-
PDF
- Split View
-
Views
-
Cite
Cite
Christian Ewerhart, Julia Lareida, Voluntary Disclosure in Asymmetric Contests, The Review of Economic Studies, Volume 91, Issue 6, November 2024, Pages 3402–3422, https://doi.org/10.1093/restud/rdae001
- Share Icon Share
Abstract
This article studies the incentives for interim voluntary disclosure of verifiable information in probabilistic all-pay contests with two-sided incomplete information. Private information may concern marginal cost, valuations, and ability. Our main result says that, if the contest is uniformly asymmetric, then full revelation is the unique perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcome. This is so because the weakest type of the underdog reveals her type in an attempt to moderate the favourite, while the strongest type of the favourite tries to discourage the underdog—so that the contest unravels. This strong-form disclosure principle is robust with respect to correlation, partitional evidence, randomized disclosures, sequential moves, and continuous type spaces. Moreover, the assumption of uniform asymmetry is not needed when incomplete information is one-sided. However, the principle may break down when type distributions are too similar, contestants possess commitment power, or information is unverifiable. In fact, cheap talk will always be ignored, even if mediated by a trustworthy third party.
1 INTRODUCTION
On February 24, 2014, the concentration of Russian troops along the entire Ukrainian–Russian border became overwhelming. In a major demonstration of force and simultaneous preparation for invasion, the Kremlin had decided to concentrate in the Kyiv, Kharkiv, and Donetsk directions 38,000 men, 761 armed tanks, 2,200 armoured vehicles, 720 artillery systems and multiple rocket launchers, as well as up to 40 attack helicopters, 90 combat support helicopters, and 90 attack aircraft. In the Black Sea, 80 Russian warships were on combat duty. On that same day, the Russian Black Sea Fleet Commander had a conversation with the Ukraine Naval Forces Commander, advocating complete surrender and handing over of the Crimea. And indeed, Ukrainian resistance quickly ebbed away in the days to follow.1
In this article, we extend the standard model of a probabilistic contest (Rosen, 1986; Dixit, 1987) by allowing for pre-play communication of verifiable information (Okuno-Fujiwara et al., 1990; van Zandt and Vives, 2007; Hagenbach et al., 2014). Contestants are assumed to possess private information regarding parameters indicative of their strength in the competition. In general, these parameters may concern marginal cost, valuations, and ability. Then, at the interim stage, i.e. after having observed her type but prior to the contest, each player may choose to disclose that information to her opponent. In this type of framework, we evaluate the incentives of players to voluntarily disclose their private information. Moreover, we characterize the perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcome of the resulting two-stage game. The focus of the analysis lies on contests that are uniformly asymmetric in the sense that one of the contestants is, subject to activity, interim always strictly more likely to win than the other.2 To be on safe ground, we offer a condition on the primitives of the model that guarantees that the contest is uniformly asymmetric. While restrictive, that condition is consistent with heterogeneity in both valuations (e.g. Amann and Leininger, 1996; Maskin and Riley, 2000) and ability (e.g. O’Keeffe et al., 1984; Meyer, 1992; Franke et al., 2014). But, we will also delineate the scope of the strong-form disclosure principle in more general contests.
Our main result says that, provided that the contest is uniformly asymmetric, the only outcome of the revelation game consistent with the assumption of perfect Bayesian rationality is the one in which all the privately held information is unfolded prior to the contest. Thus, we find general conditions under which the disclosure principle in the strong form applies to a standard contest setting. This may be of interest because effort choices in probabilistic contests are neither strategic substitutes nor strategic complements, and consequently contests do not satisfy the usual conditions sufficient for the strong-form disclosure principle.3
There is a simple intuition for why contestants find it optimal to release hard evidence in a uniformly asymmetric contest. In view of the high effort expected from a favourite that is left to speculate about the underdog’s strength, the weakest type of the underdog has a strict incentive to self-disclose, so as to moderate the favourite. But then, the set of types deemed possible by the favourite in the absence of any evidence becomes smaller. Therefore, the weakest of the remaining types of the underdog will choose to disclose her private information as well. And so on. Thus, there is an unravelling on the underdog’s side. But in the resulting contest with one-sided incomplete information, the unravelling continues on the side of the favourite. Indeed, the respective strongest type of the favourite has a strict incentive to self-disclose, so as to discourage the underdog. Ultimately, full revelation of all private information isinevitable.4
This intuition is robust in a number of dimensions. First, the strong-form disclosure principle continues to be valid generically when types are correlated. The role of the weakest type of the underdog is then taken on by the lowest-bidding type in the contest. Second, the main result extends to partitional information releases and randomized signals. Next, we show that the principle applies likewise if disclosure decisions are taken in a sequential fashion, i.e. with either the favourite or the underdog moving first. Further, we allow for continuous type spaces. Finally, we show that, in the case of one-sided private information, the assumption of uniform asymmetry may be dropped without losing the conclusion. In that case, there is always one extremal type that strictly prefers to self-disclose. The order of the unravelling may then switch hence and forth, in a “bang-bang” fashion, between the remaining weak and strong types of the informed side.
The strong-form disclosure principle is, however, not universally valid. First, if a contest with two-sided incomplete information is not uniformly asymmetric, then it may happen that no type has an incentive to self-disclose. The reason is that contestants face countervailing incentives. While a relatively efficient type benefits from demoralizing an inefficient opponent, she simultaneously suffers from revealing her information to an opponent of comparable strength. Since the situation may be similar for a relatively inefficient type, full concealment can be an equilibrium. Second, full revelation is not a necessity if contestants possess commitment power. For example, Bayesian persuasion need not lead to full revelation even if the contest would otherwise unravel. Finally, the disclosure principle crucially depends on the assumption that private information is verifiable. In fact, as we show, unverifiable messages are necessarily ignored in any probabilistic contest, even in the presence of a trustworthymediator.
Regarding welfare, we point out that unrestricted communication in probabilistic contests may lead to a Pareto-inferior outcome for the contestants. Still, depending on the objective of the contest organizer, full revelation may be socially desirable and, in particular, the result of optimal information design.
Further illustrations. Our introductory example was taken from the area of military conflict and war. The following examples may serve as additional illustrations.
- •
Public enforcement in the U.S. is characterized by a large disparity between the power of the state prosecutor and the typical criminal defendant (Lynch, 1998). Both parties possess verifiable information (Bibas, 2004). Even when plea bargaining is banned, it is common for the defendant to plead guilty to a subset of the charges (Weninger, 1987). Conversely, the prosecutor releases evidence to induce the defendant to confess (Petegorsky, 2012). As a result, only a small fraction of criminal cases go to trial.
- •
Implicit or explicit threats are used to intimidate whistleblowers (Chassang and Padró I Miquel, 2019) and witnesses (Maynard, 1994).
- •
In R&D and patent races, the frontrunner reveals research results and funding successes to discourage competitors (Baker and Mezzetti, 2005). But also laggards announce new products to influence the outcome of competition in their interest (Robertson et al., 1995).
- •
In social conflict, the use of phenotype “indices” resolves or avoids physical conflicts in dyadic relationships (Hand, 1986). For conflicts arising within dominance or subordination relationships, signals tend to be placating or acquiescent. Within egalitarian or unresolved relationships, however, there are either no signals or signals indicate relative desire for an item on a case-by-case basis.
Related literature. The economics literature has a long tradition of studying incentives for the voluntary disclosure of private information. In seminal contributions, Grossman (1981) and Milgrom (1981) pointed out that, as a consequence of unravelling, sellers will it find hard to withhold verifiable information about the quality of their products. The underlying disclosure principle has since shaped the theoretical discussion about the pros and cons of disclosure regulation, as is reflected by a very large body of literature.5
Probabilistic contests of incomplete information have been studied for some time. Rosen (1986, fn. 7) still complained that “few analytical results” were available. Early papers include Linster (1993) and Baik and Shogren (1995). The general framework with one-sided and two-sided private valuations is due to Hurley and Shogren (1998a, 1998b). Wärneryd (2003) observed that the uninformed player in a common-value setting is more likely to win than the informed player. Malueg and Yates (2004) analysed a symmetric two-player Tullock contest with two equally likely and possibly correlated types. Schoonbeek and Winkel (2006) noted that individual types may remain inactive. General results on the existence and uniqueness of Bayesian equilibrium have been obtained by Ewerhart (2014), Einy et al. (2015), and Ewerhart and Quartieri (2020).
The present paper falls into the recent and quickly expanding literature concerned with the disclosure of verifiable information in contests.6 That literature has tended to focus on either ex ante voluntary disclosure, optimal disclosure policies, or interim voluntary disclosure.7 Ex ante voluntary disclosure in probabilistic contests has been studied by Denter et al. (2014), in particular. Assuming a probabilistic contest technology with one-sided incomplete information, they showed that a “laissez-faire” policy regarding the informed player’s ex ante disclosure decision leads to lower expected lobbying expenditures than a policy of mandatory disclosure.8 The second topic, optimal disclosure policies in contests, has recently seen a strong development. In particular, effort-maximizing disclosure policies have been characterized by Zhang and Zhou (2016) and Serena (2022) for probabilistic technologies, and by Fu et al. (2014), Chen et al. (2017), and Lu et al. (2018) for deterministic technologies.9
The present analysis is mainly concerned, however, with the third topic, i.e. the interim voluntary disclosure in contests. As far as we know, there is only one paper that has dealt with this issue on a comparable level of generality.10 Specifically, Kovenock et al. (2015) showed that, regardless of whether valuations are private or common, the interim information sharing game followed by an all-pay auction admits a perfect Bayesian equilibrium in which no player ever shares her private information. Instead of the all-pay auction, however, we consider a probabilistic contest. Overall, the review of the literature suggests that the specific research question pursued in the present paper, viz. the analysis of incentives for the interim voluntary disclosure of hard evidence in contests with probabilistic technologies and two-sided incomplete information, has not been addressed in prior work.11
The remainder of this article is structured as follows. Section 2 introduces the set-up. The main result is stated in Section 3. Section 4 outlines the proof. Section 5 offers extensions, while Section 6 discusses limits to the scope of the disclosure principle. Section 7 concerns efficiency. Section 8 concludes. A Supplementary Appendix contains technical proofs and other material omitted from the body of the article.
2 SET-UP
Considered is an interaction over two stages, referred to as revelation stage and contest stage, respectively. The modelling follows the literature on pre-play communication (Okuno-Fujiwara et al., 1990; van Zandt and Vives, 2007; Hagenbach et al., 2014). We will start with the contest stage and continue backwards with the revelation stage.
2.1 The contest stage
Two players (or teams)
where
where
For convenience, we will assume that each player i’s type is independently and discretely distributed—and that it concerns the marginal cost parameter
The symbol
A bid schedule for player
The contest stage admits a unique Bayesian Nash equilibrium.14
Special notation will be used in the cases of complete and one-sided incomplete information. If
2.2 The revelation stage
At a stage preceding the contest, players simultaneously and independently decide whether to disclose their respective type or not. Initially, it will be assumed that private information cannot be misrepresented. Further, we assume that the decision to self-disclose does not lead to any direct costs.15
In response to the observation of verifiable information, prior beliefs are updated according to Bayes’ rule whenever possible. One notes that off-equilibrium beliefs may arise, but only in the distinct case where a player chooses to conceal her private information even though the equilibrium strategy entails self-disclosure by all types of that player.16
In any case, the contest stage begins with a well-defined posterior belief
3 THE UNRAVELLING THEOREM
This section is central to our analysis. We start by defining what we call uniformly asymmetric contests. We then provide a sufficient condition for a contest to be uniformly asymmetric. Finally, we present the main result of this article.
3.1 Uniformly asymmetric contests
The focus of our analysis lies on probabilistic contests with two-sided incomplete information that satisfy the following definition.
A probabilistic contest of incomplete information is uniformly asymmetric if, for any pair of posterior beliefs
- (i)
all types
supp are active at the contest stage; and - (ii)if all types
supp are active as well, then(4)
Here, as usual, supp
If the contest is of complete information (i.e. if
3.2 A sufficient condition
In this section, we derive a condition on the primitives of the model that is sufficient for a contest to be uniformly asymmetric. While the assumption is strong, it will allow us to capture a very clear and robust intuition.
Assumption 1 is a joint restriction on four parameters, each of which admits an intuitive interpretation.21 First,
When positive, the threshold value
In the limit case of complete information and symmetric costs (i.e.
Clearly, with Assumption 1 in place, Player 1 is in a quite strong position relative to Player 2. And indeed, as the following result shows, the assumption implies that the contest is uniformly asymmetric.
(Sufficient condition)
Any incomplete-information contest that satisfies Assumption 1 is uniformly asymmetric.
3.3 Main result
We will use the term full revelation to characterize the perfect Bayesian equilibrium, or the perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcome, in which all private information is revealed. The main result of the present paper is the following.
(Strong-form disclosure principle)
In any uniformly asymmetric contest with pre-play communication of verifiable information, full revelation is the unique perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcome.
Theorem 1 states that the strong-form disclosure principle applies to any uniformly asymmetric contest.
It is not hard to see that self-disclosure by all types is an equilibrium. Indeed, it suffices to specify off-equilibrium beliefs so that a player that surprises her opponent by concealing her private information is understood to be the worst-case type, i.e. the type that no other type would like to masquerade as.24 In our setting, the worst-case types are the most efficient underdog and the least efficient favourite, respectively. Provided that off-equilibrium beliefs are specified in that sceptical way (Milgrom, 2008), it is optimal for all types to stick to self-disclosure.
Note that uniqueness is claimed for the equilibrium outcome only. To reveal all private information, it suffices that, for each player, all types except one disclose their private information. However, that multiplicity of perfect Bayesian equilibria is trivial since it does not affect the outcome of the contest.
For auctions with interdependent valuations (Benoît and Dubra, 2006; Tan, 2016), incentives to reveal a private signal are typically strongest at the bottom of the signal support of the common-value component. For instance, a bidder in an auction that learns that a supposedly original painting is not authentic has an incentive to share that information with the other bidders. Thus, as in the present analysis, voluntary disclosure is likely to occur whenever it reduces the opponent’s incentives for bidding too aggressively.25
4 UNDERSTANDING THE UNRAVELLING RESULT
In this section, we explain the mechanics underlying Theorem 1, dealing first with the underdog’s and, subsequently, with the favourite’s disclosure decision. The section ends with a discussion.
4.1 Benefits of self-disclosure for the underdog
We focus on the weakest type of the underdog,
(Self-disclosure by the weakest type of the underdog)
Suppose that, in a uniformly asymmetric contest, the underdog has at least two possible type realizations. Then, a unilateral disclosure by the weakest type of the underdog,
- (i)
induces
to strictly raise her effort, i.e. ; - (ii)
strictly raises
’s interim probability of winning, i.e. (even against any given type of Player 1); and - (iii)
strictly raises
’s expected payoff, i.e. .
Thus, after revealing her relative weakness, the weakest type of the underdog behaves as if gaining confidence. She bids more aggressively and wins with a strictly higher probability. Moreover, the self-disclosure is always strictly beneficial for her.26
The proof of Proposition 1 is based on the monotonicity properties of best response mappings in uniformly asymmetric contests. Let
The fact that

The weakest type of the underdog raises her bid after self-disclosure
Self-disclosure raises also the probability of winning for
In a final step, it is shown that the weakest type of the underdog has a strict incentive to self-disclose. The proof we managed to come up with exploits type
respectively. Given parts (i) and (ii) of Proposition 1, this suffices to prove the claim.
4.2 Benefits of self-disclosure for the favourite
Repeated application of Proposition 1 shows that the underdog’s side of the contest equilibrium unravels. Let
If type
(Self-disclosure by the strongest type of the favourite)
Suppose that, in a uniformly asymmetric contest, the type of the underdog is public information, while the favourite has at least two possible type realizations. Then, a unilateral disclosure by the strongest type of the favourite,
- (i)
induces the underdog to strictly lower her effort, i.e.
; - (ii)
allows
to strictly lower her effort, i.e. ; - (iii)
strictly raises
’s probability of winning, i.e. ; and - (iv)
strictly raises
’s expected payoff, i.e. .
Thus, if the type of the underdog is public, then the self-revelation by the strongest type of the favourite discourages the underdog. As a result, the strongest type of the favourite exerts a lower effort, but still wins with higher probability. While the proof of Proposition 2 employs the same methods that have been used before, the argument is, of course, much simpler in this case.30
An iterated application of Proposition 2 implies that also the favourite’s side unravels. Thus, in a uniformly asymmetric contest, full revelation is the only outcome consistent with the assumption of perfect Bayesian rationality. But, as already discussed, self-disclosure by all types of both players is indeed a perfect Bayesian equilibrium, which yields the conclusion of Theorem 1.
4.3 Discussion: dominance and defiance
As mentioned in Section 1, the reason why the proof of Theorem 1 is not as straightforward as one might expect is that, in general, a unilateral disclosure of some type may cause some types of the opponent to raise their bids. For intuition, note that there are two countervailing effects. On the one hand, following the self-disclosure by
5 EXTENSIONS
In this section, we discuss a variety of extensions of Theorem 1. To keep the exposition as non-technical as possible, most of the formal results and derivations underlying the discussion have been moved to the Supplementary Appendix.
5.1 Correlated types
By continuity, Theorem 1 is robust with respect to the introduction of any sufficiently small correlation between contestants’ types. But suppose that correlation is more substantial. Then, negative correlation renders stronger types of the underdog more optimistic, and the proof of the crucial Proposition 1 goes through as before. Positive or general correlation, however, may render stronger types of the underdog more pessimistic. In that case, some type of the underdog other than
5.2 Partitional disclosures
In the main analysis, we assumed that disclosure is “all-or-nothing”. However, in many cases, contestants may have more control over the information they choose to disclose than what has been assumed so far. In a model with pre-play partitional disclosure of the state space, Hagenbach et al. (2014) identified necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of a fully revealing sequential equilibrium with “extremal” off-equilibrium beliefs that implements a given Nash equilibrium action profile on and off the equilibrium path. Our main result continues to hold if contestants’ message correspondences each contain an evidence base. For example, the disclosure decision might alternatively establish an upper (lower) bound for the favourite’s (the underdog’s) cost parameter. It should be immediate to see that the unravelling argument underlying Theorem 1 extends along these lines to the more general framework of partitional disclosures.32
5.3 Randomized revelations
Allowing for randomized revelations does not change the conclusion of Theorem 1. Indeed, a type’s randomized decision regarding self-disclosure cannot be more profitable than a pure decision. Therefore, full revelation remains an equilibrium outcome. But, we also note that the unravelling is inevitable when players may use randomized revelations because the self-disclosure of the relevant extremal type remains strictly optimal regardless of conditional type distributions.
5.4 Sequential moves
Theorem 1 continues to hold when the revelation stage is replaced by a sequential-move game in which the disclosure decision is made first by the favourite and then, after observation, by the underdog. Intuitively, in any equilibrium in which two or more types of the favourite pool with positive probability in the same information set, the underdog’s type will be revealed by Proposition 1. Anticipating this, the strongest type of the favourite strictly prefers to self-disclose instead of pooling with any weaker type. But also in the case where the underdog moves first, we show in the Supplementary Appendix that full revelation remains the unique perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcome in the lottery contest.33
5.5 One-sided incomplete information
If just one of the contestants is privately informed, then the assumption of uniform asymmetry is typically not needed to obtain full revelation as the unique equilibrium outcome.
(One-sided incomplete information)
Consider a probabilistic contest with one-sided incomplete information and generic types. Then, the conclusion of Theorem 1 continues to hold true.
While the result holds generally, the intuition for the proof is most transparent in the special case of the Tullock contest. Two observations are important, both of which are derived from the first-order conditions. First, in equilibrium, the expenses of the uninformed contestant,
5.6 Continuous type distributions
Benoît and Dubra (2006) have derived a general unravelling result for auctions and other Bayesian games that allows for multiple players and metric type spaces. That result may be used to extend Theorem 1 to the case of continuous type distributions.35 Suppose that for
5.7 Private information about valuations and ability
We assumed above that private information concerns marginal cost only. To accommodate more general forms of uncertainty, suppose that player i’s private information is instead summarized in the vector
Assuming that private information is exclusively about marginal cost is without loss of generality if at least one of the two following conditions is satisfied.
- (i)
and are public information; - (ii)
for some .
Part (i) captures the (well-known) equivalence between uncertainty about marginal cost and valuations. Part (ii) says that, in the case of the Tullock contest, our analysis covers multi-dimensional uncertainty without restriction. This is an important point because, as noted by a referee, in many real-world contests, verifiable evidence does not concern contestants’ preferences but rather the likelihood to win.
6 LIMITS OF THE SCOPE OF THE DISCLOSURE PRINCIPLE
The strong-form disclosure principle is not universally valid in probabilistic contests. As will be shown in this section, the principle may break down if the contest is not uniformly asymmetric or if contestants have commitment power. Moreover, the principle never holds in probabilistic contests if information is unverifiable.
6.1 Contests that are not uniformly asymmetric
The conclusion of Theorem 1 may fail if the contest is not uniformly asymmetric. In line with the intuition provided in Section 1, we outline below a numerical example of a probabilistic contest that is not uniformly asymmetric and in which the perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcome need not be fully revealing. In view of Theorem 2, any counterexample of this sort necessarily features two-sided asymmetric information.
(Countervailing incentives)

Full concealment may be an equilibrium in a contest that is not uniformly asymmetric
Thus, the assumption of uniform asymmetry cannot be easily dropped without losing the strong-form disclosure principle in probabilistic contests with two-sided incomplete information.36
6.2 Commitment power and Bayesian persuasion
Self-disclosure of one type need not be in the interest of other types. If, for example, the strongest type of the favourite reveals her private information in a uniformly asymmetric contest, then the competition for the remaining types of the favourite will typically become tougher. Thus, a contestant may be worse off as a result of voluntary disclosure. Following Kamenica and Gentzkow (2011), one may assume that each contestant possesses commitment power that allows her to follow a communication strategy optimized from an ex ante perspective. As we show in the Supplementary Appendix, however, a contestant’s optimal Bayesian persuasion strategy may take different forms, including not only full concealment but also full disclosure (in which case it may be redundant), or even the use of randomized signals. For example, given precommitment to a signal, an efficient type of the underdog may occasionally pool with an inefficient type. Conversely, a contestant might seek ways to avoid receiving messages by shutting down communication channels.
6.3 Cheap talk
In Crawford and Sobel’s (1982) model of cheap talk,37 pre-play messages released at the interim stage are assumed to be unverifiable.38 More generally, in a communication equilibrium (Myerson, 1982), each player reports private information to a mediator in an unverifiable way. Having received the reports, the mediator follows her precommitted instructions and releases a recommendation to each of the players via a bilateral communication channel. Then, based on the recommendation and her type, each player chooses a strategy. For example, the mediator may be precommitted to relay the reports unchanged to the respective other party, which would correspond to cheap talk. In the case of the two-player all-pay auction, Pavlov (2013) identified assumptions under which every communication equilibrium is interim payoff equivalent to the Bayesian equilibrium. The following result is an analogous observation for probabilistic contests.
(Babbling)
In any communication equilibrium of a probabilistic contest, all recommendations will be ignored.
Thus, cheap talk in probabilistic contests is necessarily ineffective, even if intermediated by a trustworthy third party. If the contest were a zero-sum game, then this observation would be obvious. Indeed, as noted by Farrell (1985), a player should be very suspicious to make use of information provided by another player with completely opposite preferences. However, probabilistic contests are not zero-sum, but only strategically equivalent to a zero-sum game (Moulin and Vial, 1978). To see this, one notes that adding the expenses of a player to the other player’s payoff function does not change marginal incentives. Therefore, in principle, there might be communication strategies mutually beneficial for both players to select Pareto superior outcomes. However, the Bayesian equilibrium is unique by Lemma 1, which turns out to imply that unverifiable communication is ineffective.39
7 EFFICIENCY
What are the welfare implications of information disclosure in probabilistic contests? In the Supplementary Appendix, we show with the help of an example that, in the absence of commitment power on the part of the contestants, the unravelling may lead into a “disclosure trap”. By this, we mean an outcome in which the ex ante expected payoff for both contestants is strictly lower than under mandatory concealment. Thus, in contrast to the more common situation in which the receiver in a persuasion game, such as an employer, a consumer, or a health insurer, tends to benefit from the unravelling, this need not be the case in a contest. However, many real-world contests have informational and allocational externalities on third parties. It may, therefore, be short-sighted to limit the welfare discussion solely to the expected payoffs of the contestants. For example, if contests are organized to maximize total expected expenses, and if information disclosures lower expected payoffs by tightening the competition, then that may well be desirable from the organizer’s point of view.40
8 CONCLUSION
In this article, we have identified general and robust conditions under which a probabilistic contest with verifiable pre-play communication admits full disclosure as the unique perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcome. Given that the usual assumptions for the uniqueness of the fully revealing equilibrium outcome (Milgrom, 1981; Okuno-Fujiwara et al., 1990; Seidmann and Winter, 1997; van Zandt and Vives, 2007) fail to hold for contests, our results mean an extension of existing theory. In particular, the strong-form disclosure principle is more general than previously perceived. In addition, the analysis has formalized several intuitive concepts for which, to our knowledge, a flexible and all-encompassing framework in the realm of contest theory has been lacking so far. In sum, the analysis sheds further light on the incentives for communication of both verifiable and unverifiable information in competitive situations. This is not only desirable from the perspective of economic theory but also holds the potential of facilitating both the mitigation of harmful conflict and the efficient design of real-world contests.41
Acknowledgments
Valuable comments by the Editor (Christian Hellwig) and two anonymous referees helped us to improve the article. This work has further benefited from conversations with David Austen-Smith, Mikhail Drugov, Jörg Franke, Dan Kovenock, Wolfgang Leininger, Jingfeng Lu, Meg Mayer, Alessandro Pavan, Dmitry Ryvkin, Tarun Sabarwal, Aner Sela, Curtis Taylor, Karl Wärneryd, Juuso Välimäki, Xavier Vives, and Junjie Zhou. The article has been presented at the Oligo Workshop in Piraeus, at PET in Hue, Vietnam, at the SAET conference in Taipei, as well as to seminar audiences in Bath, Zurich, and at UCLA.
Supplementary Data
Supplementary data are available at Review of Economic Studies online.
References
Footnotes
This example has been inspired by the discussion in Lenton (2022) and a recently declassified protocol of the National Security and Defense Council of Ukraine (2016, pp. 10–11).
The definition of uniform asymmetry will be given in Section 3.
Instead, given that the best-response function of the favourite is strictly increasing, while the best-response function of the underdog is strictly declining, asymmetric contests classify, at least under suitable domain restrictions, as games of strategic heterogeneity (Monaco and Sabarwal, 2016; Barthel and Hoffmann, 2019).
This simple intuition does not translate into an equally simple proof, however. Indeed, as will be explained, disclosures may lead to dominant and defiant reactions, i.e. cause some types of the opponent, be it favourite or underdog, to raise their bids.
In addition to the contributions already mentioned, see Verrecchia (1983), Dye (1985), Shin (1994), Seidmann and Winter (1997), Benoît and Dubra (2006), and Giovannoni and Seidmann (2007), for instance. Milgrom (2008) or Dranove and Jin (2010) offer surveys.
Another form of pre-play communication, not considered in the present paper, is the costly signalling of unverifiable information. See, e.g. Katsenos (2010), Slantchev (2010), Fu et al. (2013), Heijnen and Schoonbeek (2017), and Yildirim (2017).
Numerous additional research questions, related to learning, feedback, and motivation, for example, arise in the analysis of dynamic contests of incomplete information. Such research questions have been dealt with in papers by Clark (1997), Yildirim (2005), Krähmer (2007), Münster (2009), Zhang and Wang (2009), Aoyagi (2010), Ederer (2010), and Goltsman and Mukherjee (2011), for instance.
Relatedly, Wu and Zheng (2017) considered a symmetric two-player lottery contest with two equally likely, independently drawn types for each player. In that framework, they showed that ex ante disclosure decisions lead to information sharing if and only if the two possible type realizations are sufficiently close to each other.
Dubey (2013) studied a set-up with two-sided incomplete information about a binary type distribution and two effort levels. Assuming that abilities are sufficiently dispersed, he showed that incomplete (complete) information engenders more effort if the prize is high (low). Einy et al. (2017) studied the value of public information in Tullock contests with non-linear costs. Optimal disclosure policies have been analysed also in models of population uncertainty. See Münster (2006), Myerson and Wärneryd (2006), Lim and Matros (2009), Fu et al. (2011), Feng and Lu (2016), and Fu et al. (2016), among others.
Epstein and Mealem (2013) considered a lottery contest with one-sided incomplete information and characterized the perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcome in the case of two possible type realizations. While they considered also an extension to more than two types, they did not characterize the perfect Bayesian equilibrium in that case.
In general, signals may have multiple audiences. For example, in Board’s (2009) model, a direct benefit from disclosure on the consumer side is balanced by the firm against the cost of tighter competition. The present paper, however, focuses on the informational exchange between contestants in the absence of informational externalities.
Relaxing the assumption of a concave production function would take us away from the focus of this article. In contrast, the extension to player-specific production functions is easily accomplished yet does not yield additional insights.
To see this, suppose that one player bids zero with probability one. Then, any sufficiently small positive bid is a better response than the zero bid, but any positive bid is suboptimal. Hence, there is no best response.
Given strict concavity of payoff functions, Lemma 1 extends to randomized strategies, i.e. any mixed strategy equilibrium at the contest stage is degenerate and consequently in pure strategies.
Introducing costs for disclosing information would not change our conclusions, provided those are not too large compared to the benefits of self-disclosure identified below.
A formal account of belief updating is provided in the Supplementary Appendix.
This is obvious for any
Type-dependent signal spaces and continuous strategy sets preclude a direct reference to the standard definition of a perfect Bayesian equilibrium in a multi-stage game with observable actions (Fudenberg and Tirole, 1991, p. 331). Otherwise, however, the definition is standard.
To understand why the activity of all types of Player 2 is presupposed in property (ii) of the definition, it should be noted that an inactive type of Player 2 may, in general, dilute the marginal incentives of a strong Player 1 so much that the probability ranking (4) could easily break down.
The curvature
Assumption 1 does not impose any activity conditions. In general, corner solutions are known to be consistent with the existence of a perfect Bayesian equilibrium with no revelation of private information (Okuno-Fujiwara et al., 1990, Ex. 4). In our framework, however, that problem does not occur.
Indeed, in this case,
This useful terminology is borrowed from Seidmann and Winter (1997) and Hagenbach et al. (2014).
We conjecture that allowing for a common-value signal in the present set-up would lead to similar conclusions as the literature on unravelling in auctions has identified.
The conclusions of Proposition 1 are immediate for any type of the underdog that is inactive in
Thus, given bid schedules
These properties, which were documented by Dixit (1987) in the case of complete information, are verified in the Supplementary Appendix. The comparative statics of complete-information contests has been studied by Jensen (2016) and Gama and Rietzke (2017), in particular.
Part (ii) of Proposition 2 holds also in the case of two-sided incomplete information. Beyond that observation, however, the analogy to Proposition 1 is incomplete. In fact, we conjecture that parts (iii) and (iv) of Proposition 2 do not generalize to a setting with two-sided incomplete information. Below, we will derive a variant of Proposition 2 that holds even if the contest is not uniformly asymmetric.
Of course, we acknowledge the crucial role played by emotions in contests (e.g. Kräkel, 2008). Illustrations of dominant and defiant behaviour can be found in Caygill (2013).
As we further show in the Supplementary Appendix, hard evidence may also be released if it is only an imperfect signal about the type, provided that the signal is stochastically monotone.
In that case, the crucial payoff comparison is derived using a second-moment refinement of Jensen’s inequality that is stated and proved in the Supplementary Appendix as well.
However, similar to the case of correlated types, a genericity assumption is needed here because different types of the informed player may choose the same bid.
Probabilistic contests with continuous type distributions have been considered, in particular, by Fey (2008), Ryvkin (2010), Wasser (2013a, 2013b), Ewerhart (2014), and Prokopovych and Yannelis (2023).
While the bid intervals are overlapping in Example 1, it is likewise feasible to construct counterexamples with either nested or symmetric bid intervals. See the Supplementary Appendix.
We are indebted to the Editor for suggesting this interesting extension.
Fey et al. (2007) studied cheap talk in games with two-sided incomplete information and identified a role for complementarity versus substitutability. While interesting, their results do not resolve our research question.
In his analysis of sender–receiver games with two-sided incomplete information, Seidmann (1990, Ex. 1) showed that, even if all types of the sender share the same preferences over pure effort choices by the receiver, the sender types’ preferences regarding lotteries over efforts may differ. Even though our model has precisely this property, Theorem 3 shows that equilibria in which receivers react to information are not feasible in probabilistic contests. And indeed, as we checked numerically, the Tullock contest does not satisfy Seidman’s condition for
As argued by Denter et al. (2014), Zhang and Zhou (2016), and Serena (2022), contest organizers may be able to influence contestants’ beliefs about each other by information design. In the Supplementary Appendix, we characterize optimal signals under a variety of policy objectives. In particular, we provide conditions under which the delegation to an informed contestant is optimal.
We did not answer all research questions regarding communication in contests. For example, it would be interesting to extend the analysis to contests with more than two players, to deal with common-value components and interdependent valuations, or to consider some form of dynamics. Tackling such questions seems both interesting and feasible.
Author notes
The editor in charge of this paper was Christian Hellwig.