are committed to the existence of properties.

A second group of terms that involves apparent reference to properties is that of abstract singular terms. The following examples are common:

  • (1) Humility is a virtue.

  • (2) Redness is a sign of ripeness.

The truth of claims such as (1) and (2) seemingly commits us to entities corresponding to the terms ‘humility’ and ‘redness’, that is, to properties (Armstrong 1997a).

A related argument involves true sentences that apparently quantify over (rather than refer to) properties. Examples include:

  • (3) He has the same virtues as his father.

  • (4) There are undiscovered fundamental physical properties.

According to the quantification argument, there are some sentences—such as (3) and (4)—that are true and that apparently quantify over properties. So properties exist (Armstrong 1997a; Edwards 2014, pp. 6–7).

The reference and quantification arguments are not without critics. One type of response is to suggest paraphrases of the relevant sentences which preserve their meaning but eschew the apparent commitment to properties. A suitable paraphrase of (2), for instance, might be ‘Red fruits are ripe’ (Devitt 1997; Armstrong 1997a). A worry with paraphrasing responses, however, is that they are ad hoc. Even assuming that a suitable paraphrase can be found for these particular examples, there is no guarantee that they are always available.

David Lewis extends this criticism to offer a synthesis of the reference and quantification arguments. Considering sentences such as (1) and (2), he says:

Prima facie, these sentences contain names that cannot be taken to denote particular, individual things. What is the semantic role of these words? If we are to do compositional semantics in the way that is best developed, we need entities to assign as semantic values to these words, entities that will encode their semantic roles. Perhaps sometimes we might find paraphrases that will absolve us from the need to subject the original sentence to semantic analysis … But even if such paraphrases sometimes exist—even if they always exist, which seems unlikely—they work piecemeal and frustrate any systematic approach to semantics. (Lewis 1997b, pp. 194-5)

By a ‘compositional’ semantics Lewis means an assignment of meanings to sentences that can demonstrate how those meanings are built up systematically from the meanings of their constituent parts. Suppose we accept that such a semantics works best when it assigns entities to predicates like ‘red’ and abstract singular terms like ‘redness’, and that it works systematically when it assigns such entities to all meaningful predicates and abstract singular terms. What type of entities should it assign? Should it, for example, assign universals (the realist answer)? Or classes of particulars (the class nominalist answer)? Lewis prefers the latter because the former would break the connection between universals and genuine similarity. A dramatic example is provided by:

  • (5) Grueness does not make for resemblance among all its instances (Lewis 1997b, p. 195).

This sentence is true, and, given compositional semantics, there is reason to assign an entity as the semantic value of ‘grueness’. Yet if we took this entity to be a universal, we would be forced to deny one of the essential features of universals: the marking of genuine similarities. Best then, to take the entities assigned to abstract singular terms (and predicates) to be classes of particulars. This is Lewis’s conclusion. As far as compositional semantics is concerned, predicates and abstract singular terms are set-contributing rather than universal-ascribing (Lewis 1997b, p. 195; Edwards 2014, pp. 82–4).

The upshot is that the semantic argument supports class nominalism rather than any more substantial theory of properties. We saw in the previous section that class nominalism is inconsistent (or at least in tension) with moral realism. Therefore the semantic argument for the existence of properties does not support moral realism.15

V

This completes my partial investigation of the connections between theories of properties and morality. In this section, I consider the second of the two questions distinguished in §i: how should we respond to the connections thus established?

A natural principle is to start from the general and move to the particular. On this view we should first articulate and defend a general theory of properties, for example, and then apply it to the particular case of morality, forming our metaethical views accordingly. For example, if our theory of properties entails that properties are necessarily causal, then we should reject metaethical theories that posit the existence of causally inert moral properties (that is, non-naturalist realism). The risk of this strategy is one of over-generalization. This is the vice of forming a general theory of a phenomenon based on a limited range of its instances, and then taking that theory to determine our views in every other case. I think that sometimes this risk is manifest in moving from theories of properties to theories of morality. It is notable, for instance, how those formulating theories of properties take as their paradigms properties as they appear in perception or scientific explanation. It is perhaps not surprising if theories based on generalization from such cases rule out the possibility of autonomous, causally inert, moral properties.

Suikkanen (2024, §v) argues that trope theory is theoretically friendly towards moral non-naturalism in so far as it provides a framework in which the latter can explain moral supervenience. According to that framework, moral properties are properties of properties, and properties are sets of resembling tropes. So, for example, consider the maximal set, S1, containing all and only being-a-hurtful-lie tropes {T1, T2, …, Tn}. Suppose that all hurtful lies are wrong. Suikkanen’s trope theorist understands this situation as one where a wrongness trope, W1, is compresent with S1, where ‘compresence’ is the tie that bundles tropes together to form objects. This in turn provides an explanation of moral supervenience, as follows. Because the moral properties of a particular object are determined by the moral properties of the (non-moral) types it belongs to (such as the type: being a hurtful lie), any two particular objects that share all the same (non-moral) types will share the same moral properties. Hence there can be no moral difference without non-moral difference.

I am unsure whether trope theory is as helpful for non-naturalists as Suikkanen suggests. First, as he acknowledges, traditional versions of trope theory take tropes to be located in space and time (perhaps even individuated thus) and the compresence relation is understood in terms of spatio-temporal co-location (Williams 1997, pp. 115–17; Schaffer 2001). They also identify tropes with causal relata.16 Obviously, qua non-naturalist, Suikkanen’s trope theorist cannot accept this last view. But they seem hard pressed, too, to accept the first two, given that they take (some) tropes to be compresent with sets of tropes, and sets are typically taken to be abstract, that is, not spatio-temporally located.17 Second, it is unclear how, on trope theory, the moral properties of particular objects can be determined by the properties of the kinds to which they belong. For example, consider S1 (the maximal set of being-a-hurtful-lie tropes), which is compresent with a particular wrongness trope, W1. Now consider the particular lie that Jon told last Thursday, and the being-a-hurtful-lie trope it contains as a part, call this T1. T1 is a member of S1. Jon’s action is also wrong, so assume (for the time being at least), in line with the general trope theory of possessing a property, that this entails that T1 is compresent with a distinct wrongness trope, W2. The question now is why it should be the case that S1 being compresent with W1, and T1 being a member of S1, jointly determines T1 being compresent with W2. S1, W1, T1 and W2 are, after all, distinct, particular existents. Admittedly, the foregoing picture, which takes particular objects such as Jon’s lie to be compresent with wrongness tropes (like W2), is not one that Suikkanen explicitly attributes to the trope theorist (here my previous assumption lapses). Suikkanen describes the view as holding that ‘the primary bearers of normative properties are kinds’ (2024, §v, my emphasis). One might then ask how we are to interpret the implication that particulars like Jon’s lie are secondary bearers of normative properties. One might say (and this I take to be the view Suikkanen attributes to the trope theorist) that for Jon’s lie to be wrong just is for T1 to be a member of S1 and for S1 to be compresent with W1. But in that case, a particular action’s being wrong is not a matter of the tropes that constitute it including a wrongness trope—there is no wrongness trope that is compresent with the bundle of tropes that constitutes Jon’s action—which seems to abandon altogether the thought that objects possess moral properties in the same way that they possess non-moral properties such as being hurtful.18 A third worry is that we lack an explanation of why higher-order moral tropes are compresent only with maximal sets of resembling tropes (that is, with properties). Consider, for example, the non-maximal set S2, which contains all of the being-a-hurtful-lie tropes except T1. Suppose that S2, rather than S1, is compresent with wrongness trope W1. Then, accepting that the moral properties of particulars (that is, bundles of tropes) derive from the higher-order moral properties of the sets of tropes of which they contain a member, all of the actions that include being-hurtful-lie tropes are wrong, except Jon’s lie. And, moreover, this is compatible with Jon’s lie being exactly qualitatively identical with some other lies: a moral difference without a non-moral difference. It is unclear why such a situation could not arise, according to trope theory.19

Putting these worries aside, though, Suikkanen’s paper (§vi) draws a particular conclusion from the premiss that only the trope theory of properties is compatible with both naturalist and non-naturalist moral realism. The conclusion is that we should accept trope theory.

The general principle behind this argument seems to be as follows:

Positive Epistemic Neutrality (pen) . Other things being equal, we should accept theories in area A that uniquely do not foreclose otherwise live options in related area B.

In the case at hand, we are assuming that both realist non-naturalism and naturalism are—independent of the debate about properties—live options. Only trope theory does not determine the choice between them. Therefore, we should accept trope theory (other things being equal).

I am sceptical that pen is true. It appears to take something that is partly an artefact of our current state of knowledge (that a theory is neutral between theories that we cannot yet decide between) to be a reason to think that a theory is true. Ultimately, truth will not be neutral between B1 and B2, so it is unclear why the neutrality of A1 counts in favour of its truth. What might be the rationale for such a principle? Suikkanen’s autonomy assumption (§i) may be one:

[W]hich side in this debate [between naturalism and non-naturalism] is right ought to turn only on what is distinctive of the normative properties in particular … [This] entails that the metaethical debate should not be decided based on considerations external to the debate, for example, concerning the nature of properties generally. (Suikkanen 2024, p. 115)

I am sceptical. Which side of the debate between naturalism and non-naturalism is true certainly ought to turn on the nature of the properties posited by each side, but it may also turn on whether those proposed natures are consistent (or coherent) with any well-established theory of properties. With such a theory in hand, metaethical debates could well be decided, in part, by issues external to the moral case, issues such as the general nature of properties. Of course, this can only happen when we have a well-established general theory of properties. The risk of over-generalization is the risk that our actual theories might not be well-established. But we should not rule out the possibility that such theories, were they to be available, determine metaethical issues. This possibility seems to be part of many methodologies in metaethics (for example, Timmons 1999, ch. 1), and extends not just to general theories of properties but those of meaning and knowledge as well.

An alternative to pen is:

Negative Epistemic Neutrality (nen). Other things being equal, we should not accept theories in area A that foreclose otherwise live options in related area B.

nen avoids the objection to pen since it does not treat neutrality as a reason to think that a theory is true. nen seems especially plausible where area A is general (for instance, the theory of properties) and area B is one species that falls under it (for instance, the theory of moral properties). This is in part because of the vice of over-generalization: there is a risk, for example, that theory A1 only forecloses otherwise live options in B because the subject matter of B has not been considered in arguing for A1. Of course, if A1 is well-established (that is, one has a sufficient argument in favour of it), then other things are not equal and we should accept it, even if it forecloses what would otherwise be live options in B. In philosophical debates, however, most often other things are equal in this sense: few theories are well-established.

If we replace pen with nen, the imperative to accept trope theory does not follow. Granting that (class) nominalism, immanent realism and transcendent realism foreclose otherwise live options in metaethics, nen entails that we should not accept those theories (other things being equal). But from the fact that trope theory uniquely does not foreclose otherwise live options, it does not follow that we should accept it. Another option is agnosticism.20 On this view, in our current state of knowledge, it is less important to consider which views to accept as final truth, and more important to consider which views hang together. Accepting Suikkanen’s arguments, non-naturalism hangs best with transcendental realism or trope theory. Naturalism hangs best with immanent realism or trope theory. Methodologically, we can rest here, accepting (for the time being) no theory of properties, and no theory of moral properties, but instead merely recognizing the connections between them. What hangs together need not come down to earth.21

References

Armstrong
,
D. M.
1978
:
Universals and Scientific Realism
. 2 vols.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

——

1997a
:
‘Against “Ostrich” Nominalism: A Reply to Michael Devitt’
. In
Mellor and Oliver 1997
, pp.
101
11
.
First published in
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 61(4) (1980), pp. 440–9. Page references are to the reprint.

——

1997b
:
‘Properties’
. In
Mellor and Oliver 1997
, pp.
160
72
. First published in Kevin Mulligan (ed.), Language, Truth and Ontology, pp. 14–27. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992.

Brink
,
David O.
1989
:
Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Campbell
,
Keith
1990
:
Abstract Particulars
.
Oxford
:
Basil Blackwell
.

Cuneo
,
Terence
2014
:
Speech and Morality: On the Metaethical Implications of Speaking
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Daly
,
Chris
1997
:
‘Tropes’
. In
Mellor and Oliver 1997
, pp.
140
59
. Revised from the original, published in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 94(2) (1994), pp. 253–62.

Devitt
,
Michael
1997
:
‘“Ostrich Nominalism” or “Mirage Realism”’
. In
Mellor and Oliver 1997
, pp.
93
100
. First published in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 61(4) (1980), pp. 433–9. Page references are to the reprint.

Edwards
,
Douglas
2014
:
Properties.
Cambridge
:
Polity Press
.

Effingham
,
Nikk
2018
:
‘Mereological Nominalism’
.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
,
100
(
1
), pp.
160
85
.

Ehring
,
Douglas
2011
:
Tropes: Properties, Objects, and Mental Causation
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Enoch
,
David
2011
:
Taking Morality Seriously: A Defense of Robust Realism
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Feldman
,
Fred
2019
:
‘The Naturalistic Fallacy: What It Is, and What It Isn’t’
. In
Neil
Sinclair
(ed.),
The Naturalistic Fallacy
, pp.
30
53
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

FitzPatrick
,
William J.
2019
:
‘Open Question Arguments and the Irreducibility of Ethical Normativity’
. In
Neil
Sinclair
(ed.),
The Naturalistic Fallacy
, pp.
138
61
.
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Lewis
,
David
1997a
:
‘Modal Realism at Work: Properties’
. In
Mellor and Oliver 1997
, pp.
173
87
. Excerpted from David Lewis, On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell, 1986.

——

1997b
:
‘New Work for a Theory of Universals’
. In
Mellor and Oliver 1997
, pp.
188
227
. First published in Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4) (1983), pp. 343–77. Page references are to the reprint.

Mellor
,
D. H.
1997
:
‘Properties and Predicates’
. In
Mellor and Oliver 1997
, pp.
255
67
. First published in D. H. Mellor, Matters of Metaphysics, pp. 170–82. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.

——and

Alex
Oliver
1997
:
Properties
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Quine
,
W. V.
1997
:
‘On What There Is’
. In
Mellor and Oliver 1997
, pp.
74
88
. Review of Metaphysics, 2 (1948), pp. 21–38. Page references are to the reprint.

Railton
,
Peter
1986
:
‘Moral Realism’
.
Philosophical Review
,
95
(
2
), pp.
163
207
.

Rodriguez-Pereyra
,
Gonzalo
2001
:
‘Resemblance Nominalism and Russell’s Regress’
.
Australasian Journal of Philosophy
,
79
(
3
), pp.
395
408
.

——

2002
:
Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals
.
New York
:
Oxford University Press
.

Russell
,
Bertrand
1912
:
The Problems of Philosophy.
London
:
Williams and Norgate
.

Schaffer
,
Jonathan
2001
:
‘The Individuation of Tropes’
.
Australasian Journal of Philosophy
,
79
(
2
), pp.
247
57
.

Schiffer
,
Stephen
2003
:
The Things We Mean
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Sellars
,
Wilfrid
1963
:
Science, Perception and Reality
.
London
:
Routledge and Kegan Paul
.

Shafer-Landau
,
Russ
2003
:
Moral Realism: A Defence.
Oxford
:
Clarendon Press
.

Sinclair
,
Neil
2021
:
Practical Expressivism.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Skarsaune
,
Knut Olav
2015
:
‘How to Be a Moral Platonist’
. In
Russ
Shafer-Landau
(ed.),
Oxford Studies in Metaethics
, vol.
10
, pp.
245
72
. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Suikkanen
,
Jussi
2024
:
‘Metaethics and the Nature of Properties’
.
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume
98
, pp.
113
132
.

Timmons
,
Mark
1999
:
Morality Without Foundations
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Whittle
,
Ann
2009
:
‘Causal Nominalism’
. In
Toby
Handfied
(ed.),
Dispositions and Causes
.
Oxford
:
Oxford University Press
.

Williams
,
Donald C.
1997
:
‘On the Elements of Being:
i
. In
Mellor and Oliver 1997
, pp.
112
24
. First published in Review of Metaphysics, 7 (1953), pp. 3–18. Page references are to the reprint.

Footnotes

1

I use the term ‘object’ inclusively to mean any referent of a singular term, including actions, events, people, sets, and so on. By ‘concrete object’ I mean one existing in space and time.

2

I follow Feldman’s (2019) ‘ness-ity-hood’ principle: to talk about properties take the relevant adjective and add ‘ness’ or ‘ity’ or ‘hood’. My term ‘properties’ includes both monadic properties and relations.

3

The phrase ‘nature-furnishing’ comes from Campbell (1990, p. 131). The job description metaphor is from Edwards (2014, pp. 8–11).

4

Lewis (1997b) appends class nominalism with an account of sparse properties as those constituted by natural classes, where naturalness is primitive.

5

The distinction between particulars and universals is controversial. For one proposal, see Ehring (2011).

6

My list is not exhaustive. For example, I have excluded views which hold that there is more than one type of property (for instance, Lewis 1997b).

7

Given ostrich nominalism, this is not compulsory. I’m not aware of any moral ostriches.

8

Suikkanen argues that moral realists should reject class nominalism because it entails that necessarily co-extensive properties are identical (‘intensionalism’), which, together with Frank Jackson’s supervenience argument, rules out the possibility of non-natural moral properties. However, not all class nominalists accept intensionalism (for example, Lewis 1997a, pp. 176–7). Jackson’s conclusion is also consistent with many of the important claims of the non-naturalist position, for example, that moral predicates have sui generis meaning, that their application is not known a posteriori, and that they do not feature in causal laws.

9

Some versions of class nominalism may seek to draw distinctions here, for example, by positing a naturalness primitive that characterizes some but not all classes (see Lewis 1997b, p. 194). However, such a strategy is not available to non-naturalist realists.

10

Lewis’s hybrid nominalism (1997b) could also be included here, given the connections it draws between naturalness and causation.

11

See also Whittle (2009).

12

Or else take genuine similarity as primitive.

13

Consider, for example, the rationalizing explanation of moral practice offered in Shafer-Landau (2003) or the ingredient explanation of speech offered in Cuneo (2014).

14

For instance, Plato (Parmenides 130b–d) denied that there are Forms of hair or dirt.

15

Nor does it rule out moral expressivism, since expressivists can claim that predicates serving to express attitudes also contribute sets of objects to compositional semantics, namely, those sets of objects which are the objects of the attitude. This also distances expressivism from the paraphrase strategy. See Sinclair (2021, ch. 6).

16

Traditional versions of trope theory (for instance, Campbell 1990, p. 93) also reject modal realism, in contrast with Suikkanen’s trope theorist.

17

As Suikkanen suggests, this assumption may not be necessary. The alternative takes wrongness tropes to be compresent with spatio-temporally scattered objects and thus themselves spatio-temporally scattered. This seems at least in tension with traditional accounts of trope individuation (for example, Schaffer 2001).

18

I take this worry to apply only to the trope-theoretic version of the higher-order property explanation of supervenience. The moral Platonist (for instance, Skarsaune 2015) can hold that the universal of wrongness instantiated by action-kinds is necessarily related to the distinct universal of wrongness instantiated by particular actions.

19

Again, the moral Platonist does not face this problem, because on their view higher-order properties are properties of universals, not sets. There is no universal equivalent to the set S2 which might possess a higher-order moral property.

20

I assume that the ‘should’ involved in pen and nen is directly epistemic (that is, concerning the truth of the theories in question). There may be prudential, or indirectly epistemic, reasons to accept a permissive theory rather than remain agnostic, for example, because doing so is more psychologically comfortable or discursively fruitful.

21

I would like to thank Jussi Suikkanen and Jessica Leech for their invaluable input in helping me think about these topics.

This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted reuse, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.