Abstract

Mental imagery is a process by which thoughts become experienced with sensory characteristics. Yet, it is not clear why mental images appear diminished compared to veridical images, nor how mental images are phenomenologically distinct from hallucinations, another type of non-veridical sensory experience. Current evidence suggests that imagination and veridical perception share neural resources. If so, we argue that considering how neural representations of externally generated stimuli (i.e. sensory input) and internally generated stimuli (i.e. thoughts) might interfere with one another can sufficiently differentiate between veridical, imaginary, and hallucinatory perception. We here use a simple computational model of a serially connected, hierarchical network with bidirectional information flow to emulate the primate visual system. We show that modelling even first approximations of neural competition can more coherently explain imagery phenomenology than non-competitive models. Our simulations predict that, without competing sensory input, imagined stimuli should ubiquitously dominate hierarchical representations. However, with competition, imagination should dominate high-level representations but largely fail to outcompete sensory inputs at lower processing levels. To interpret our findings, we assume that low-level stimulus information (e.g. in early visual cortices) contributes most to the sensory aspects of perceptual experience, while high-level stimulus information (e.g. towards temporal regions) contributes most to its abstract aspects. Our findings therefore suggest that ongoing bottom-up inputs during waking life may prevent imagination from overriding veridical sensory experience. In contrast, internally generated stimuli may be hallucinated when sensory input is dampened or eradicated. Our approach can explain individual differences in imagery, along with aspects of daydreaming, hallucinations, and non-visual mental imagery.

Introduction

Mental images are internally generated thoughts which can be seen, heard, or in some way perceived with sensory qualities. Yet, how does the brain generate sensory experiences without a real sensory stimulus in the environment to perceive? One answer might be that mental imagery involves similar processes to those used during veridical perception, yet with an opposite direction of information flow. Instead of pooling together sensory information to extract abstract knowledge from a real stimulus, mental imagery may involve retrohierarchically reconstructing the sensory features of an imagined stimulus from abstract knowledge we already possess. In line with this idea, mental imagery seems to use the same neural machinery as that used during veridical perception (Kosslyn et al. 1993; Ishai 2010; Cichy et al. 2012; Dijkstra et al. 2017, 2018, 2019a; Xie et al. 2020), yet with neural activity during the early stages of veridical visual perception resembling neural activity during the later stages of visual mental imagery and vice versa (Dentico et al. 2014; Linde-Domingo et al. 2019; Breedlove et al. 2020; Dijkstra et al. 2020).

However, mental imagery is unlikely to be an exact reverse of feedforward processes in veridical perception given that individuals reliably report that their mental images are experienced with some form of reduced sensory quality (termed ‘vividness’) compared to real images (Galton 1880; Marks 1973). Some researchers have proposed that this difference follows from differences between feedforward and feedback processes, the latter of which are believed to be responsible for propagating mental images. For instance, information about mental image content tends to be most detectable in superficial and deep cortical layers, but not granular mid-layers, in contrast to information about environmental stimulus content, which can be detected across all cortical layers (Lawrence et al. 2018; Bergmann et al. 2019). Other accounts suggest that imagery could be propagated using weak feedback connections in the visual system, in contrast to feedforward connections that stereotypically drive, rather than modulate, action potentials (Koenig-Robert and Pearson 2021). However, feedback to early visual regions can drive action potentials depending on local neurochemistry (Aru et al. 2020). Furthermore, neither of these differences between feedforward and feedback processes can explain the unique experience of mental imagery without a framework specifying what it means for a mental image to be a quasi-sensory experience to begin with.

A more readily interpretable explanation is that mental images appear impoverished simply because the features of the images they depict are distorted relative to those of real images. That is, mental images might merely have less-precise image statistics (e.g. spatial frequency, location, and size) compared to real images, but are otherwise just as visible. Breedlove et al. (2020) provide an account that allows for this possibility, finding that representations of mental images in early visual cortices are deficient in detailed sensory information compared to real images. As hierarchical feedforward processes combine multiple pieces of sensory information (e.g. edges) to form fewer pieces of more abstract information (e.g. a shape), reconstructing sensory information using retrohierarchical feedback requires extrapolating from a relatively information-deficient source material. This process should distort imagined stimuli in predictable ways such that neural populations that represent mental images in early visual cortices have lower spatial frequency preferences, more foveal receptive fields, and larger receptive fields than when responding to real images (Breedlove et al. 2020).

Ultimately, many factors may distinguish between veridical and mental percepts given that the former are externally generated while the latter are internally generated. However, any complete explanation of the unique appearance of mental images must also account for how the quasi-sensory experience of mental imagery might be differentiated from other internally generated, yet unambiguously sensory experiences, such as which occur in hallucinations, many dreams, and eidetic imagery. Regardless of the image statistics of the internally generated content being depicted, these latter phenomena tend to involve a sensory experience of internally generated content that is entirely equivalent to the subjective experience of externally generated content (Chiu 1989; Ffytche et al. 1998) except that the content experienced is non-veridical and is not typically experienced as part of normal waking life. For the purposes of this article, we refer to the internally generated, unambiguously sensory experience common to each of hallucinations, dreams, and eidetic imagery as hallucinatory imagery, or a hallucination generally, regardless of whether such imagery is voluntary or involuntary, regardless of whether it is believed to be real or unreal, and regardless of where exactly within the visual field it is perceived to be located. Crucially, while mental imagery is quasi-sensory, seemingly seen yet unseen, hallucinatory imagery is definitively visible. This should require that non-veridical, internally generated sensory content or features replace veridical sensory content or features, overwriting them in a given region of the visual field. For instance, hallucinations may involve seeing a cat on this page instead of text, or seeing the text on this page as moving instead of still, or seeing anything at all during a dream instead of merely the back of our eyelids.

Here, we propose that imagined, veridical, and hallucinated percepts can be clearly distinguished by considering perception as a competitive, hierarchical process. While mental image generation can be modelled without competition from veridical perception (e.g. Breedlove et al. 2020), mental imagery almost never occurs in isolation. Instead, mental images are invariably generated while we are awake and receiving sensory input from the external world. If mental imagery and veridical perception share neural resources, then both processes should interact such that neural representations of imagined and real stimuli interfere or compete with one another.

Interactions between real and imagined stimuli have been previously demonstrated, lending support to the idea that perception may be a competitive process, although the exact outcome and nature of this interaction seems to vary. For instance, mental images can constructively interfere with real image content, depending on stimulus congruency (Dijkstra et al. 2022), and can induce priming or adaptation to veridical stimuli, depending on the individual (Keogh and Pearson 2017; Dijkstra et al. 2019b, 2021). Increasing environmental luminance can also impede the priming effects of mental imagery (Keogh and Pearson 2017), while real modality-specific distractors reduce the recall of modality-specific information (Wais et al. 2010; Vredeveldt et al. 2011), potentially reflecting competitive interference.

We sought to predict whether perceptual interference could account for the quasi-sensory, rather than hallucinatory, experience of mental imagery. Yet, any valid explanation of the quasi-sensory experience of mental imagery must first clearly specify what it means to have a quasi-sensory experience at all. Such an experience may be possible under a framework where perceptual experience itself is considered as a multifaceted phenomenon, composed of both sensory and abstract experiences at any given time. In vision, this entails having an experience of low-level features of an image, such as its hues and edge orientations, while also having an experience of high-level features of what the image actually depicts, such as recognizing that an image is depicting a duck. Usually, low- and high-level features of an image seem intertwined such that it is unintuitive to consider them as separate components of perceptual experience. Yet, these aspects become clearly separable when we consider bistable percepts (e.g. the rabbit–duck illusion), where the same low-level information can give rise to different abstract experiences. These abstract experiences feel perceptually distinct from one another even though the spatial pattern of light in our visual field, and our purely low-level visual experience of it, remains unchanged.

To anchor these experiences to physical processes, we assume that the sensory and abstract aspects of experience are dependent on neural systems encoding each respective type of information in the brain, such as those along the visual ventral stream. However, as neural representations of externally and internally generated stimuli are not explicitly sensory or abstract, but distributed on a spectrum, so too may perceptual experience itself be composed of a spectrum of sensory and abstract aspects. Given that internally generated perceptual experiences also seem to use similar neural resources to their externally generated counterparts, including in a feature-specific manner (Ffytche et al. 1998), then mental and hallucinatory imagery processes may also be experienced with a spectrum of abstract and sensory features. Under this framework, the quasi-sensory experience of mental imagery can be clearly conceptualized as the experience arising from the activation of high-level to mid-level, but not low-level, feature representations of internally generated content, regardless of the content itself. Hallucinatory imagery, in contrast, may invoke low-level sensory representations, with or without more abstract components, while veridical percepts should at least invoke low-level featural representations given their bottom-up entryway into the visual system.

Under these assumptions, we constructed a simple computational model of a serially connected network with bidirectional information flow as a first approximation to simulating the hierarchical interaction of internally and externally generated stimulus representations (Fig. 1). We used this model to evaluate the degree to which internally generated (i.e. imagined) stimulus representations are able to spread throughout a hierarchical system, with and without competition from externally generated stimuli. We demonstrate that competition from external sensory input could prevent internally generated content from ever recruiting the low-level neural infrastructure best suited to representing highly sensory, highly modal information. In doing so, we show that accounting for perceptual interference, even with preliminary models, can provide an arguably more coherent explanation for the unique phenomenology of mental imagery than approaches that consider mental imagery in isolation. We explore the perceptual implications of such predictions on the subjective experience of mental imagery, provide a neurochemically grounded hypothesis for variance in imagery across individuals and states, and delineate how perceptual interference may relate to hallucinations and mental imagery in non-visual modalities. Ultimately, we demonstrate that reconceptualizing mental imagery as an intrinsically competitive process can resolve major lingering questions in imagery research.

A hierarchical network modelling interference between externally and internally generated stimuli
Figure 1.

A hierarchical network modelling interference between externally and internally generated stimuli

Note. (a) A hierarchical network model of visual perception. Layer size indicates the relative dimensionality of the encoded representation. Information is pooled via feedforward processes (red, upward arrows) and extrapolated via feedback processes (blue, downward arrows). Lock icons indicate input layers with clamped representations during simulations where mental imagery is attempted during veridical perception. Clamped representations do not evolve with time. Note that a ‘thought’ here could be any internally generated representation. (b) Evolution rule for unclamped layers. Each value r in the representational matrix of each layer l evolves at each time point t according to a weighted average of the adjacent layers and the current layer at the previous time step with weights w. The ascending value array was convolved with an averaging kernel before being weighted to facilitate feedforward dimensionality reduction.

Materials and Methods

Computational model

Our goal was to assess the degree and extent to which internally generated stimuli are able to spread throughout a hierarchical system, with and without competition from externally generated stimuli. To do this, a dynamic, serially connected, five-layer computational network was constructed as a simple model of how stimulus information may flow bidirectionally in the hierarchical human visual system (Fig. 1). Each layer l encoded a representation r consisting of a square matrix of values. The number of units available to represent information (i.e. dimensionality) in each layer shrank in size from 256 × 256 matrix elements at the lowest layer (l = 0) to 208 × 208 elements at the higher layer (l = 4) by linearly decreasing the square root of the number of elements in each layer. This mimics feedforward dimensionality reduction in the visual system such that upper layers encode information that is more abstract than lower layers, analogous to neural structures towards the parietal and temporal lobes (Binder 2016). Each element in the matrix could vary in value along a single dimension, from 0 to 1, encoding the variation of an arbitrary stimulus feature. The lowest layer acted as an input layer for externally generated stimuli and never received feedback, analogous to the retina in visual perception.

The network allowed representations to propagate between layers and for bottom-up processes to interact with top-down processes. Hence, the representation r of each layer l was updated at each time step t according to a weighted average of the ascending representation rl−1 from the layer below, descending representation rl+1 from the layer above, and representation rl of the current layer, each at the previous time step t − 1 (Fig. 1b). We note that despite the simplicity of this approach, weighted averaging is approximately equivalent to the biologically plausible additive combination of neural inputs, followed by a decay of activity proportional to the strength of activation. However, unlike in real neurons, decay here occurs instantaneously. We allow for this simplification given that we simulate the perception of static images only and are therefore most concerned with the steady-state, rather than moment-to-moment, profile of the system.

Each layer was updated sequentially, first as part of a feedforward sweep, then as part of a feedback sweep, and then alternating with every subsequent iteration. Weightings wl−1, wl+1, and wl for the ascending, descending, and current representations, respectively, were each equal to one except where the effect of weighting ratios was explicitly investigated. However, if a layer acted as a constant source of information in the network (representing either an internally or externally generated stimulus), the values in its representational matrix were locked in place (clamped) by setting the weightings of ascending and/or descending inputs to that layer to zero. Given that the retina is always receiving visual input in an awake state, the lowest layer of the network was always clamped to some predetermined set of input values. Drawing from modelling by Breedlove et al. (2020), the highest layer in the network was also clamped to a fixed set of input values to simulate an internally generated stimulus (i.e. a thought) during mental imagery.

To simulate feedforward information pooling in the visual ventral stream, ascending representations were combined using a 13 × 13 square convolutional kernel such that each element of the layer above received the average of inputs from multiple elements from the layer below. Hence, from l = 0 to l = 4, the receptive field size of each element in each representation increased while layer dimensionality decreased. Because forming a mental image of an object first requires at some point seeing the object or its constituent parts, internally generated stimulus representations were formed from externally generated (e.g. retinal) stimulus inputs first processed through a single complete feedforward sweep from the lowest to the highest layer.

To assess the degree to which mental imagery was able to compete with veridical sensory input, we allowed the network to evolve under three main sets of initial conditions: veridical perception without imagination, imagination without veridical perception, and imagination during veridical perception. In the first case, to simulate a scenario where externally generated visual input is present without competition, only the bottom layer was clamped to a stimulus representation (veridical perception without imagination). Second, to simulate a scenario where an internally generated stimulus is present without competition, the top layer was clamped to an imagined stimulus representation (imagination without veridical perception). The ascending input from the base layer was downweighted to zero in this scenario to enforce a state of sensory disconnection. Third, in what we consider a more realistic mental imagery scenario, both the top and bottom layers were simultaneously clamped to different stimulus representations to simulate mental imagery occurring in the presence of competing sensory input (imagination during veridical perception). All intervening or non-input layers were initialized with white noise.

In each scenario, we measured the steady-state contribution of top-down representations relative to bottom-up representations at each layer. This was achieved by taking the average value of all elements in each layer for the case where the initial low-level or high-level input representations were set homogenously to zeros or ones, respectively (Fig. 2d–f). Each scenario was also replicated using images as inputs with each element of a representation corresponding to one pixel in the image such that the collective pixel values of each image equate to a simulated neural activity pattern (Fig. 2a–c). A 256 × 256 greyscale image of a camel was used for sensory input, and a 256 × 256 greyscale image of a hat was used for imagined input after conversion to a reduced dimensionality of 208 × 208 via feedforward pooling. Both were sourced from the BOSS image database (Brodeur et al. 2010). The similarity between layer activity patterns and the original imagined or veridical stimulus patterns can be quantified by calculating the absolute mean pixel difference between the images. We also separately explored how varying the ascending and descending weighting schemes affected competition between simulated imagined and veridical stimulus representations (Fig. 3). For each scenario in Fig. 3, all mid-layer feedforward or feedback weightings were ≤1 with the ratio specified in the figure for the duration of the simulation.

Veridical stimuli outcompete imagined stimuli at low-level sensory representations, but not high-level abstract representations
Figure 2.

Veridical stimuli outcompete imagined stimuli at low-level sensory representations, but not high-level abstract representations

Note. How simulated neural representations of an internally generated (imagined) hat and an externally generated (veridical) camel spread through a perceptual processing hierarchy with and without competition. (a–c) Simulated neural activity patterns, coded as image pixel values, evolving over 0, 2, and 20 alternating feedforward-feedback sweeps. Initial activity patterns are the same in each scenario and mimic thinking about a hat while receiving a retinal image of a camel. Lock icons indicate clamped representations that do not evolve. The crossed arrow indicates disconnected sensory input (wl=0 = 0). (a) All layers except the base layer are free to evolve, causing activity patterns to be dominated by the initial veridical input. (b) Mid-layers are free to evolve only. Sensory input is present but disconnected. All evolving activity patterns become dominated by the initial imagined input. (c) Mid-layers are free to evolve only, and sensory input is present and connected. Imagined content dominates upper layers, and veridical content dominates lower layers. The dashed, magenta line indicates the ‘representational equilibrium point’ where the internally and externally generated stimuli equally contribute to a layer. (d–f) One-dimensional simulations of each scenario in (a)–(c), illustrating how the character of each layer evolves over time. The dominance of the original externally generated stimulus representation at l = 0 can be obtained by subtracting the internally generated stimulus dominance from 100%.
Decreasing feedforward-to-feedback weighting ratio increases the sensory character of thoughts
Figure 3.

Decreasing feedforward-to-feedback weighting ratio increases the sensory character of thoughts

Note. Hierarchical competition between simulated neural representations of an internally generated (imagined) hat and an externally generated (veridical) camel modelled under different feedforward-to-feedback weighting ratios. Simulated neural activity patterns, coded as image pixel values, are depicted after 20 alternating feedforward-feedback sweeps. Initial activity patterns are the same in each scenario and mimic thinking about a hat while receiving a retinal image of a camel. Lock icons indicate clamped representations that do not evolve. The crossed arrow indicates disconnected sensory input (wl=0 = 0). Each dashed, magenta line indicates the ‘representational equilibrium point’ where the internally and externally generated stimuli contribute equally to a layer. (a–c) Globally varying the ratio of bottom-up (wl−1) and top-down (wl+1) weightings affects representational equilibrium and the extent to which thoughts should be experienced visually (e.g. weak, moderate, or high). (d) All unclamped layers converge towards the original internally generated stimulus representation once sensory input is disconnected, even if feedforward and feedback weights are equal.

Model interpretation

Our model can be interpreted as analogous to a simplified model of the human visual processing hierarchy, with a basal layer encoding externally generated retinal input and an apical layer housing more abstract internally generated stimulus representations encoded by neural structures towards the parietal and temporal lobes (Binder 2016). To interpret simulation outcomes phenomenologically, we considered that a single perceptual experience can contain a distribution of information, spanning from highly sensory (modal) in nature to highly abstract (amodal). We assume that each representational layer in the visual hierarchy contributes information to the construction of conscious perceptual experience if it receives both feedforward and feedback input. We also assume that the type of information provided by each layer aligns with the layer’s dimensionality such that high-dimensional representations contribute most to the sensory aspects of the experience, while low-dimensional representations contribute most to the non-sensory aspects of the experience. Hence, low-level representations would be most influential in determining the literal image content of a visual experience (e.g. the exact location, orientation, and contrast of high-spatial frequency edges), while high-level representations would contribute most to the abstract understanding of what is being thought about or observed (e.g. knowing whether the edges in a scene form a hat or a camel), with a spectrum of quasi-sensory or quasi-abstract features in between.

Crucially, this implies that a perceptual experience gains sensory or abstract properties depending on how well neural regions with the corresponding high- or low-dimensional structure, respectively, are recruited during that experience. Therefore, the further an internally generated stimulus representation is able to spread towards the primary visual cortex, for instance, the more it may be experienced with properties approaching that of an actual visual image (i.e. a true mental image) rather than something pondered without sensory qualia (i.e. a non-sensory thought). This approach can therefore maintain consistency with traditional accounts implicating the primary visual cortex in mental imagery (Kosslyn and Thompson 2003; Kosslyn 2005; Pearson and Kosslyn 2015; Pearson 2019).

Note that, as hallucinatory visual experience is possible without corresponding retinal activity, we consider the lowest level in the hierarchy purely as a non-conscious input layer to the rest of the network. We also note that while there is compelling evidence that some high-level representations are stored in a largely amodal form (e.g. Popham et al. 2021), they are not necessarily completely non-sensory. Late-stage object representations can still contain some degree of sensory information (e.g. DiCarlo and Cox 2007), albeit in a considerably more low-dimensional form relative to primary sensory areas. Our model only requires higher-level representations to be less sensory than low-level representations rather than completely non-sensory.

Results

Perception without competition

Two scenarios were simulated where competition was not present: veridical perception without imagination and imagination without veridical perception. Initiation of veridical perception was simulated by allowing the lowest representational layer to have a non-zero contribution to the layer above. Imagination was simulated by preventing the highest layer from being affected by feedforward inputs below such that it provided a constant source of top-down information to the system. In both cases, only one fixed source of perceptual information was present within the network, either an externally or internally generated stimulus representation. An example simulation is shown in Fig. 2 using an image of a camel as the externally generated veridical stimulus input (i.e. retinal activity pattern) and a compressed image of a hat as the internally generated imagined stimulus input (i.e. high-level neural activity pattern).

Without competition from imagination, all freely evolving (unclamped) layers in the network converged asymptotically to a representation dominated by the externally generated stimulus representation (Fig. 2a). Conversely, without competition from veridical perception, all unclamped layers converged to a representation dominated by the internally generated stimulus representation (Fig. 2b). As all unclamped representations are eventually dominated by the original externally or internally generated source stimulus, both scenarios each result in a state corresponding to having a visual experience of the same stimulus that is being simultaneously thought about abstractly. In the case of pure veridical perception, the system evolves to emulate a common perceptual experience: seeing an object while also knowing what it is. Yet, when the internally generated stimulus is uncontested, the sensory characteristics of the imagined stimulus should completely dominate visual experience, resulting in the perception of what was imagined and not what was present in the environment. Hence, pure imagination imitates hallucinating the object that one is thinking about.

Although, in both cases, layer l = 1 is entirely dominated by one stimulus, each state occurred through a distinct formation route. Note that the top-down, but not bottom-up, formation route resulted in substantial distortions at lower layers, reflecting the findings of Breedlove et al. (2020). Yet, these distortions only affect the content of the imagined stimulus, not the degree to which that stimulus is able to commandeer a hierarchical layer in this model.

Perception with competing imagined and veridical stimuli

Where two fixed sources of information are simultaneously present within the network, neither the imagined nor veridical stimulus can dominate every unclamped layer in the system (Fig. 2c). Instead, the network represents both stimuli simultaneously at the steady state. However, the further a given layer is from an externally or internally generated stimulus input layer, the smaller the contribution of the original veridical or imagined stimulus to the representation held by the given layer. This is shown in Fig. 2f for the case where feedforward and feedback weightings are equal (wl−1 = wl+1 = 1).

Consequently, when imagination occurs in the presence of bottom-up sensory input, the externally generated veridical stimulus dominates low-level representations, while the internally generated imagined stimulus dominates high-level representations. Such a system is therefore representing two distinct stimuli, yet at largely separate hierarchical levels. As lower levels are more suited for representing sensory information and higher levels for abstract, this state corresponds to a situation where an individual has a visual experience of their veridical environment despite simultaneously having relatively non-sensory thoughts about what they are imagining. Hence, the simulation suggests that external sensory input outcompetes imagination at the low-level regions that most contribute to the sensory aspects of perceptual experience.

Modelling variation in imagery quality (e.g. aphantasia and hyperphantasia) as a shift in representational equilibrium

This model can also be used to understand states where thoughts are experienced in a highly sensory way (hyperphantasia) or in a non-sensory or weakly sensory way (aphantasia; Fig. 3). When sensory input and imagination compete, our simulation showed that spanning along the perceptual hierarchy from bottom to top corresponded to transitioning from primarily representing a veridical stimulus to primarily representing an imagined stimulus. The exact point where the two stimuli are represented in equal proportion is here dubbed the ‘representational equilibrium point’ for the system. Representations contain more veridical stimulus character below this point and more imagined stimulus character above it.

The location of the representational equilibrium point can summarize how far an imagined representation can penetrate towards lower layers before it is outcompeted by the veridical stimulus, or how far a veridical stimulus representation can penetrate towards upper layers before it is outcompeted by the imagined stimulus. Where ascending and descending information is weighted equally (wl−1 = wl+1 = 1; Fig. 3b), the equilibrium point lies in the middle layer at the centre of the hierarchy such that lower layers (e.g. towards the primary visual cortex) are dominated by externally generated sensory input and upper layers (e.g. towards the temporal lobe) are dominated by internally generated thoughts, symmetrically. However, overweighting feedforward information (wl−1/wl+1 > 1) elevates the equilibrium point such that the imagined stimulus is restricted to only the highest, least-modal hierarchical layers, corresponding to a state of aphantasia (Fig. 3a). In contrast, overweighting feedback information (wl−1/wl+1 < 1) lowers the equilibrium point such that the imagined stimulus dominates the majority of the hierarchy, corresponding to a state of hyperphantasia (Fig. 3c). Feedforward-to-feedback weighting ratio variation could therefore account for between-person and moment-to-moment differences in the apparent sensory quality of mental imagery experiences.

Discussion

Distinguishing imagined, veridical, and hallucinatory percepts

In this study, we aimed to explain the apparent differences in vividness between veridical, imagined, and hallucinated percepts. We show that, for a hierarchical system with bidirectional information flow, the presence of competing sensory input can prevent internally generated stimuli from dominating low-level regions most suited for supporting a modal, highly sensory neural representation. We interpret this finding as suggesting that, when competing sensory input is present, the sensory content of imagination does not supersede the sensory content of veridical perception. That is, for instance, even if we imagine a hat, our mental image of the hat does not replace the image of a real camel in our visual field: the camel is still more visible. In contrast, the attenuation or abolition of competing external sensory input could facilitate internally generated stimuli becoming the dominant contributor to sensory experience, creating hallucinatory imagery. Our model therefore illustrates that the apparent difference in reported vividness between veridical and imagined percepts could be explained by the degree to which imagined and veridical stimulus representations spread hierarchically and that this difference can arise due to external sensory input competing with our internally generated thoughts.

Neurological consequences of perceptual competition

Our model results in some counterintuitive implications. Despite the suitability of the early visual cortex for representing retinotopic, visual information, our account suggests that hierarchically low-level neural regions (e.g. primary sensory cortices) may be less involved in representing an imagined stimulus than any other region in the corresponding perceptual hierarchy. However, this implication is consistent with existing findings. Individuals still report being able to create mental images despite near-complete bilateral lesions to primary visual cortex, suggesting that the primary visual cortex is not necessary for visual mental imagery (Chatterjee and Southwood 1995; Zago et al. 2010; Bridge et al. 2012; de Gelder et al. 2015). Even mid-level impairments to the visual system, a potential cause of visual agnosia, can leave visual mental imagery preserved (Behrmann et al. 1994). Furthermore, a meta-analysis of the neural correlates of visual mental imagery by Spagna et al. (2021) found that the left fusiform gyrus, a high-level region within the visual ventral stream, was reliably involved during mental imagery across studies while early visual cortices were not.

These findings are entirely in line with the predictions of our model: while primary sensory cortices can be involved in mental imagery, the only essential component of the experience is the internal generation of a non-veridical stimulus representation, which, in our model, occurs at the hierarchical apex, corresponding, for instance, to late in the visual ventral stream. This may be why subjective vividness ratings better correlate with how distinctly imagined information is represented in retinotopic, rather than associative, neural regions (Lee et al. 2012). Under our model, activation at levels below the clamped internally generated representation can add progressively more sensory components to the experience of imagining, although at what stage a relatively amodal, abstract thought formally becomes a truly sensory mental image may be an arbitrary distinction.

Our simulations predict that the dominance of internally generated stimuli should increase from posterior to anterior regions of the visual hierarchy. Supporting this prediction, VanRullen and Reddy (2019) used a mental imagery decoding paradigm to show that more information about imagined face images was present in temporal regions than occipital regions. Lee et al. (2012) likewise showed that less information about imagined object images could be decoded towards more posterior, retinotopic areas of the visual system. Both studies also found that externally and internally generated stimulus representations became more similar towards higher-level regions, aligning with the notion that imagined content is propagated from areas active during late-stage veridical perception.

Phenomenological consequences of perceptual competition

Our model has implications for the functional and subjective characteristics of imagery. For instance, the relegation of imagination to relatively high-level representations suggests that thinking in a non-sensory way may be more commonplace than manifesting thoughts in a sensory way (e.g. as an actual visual image). This makes pragmatic sense in everyday life: thinking about what you are seeing is often favourable during veridical visual perception, yet it may be quite unfavourable to see what you are thinking about given that such hallucinations may supersede important survival-relevant environmental information. However, this process could involve a functional trade-off as the semantic content of sensory input may be processed poorly if high-level regions are already occupied by unrelated thoughts. Mental imagery could push internally generated high-level representations towards mid-level regions, interfering with the ascending processing of externally generated stimuli. This could explain why internal attention can affect the processing of environmental stimuli, such as during daydreaming (Schooler et al. 2011; Smallwood 2011). States of immersive mental imagery (e.g. daydreaming) might then loosely and transiently share phenomenological similarities with agnosia given that high-level processing of externally generated stimuli may be impeded despite low-level visual feature processing being relatively unaffected. For instance, when reading text while distracted by other thoughts, one may find themselves rereading the same paragraph repeatedly, seeing the words each time, yet failing to process the meaning of the text.

Another effect of abstract representations being activated without any significant low-level representation during imagery is that a perceiver might plausibly even ‘feel’ like they have seen their imagined thought without ever experiencing it in any substantially visual way. That is, units involved in the recognition of an object may be activated despite minimal low-level activation. Hence, people could theoretically report being able to visualize objects, yet fail to be able to reconstruct the details of these imagined stimuli accurately.

Additionally, experiencing imagery on a spectrum from highly abstract to highly sensory may explain why the unique quasi-sensory experience of mental imagery may be difficult to describe. Common language generally only allows perceptual experience to be described as explicitly sensory (e.g. seen) or explicitly non-sensory (e.g. unseen), forcing ambiguously defined terms like ‘vividness’ to fill in the gaps. While the content of mental imagery could be described in terms of objectively quantifiable stimulus properties (e.g. contrast, size, and duration), the experience of such content is modified by the degree to which a mental image gains sensory features as well as just abstract features. This modulation, encapsulated by the aforementioned concept of a representational equilibrium point, could be the underlying variable commonly measured (albeit somewhat indistinctly) by subjective ratings of imagery ‘vividness’. If so, this would justify why vividness ratings are generally only investigated concerning imagined, not veridical, experiences: veridical percepts are maximally sensory by default.

Hallucinations

Our model also delineates conditions for hallucinations. Visually, a hallucination entails seeing a non-veridical sensory percept in a given region of the visual field instead of a percept that reflects external reality. Under our model, for any modality, the most perceptually compelling hallucinations would then be those where a non-veridical stimulus dominates most, if not all, low-level representations. The notion of non-veridical information penetrating sensory systems top-down to cause hallucinations has been previously explored in depth under a predictive coding framework (Powers et al. 2016). In our model, it can occur from overweighting top-down information relative to bottom-up information. However, hallucinations could also occur simply if aberrant low-level activity is fed through an otherwise normal perceptual system (Hahamy et al. 2021). Note that, in both cases, our model only accounts for the perceptual experience of imagery, hallucinated or otherwise, and not whether it was induced voluntarily (as imagery tends to be) or involuntarily (as hallucinations tend to be).

In the first suggested route to hallucinations, top-down information becomes overweighted such that non-veridical thoughts can permeate low-level areas to nearly the same extent as uncontested bottom-up veridical input. In this case, hallucinations are modelled as an anomalous case of mental imagery with an extremely low representational equilibrium point, similar to hyperphantasia. If our model is correct, then individuals with hallucinatory disorders should tend to have improved mental imagery abilities. Accordingly, Parkinson’s hallucinators tend to have stronger mental imagery priming effects than non-hallucinating controls, with the degree of imagery-induced priming predicting hallucination frequency (Shine et al. 2015). Parkinson’s hallucinators also mind-wander more than non-hallucinators, corresponding to increased connectivity to the early visual cortex from default network regions (Walpola et al. 2020). Additionally, although individuals with schizophrenia can have impaired memory, their abilities on visuospatial mental imagery manipulation tasks are enhanced compared to neurotypical controls (Benson and Park 2013; Matthews et al. 2014). However, note that some individuals are able to complete mental imagery manipulation tasks while reporting no visual mental imagery (Zeman et al. 2010).

Hallucinations should also occur when sensory input is disconnected altogether such that internally generated percepts are entirely uncontested. If feedforward information is downweighted completely (wl−1= 0) to any layer, then that layer and any layer above it are free to be commandeered by any high-level internally generated stimulus present. Representations at such layers will then inevitably converge towards the internally generated stimulus representation (Figs 2b, e, and 3d). This could contribute to hallucinations in disorders of afferent visual processing (e.g. Charles Bonnet syndrome; Reichert et al. 2013). Hallucinations are reasonably common following cortical blindness (Aldrich et al. 1987), and in one such reported case, hallucinations could be induced directly from attempting voluntary mental imagery (Wunderlich et al. 2000). Dampening external sensory input might also contribute to hypnagogic hallucinations, which occur during sleep onset. When falling asleep, the cortex remains active several minutes after the thalamus begins silencing external sensory information (Magnin et al. 2010), potentially providing a window of time in which internally generated cortical activity has reduced competition from the external environment.

Top-down effects are probably not solely responsible for hallucinatory perception, however. Hallucinations can be visually detailed and sometimes reportedly even clearer than veridical percepts (Teunisse et al. 1996; Ffytche et al. 1998; Manford and Andermann 1998). This implies that hallucinations may not be a purely top-down phenomenon given that retrohierarchically extrapolating high-level information into low-level regions should result in a degradation of visual information (Breedlove et al. 2020). Many hallucinations are therefore likely to also involve aberrant low-level cortical activity (Manford and Andermann 1998; Hahamy et al. 2021) perhaps independent of, or in tandem with, amplified feedback signals.

Eyes-open versus eyes-closed imagery

We note that the model proposed in this paper does not presume any difference between an eyes-closed and eyes-open state apart from the change to the content of the sensory input each act produces. Although closing one’s eyes might be ostensibly interpreted as disconnecting external sensory input to the visual system, if this were the case, our model would predict that closing one’s eyes would rapidly result in hallucinations. While hallucinations can happen when the eyes are deprived of light, such phenomena generally require either drugs (Fisher 1991) or multiple hours (if not days) of light deprivation to manifest (Merabet et al. 2004). It could be that darkness constitutes a genuine sensory disconnection, yet with neural activity adapting to a lack of competition on slow timescales, or it could be that sensory deprivation alone does not equate to a true sensory disconnection. A formal disconnection or downweighting of sensory input could instead require large-scale neurochemical or neurophysiological changes, such as those which occur when shifting between different states of arousal (see the following section, ‘Serotonin and acetylcholine: neurologically plausible bottom-up and top-down weighting agents’, for details). This may be why eye closure (or darkness) is not sufficient for hallucinations in neurotypical individuals during normal waking states, but does co-occur with hallucinations during altered neurochemical states, such as during sleep onset and offset (i.e. hypnagogic and hypnopompic hallucinations) and during sleep itself (i.e. dreaming). Even in blind individuals who cannot perceive environmental light levels, hallucinations are not ubiquitous and tend to occur later in the day when drowsy (Manford and Andermann 1998), suggesting that darkness alone is not a form of sensory disconnection.

Closing one’s eyes (at least on short time scales) might then be most aptly interpreted as changing sensory input to a diffuse, dark, and generally unremarkable stimulus image rather than disconnecting it altogether. Still, visual mental imagery is more likely to be reported when eyes are closed rather than open (Sulfaro et al. 2023). However, while eye closure tends to aid the recall of fine-grained sensory information, potentially by improving mental imagery, recall is not significantly improved compared to merely looking at blank space (Vredeveldt et al. 2011). Yet, we acknowledge that our conceptualization of eye closure may be a simplification given that neural activity patterns between eyes-closed and eyes-open states can differ substantially even when both occur in darkness (Marx et al. 2003, 2004). Even so, an eyes-closed state could still improve mental imagery simply due to the signal-to-noise ratio advantage gained by pitting an imagined stimulus representation against a homogenous closed-eye scene, with the additional benefit of hiding attentional distractors.

Serotonin and acetylcholine: neurologically plausible bottom-up and top-down weighting agents

This model implies that neural agents exist which modulate the relative contribution of top-down and bottom-up processes. Given that this model predicts that weighting schemes affect veridical and hallucinatory perception as well as mental imagery, agents that modulate these processes might also be apt candidate weighting agents in our current model.

Serotonin may be one such agent that modulates the contribution of bottom-up information during visual perception. Classic hallucinogens act on the serotonergic system via 5-hydroxytryptamine 2A (5HT2A) receptors (Nichols 2016), and cortical serotonin levels are dependent on plasma levels of tryptophan, serotonin’s precursor, which readily crosses the blood-brain barrier (Fernstrom and Wurtman 1971). Plasma tryptophan increases over the course of the day, peaking in the late evening (Rao et al. 1994), approximately corresponding to the most common time of hallucination onset for individuals with Charles Bonnet syndrome, peduncular hallucinosis, and Parkinson’s disease, including for those without any ability to perceive light (Manford and Andermann 1998). Furthermore, 5HT2A receptor expression in the ventral visual pathway of Parkinson’s disease hallucinators is elevated compared to non-hallucinators (Ballanger et al. 2010; Huot et al. 2010), while inverse agonists for this receptor are used to treat Parkinson’s disease hallucinations (Yasue et al. 2016). Outside of hallucinatory states, serotonin administered in the primary visual cortex of awake macaques acts as a gain modulator, dampening cell responses to external sensory input without affecting stimulus tuning or selectivity profiles (Seillier et al. 2017). In mice, this dampening in V1 was mediated by a 5HT2A receptor agonist (Michaiel et al. 2019).

Additionally, acetylcholine may modulate the contribution of top-down information during visual experience. The ratio of acetylcholine to serotonin is a factor in hallucination aetiology (Manford and Andermann 1998), and both serotonin and acetylcholine target Layer 5 cortical pyramidal neurons, cells which have been proposed as essential for manifesting conscious sensory perception (Aru et al. 2019). High concentrations of acetylcholine can transition the activity of Layer 5 cortical pyramidal neurons from being driven by feedforward inputs to feedback inputs, which may mediate the hallucinatory experience of dreaming (Aru et al. 2020). The concentration of cortical acetylcholine peaks during rapid eye movement sleep, where dreaming is most likely, higher than during wakefulness and higher still than during non-rapid eye movement sleep where consciousness is greatly impaired (Lee et al. 2005). Hence, cortical acetylcholine concentrations may modulate feedback connectivity in sensory cortices.

Given their actions in the visual system, serotonin and acetylcholine levels could be plausible factors accounting for contextual and interindividual differences in the perceptual experience of mental imagery. Accordingly, they could also be considered as factors which modulate interlayer weightings within our proposed model. However, ascertaining the role of such neurotransmitters in mental imagery research is challenged by a reliance on human models for self-report, indistinct metrics and constructs (e.g. vividness ratings), and the restricted access of psychoactive serotonergic drugs. Ultimately, there are many mechanisms by which our model can facilitate hallucinations and such mechanisms may work in tandem. Note that in all cases, our model does not explain how the initial internally generated source stimulus might be produced, only how it may be represented, regardless of whether it was generated as part of a voluntary thought, involuntary hallucination, or otherwise.

Mental imagery as a dynamic process

So far, our predictions have been based on simulations where imagery, once generated, continues to be generated indefinitely and without interruption. Under these conditions, internally generated content can continue to spread downwards until it reaches an equilibrium point and can spread no further. Yet, if imagery is interrupted or generated intermittently, it may never be generated for a period long enough for it to spread to its maximum possible extent, even if the balance of top-down and bottom-up processes favours a very low equilibrium point (i.e. highly sensory mental imagery). Analogously, even though the maximum possible speed of a sports car may be faster than that of a van, the sports car will be outpaced if the van driver keeps the pedal floored while the sports car driver only taps the pedal on and off. If mental image content can be generated continuously, or supported by a stream of simulated sensory information at lower levels, then the chances of that content spreading to its maximum possible extent are increased.

Visual versus auditory mental imagery

Although we have focused on visual mental imagery, mental imagery can occur in other sensory modalities, presumably through similar generative feedback. A complete account of mental imagery should be able to predict and explain modality-specific differences in imagined experience. Auditory hallucinations are roughly twice as common as visual hallucinations in schizophrenia and bipolar disorder (Waters et al. 2014), although how experiences differ between modalities specifically for mental imagery is not well understood. Comparisons generally rely on mental image vividness ratings (e.g. Betts 1910; Sheehan 1967; Switras 1978; Gissurarson 1992; Schifferstein 2009; Andrade et al., 2014; Talamini et al. 2022). Yet, as such rating systems are ambiguously defined and difficult to meaningfully interpret (Richardson 1988), findings have been understandably mixed. Here, we make predictions about how the quality of mental imagery may differ between visual and auditory mental imagery, perhaps the two most-studied imagery modalities, based on the differences in the brain’s ability to synthesize sensory information in each modality.

Unlike with visual stimuli, our bodies are readily capable of producing their own auditory stimuli using speech. Self-initiated movements, including the act of speech, produce signals (e.g. efference copies) that carry temporally precise predictions of the sensory consequences of such movements (Curio et al. 2000). Sensory predictions related to motor movements have been suggested to aid mental imagery when they are produced in the absence of real movements (Scott 2013; Whitford et al. 2017; Gelding et al. 2019; Jack et al. 2019; Pruitt et al. 2019). This could occur by supplying imagination with the sensory content needed to generate a mental image or by supporting existing mental imagery with a stream of sensory predictions linked to real or simulated movements. As discussed previously, anchoring mental images to continuous sensory information should improve the quality of mental imagery under our model.

While visual mental images could be supported by sensory predictions from real or simulated eye movements, eye movements generally contain information about where imagined content is, was, or will be (e.g. Fourtassi et al. 2017). However, they are far less informative about what the content actually is that is being imagined in a given region of the visual field. In comparison, consider inner speech, a type of auditory imagery specifically related to the imagination of oral sound content like words. If auditory imagery can be expressed as inner speech, such as through converting imagined sounds to onomatopoeia, then real or simulated vocal movements could produce a stream of temporally precise sensory information not just informing on when a particular imagined sound should be heard but also informing on what the imagined sound content should actually be. In essence, using motor systems, the brain could have a greater capacity to simulate sensory features of imagined sounds compared to images, provided that the imagined sounds are somewhat possible to replicate vocally. Yet, even when not readily imitable, sounds could still be imagined as some form of onomatopoeia, sacrificing real-world accuracy in order to boost the sensory quality of the imagery experience. Consequently, we expect that auditory mental imagery may often be a more compelling sensory experience than visual mental imagery. Recent work supports these predictions, finding that auditory imagery is generally superior to visual mental imagery across a number of self-report metrics, although experiences seem to be quite diverse overall (Sulfaro et al., 2023).

Limitations and future directions

The primary intention of this article is to highlight that competition from externally generated sensory input could be a major factor that explains the unique phenomenology of mental imagery. Our modelling is mainly intended merely to provide a simple example of how treating perception as a competitive process can explain aspects of imagery, supporting the larger theoretical argument that mental imagery should always be considered in tandem with co-occurring veridical perceptual processes. Nonetheless, both our argument and our suggested model rely on some assumptions.

Our most crucial restraint is that we require that internally and externally generated perceptual processes utilize the same neural substrates such that interference can occur. Our current understanding is that these processes do overlap (Ffytche et al. 1998; Dijkstra et al. 2017, 2020), down to the laminar cortical (Lawrence et al. 2018; Bergmann et al. 2019), if not cellular (Aru et al. 2020), level. However, differences between each process may mean that overlap might vary across the visual hierarchy (e.g. Lawrence et al. 2018), influencing the degree or nature of interference. Yet, even if these processes do overlap, imagined representations may not necessarily propagate smoothly along a serial, retrohierarchical cascade. If imagery utilizes direct feedback connections from associative cortices to primary sensory cortices, rather than via a series of intermediate cortical units, interference may have radically different outcomes.

We also rely on assumptions about how neural activity translates into subjective experience. Namely, we assume that lower and higher levels of processing, respectively, contribute to sensory and abstract features of perceptual experience. Yet, encoding along the visual hierarchy may only correlate with the degree to which semantic content of a perceptual experience is simple or complex, rather than the degree to which such content is experienced in a sensory and modality-specific, rather than non-sensory, way at all. Of course, ascertaining the neural substrates of subjective experience is an immense area of investigation.

Although we make broad predictions about the decaying influence of internally generated stimuli towards primary sensory regions, the exact balance of this influence, and its dynamics, would likely vary substantially with more neurologically plausible methods of simulating interference beyond the simple weighted-averaging rule used to approximate interference in our model. Also, note that our model does not comment on any of the non-linear transformations necessary to encode a representation within a layer but only makes assumptions about how such representations, once formed, may be transmitted and combined. Modelling a more neurologically plausible system would be a logical next step for investigating mental imagery as a competitive process. Furthermore, it is entirely plausible that other mechanisms aside from competition could account for the segregated distributions of internally and externally generated content in the visual system. We merely show that simple models of competition can account for these distributions and many other imagery phenomena.

Our simulations also use retinal inputs (and generally imagined stimulus inputs) that are static and constant, so our simulations cannot account for the effects of neural adaptation on perceptual interference. In reality, retinally stabilized images tend to induce a reversible blindness, greying out the visual field. However, such blindness is suspected to be a very early, low-level effect, at or near the retina (Martinez-Conde et al. 2004). Within our model, this state should then be roughly equivalent to feeding in a homogenous field as a real stimulus input, such that the same logic regarding the imagery improvements (or lack thereof) associated with eye closure and the perception of a dark room would also apply to the perceptual greying out that occurs with retinally stabilized images. However, neural adaptation could have many more consequential effects on mental imagery which future studies could explore.

Our model also assumes that feedforward and feedback processes are computationally equivalent. However, Koenig-Robert and Pearson (2021) argue that while feedforward signals initiated from visual input may drive action potentials in the visual cortex, feedback signals terminating in early visual areas tend to be more modulatory, guiding but not overriding activity induced by sensory input. They suggest that this asymmetry could account for the apparent difference in vividness between veridical and mental imagery. However, weak feedback could also be a logical consequence of competition within our model. Our simulations predict that the influence of internally generated stimulus information should gradually diminish towards lower levels in the presence of bottom-up competition. At some point, this declining influence could fall below a threshold such that it can no longer drive action potentials. Yet, our model still uniquely predicts that feedback should remain influential when external competition is not present. Evidence supports this prediction, as feedback can drive action potentials in the visual cortex of neurotypical individuals during dreaming (Aru et al. 2020), including in neurons that are arguably crucial for manifesting conscious sensory perception (Aru et al. 2019). Hence, it is plausible that weak feedback follows from perceptual competition. Our model may then supplement the account of Koenig-Robert and Pearson (2021) which could otherwise be interpreted as precluding the possibility of purely top-down hallucinations. Asymmetries in feedforward and feedback processing can still be operationalized in our model by manipulating bottom-up and top-down weightings, but our model distinctly predicts that imagined percepts should be experienced in a less sensory manner than veridical percepts, even if feedforward and feedback processes are computationally equivalent, due to the interference caused by competing sensory input.

Overall, vindicating or falsifying competition as the origin of the quasi-sensory experience of mental imagery will ultimately require a detailed understanding of how neural representations of internally and externally generated perceptual content interact. Future studies may seek to explore the predicted impact of hierarchical competition on neural activity using alternative models of feedforward–feedback interference, although our model still capably emulates findings on how imagined and veridical information is distributed in real human brains (e.g. Lee et al. 2012; VanRullen and Reddy 2019; Spagna et al. 2021).

Conclusion

Overall, this work provides a formal framework for explaining the unique quasi-sensory experience of mental imagery. We propose that internally generated thoughts are experienced along an axis from highly abstract to highly sensory in nature, aligning with the degree of dimensionality that a given thought is represented in. Under this assumption, we show that competition from bottom-up sensory input may prevent imagined stimuli from being perceived in any substantially sensory way. Accounting for competition in a hierarchical system can therefore provide sufficient conditions for distinguishing imagined, veridical, and hallucinatory perception, as well as variation within these phenomena. As modelling imagery competitively may resolve major lingering questions in imagery research, we recommend that future studies investigate the exact manner by which internally and externally generated stimuli may be combined in the brain. Ultimately, we conclude that mental imagery is most logically understood as an intrinsically competitive process and should be largely considered as such in ongoing research.

Funding

A.A.S was supported by an Australian Government Research Training Program Scholarship. A.K.R. was supported by an Australian Research Council Discovery Early Career Researcher Award (DE200101159). T.A.C. was supported by an Australian Research Council Discovery Project (DP200101787).

Conflict of interest

None declared.

Data availability

No data was collected as part of this study.

References

Aldrich
MS
,
Alessi
AG
,
Beck
RW
et al.
Cortical blindness: etiology, diagnosis, and prognosis
.
Ann Neurol
1987
;
21
:
149
58
.

Andrade
J
,
May
J
,
Deeprose
C
et al.
Assessing vividness of mental imagery: the Plymouth Sensory Imagery Questionnaire
.
Br J Psychol
2014
;
105
:
547
63
.

Aru
J
,
Siclari
F
,
Phillips
WA
et al.
Apical drive—a cellular mechanism of dreaming?
Neurosci Biobehav Rev
2020
;
119
:
440
55
.

Aru
J
,
Suzuki
M
,
Rutiku
R
et al. .
Coupling the state and contents of consciousness
.
Front Syst Neurosci
2019
;
13
:43.

Ballanger
B
,
Strafella
AP
,
van Eimeren
T
et al. .
Serotonin 2A receptors and visual hallucinations in Parkinson disease
.
Arch Neurol
2010
;
67
:
416
21
.

Behrmann
M
,
Moscovitch
M
,
Winocur
G
.
Intact visual imagery and impaired visual perception in a patient with visual agnosia
.
J Exp Psychol Hum Percept Perform
1994
;
20
:
1068
87
.

Benson
T
,
Park
S
.
Exceptional visuospatial imagery in schizophrenia; implications for madness and creativity
.
Front Hum Neurosci
2013
;
7
:756.

Bergmann
J
,
Morgan
AT
,
Muckli
L
.
Two distinct feedback codes in V1 for ‘real’ and ‘imaginary’ internal experiences
. BioRxiv
2019
;664870.

Betts
GH
.
Review of the distribution and functions of mental imagery
.
Psychol Bull
1910
;
7
:
351
2
.

Binder
JR
.
In defense of abstract conceptual representations
.
Psychon Bull Rev
2016
;
23
:
1096
108
.

Breedlove
JL
,
St-Yves
G
,
Olman
CA
et al. .
Generative feedback explains distinct brain activity codes for seen and mental images
.
Curr Biol
2020
;
30
:
2211
24.e6
.

Bridge
H
,
Harrold
S
,
Holmes
EA
et al. .
Vivid visual mental imagery in the absence of the primary visual cortex
.
J Neurol
2012
;
259
:
1062
70
.

Brodeur
MB
,
Dionne-Dostie
E
,
Montreuil
T
et al. .
The Bank of Standardized Stimuli (BOSS), a new set of 480 normative photos of objects to be used as visual stimuli in cognitive research
.
PLoS One
2010
;
5
:e10773.

Chatterjee
A
,
Southwood
MH
.
Cortical blindness and visual imagery
.
Neurology
1995
;
45
:
2189
95
.

Chiu
LPW
.
Differential diagnosis and management of hallucinations
.
Hong Kong Med Assoc
1989
;
41
:
292
7
.

Cichy
RM
,
Heinzle
J
,
Haynes
J-D
.
Imagery and perception share cortical representations of content and location
.
Cereb Cortex
2012
;
22
:
372
80
.

Curio
G
,
Neuloh
G
,
Numminen
J
et al. .
Speaking modifies voice-evoked activity in the human auditory cortex
.
Hum Brain Mapp
2000
;
9
:
183
91
.

de Gelder
B
,
Tamietto
M
,
Pegna
AJ
et al. .
Visual imagery influences brain responses to visual stimulation in bilateral cortical blindness
.
Cortex
2015
;
72
:
15
26
.

Dentico
D
,
Cheung
BL
,
Chang
J-Y
et al. .
Reversal of cortical information flow during visual imagery as compared to visual perception
.
NeuroImage
2014
;
100
:
237
43
.

DiCarlo
JJ
,
Cox
DD
.
Untangling invariant object recognition
.
Trends Cogn Sci
2007
;
11
:
333
41
.

Dijkstra
N
,
Ambrogioni
L
,
Vidaurre
D
et al. .
Neural dynamics of perceptual inference and its reversal during imagery
.
eLife
2020
;
9
:e53588.

Dijkstra
N
,
Bosch
SE
,
Gerven
MAJV
.
Vividness of visual imagery depends on the neural overlap with perception in visual areas
.
J Neurosci
2017
;
37
:
1367
73
.

Dijkstra
N
,
Bosch
SE
,
van Gerven
MAJ
.
Shared neural mechanisms of visual perception and imagery
.
Trends Cogn Sci
2019a
;
23
:
423
34
.

Dijkstra
N
,
Hinne
M
,
Bosch
SE
et al. .
Between-subject variability in the influence of mental imagery on conscious perception
.
Sci Rep
2019b
;
9
:15658.

Dijkstra
N
,
Kok
P
,
Fleming
SM
.
Imagery adds stimulus-specific sensory evidence to perceptual detection
.
J Vis
2022
;
22
:11.

Dijkstra
N
,
Mazor
M
,
Kok
P
et al. .
Mistaking imagination for reality: congruent mental imagery leads to more liberal perceptual detection
.
Cognition
2021
;
212
:104719.

Dijkstra
N
,
Mostert
P
,
Lange
FPD
et al. .
Differential temporal dynamics during visual imagery and perception
.
eLife
2018
;
7
:e33904.

Fernstrom
JD
,
Wurtman
RJ
.
Brain serotonin content: physiological dependence on plasma tryptophan levels
.
Science
1971
;
173
:
149
52
.

Ffytche
DH
,
Howard
RJ
,
Brammer
MJ
et al. .
The anatomy of conscious vision: an fMRI study of visual hallucinations
.
Nat Neurosci
1998
;
1
:
738
42
.

Fisher
CM
.
Visual hallucinations on eye closure associated with atropine toxicity. A neurological analysis and comparison with other visual hallucinations
.
Can J Neurolog Sci
1991
;
18
:
18
27
.

Fourtassi
M
,
Rode
G
,
Pisella
L
.
Using eye movements to explore mental representations of space
.
Ann Phys Rehabil Med
2017
;
60
:
160
3
.

Galton
F
.
Statistics of mental imagery
.
Mind
1880
;
5
:
301
18
.

Gelding
RW
,
Thompson
WF
,
Johnson
BW
.
Musical imagery depends upon coordination of auditory and sensorimotor brain activity
.
Sci Rep
2019
;
9
:16823.

Gissurarson
LR
.
Reported auditory imagery and its relationship with visual imagery
.
J Mental Imagery
1992
;
16
:
117
22
.

Hahamy
A
,
Wilf
M
,
Rosin
B
et al. .
How do the blind ‘see’? The role of spontaneous brain activity in self-generated perception
.
Brain
2021
;
144
:
340
53
.

Huot
P
,
Johnston
TH
,
Darr
T
et al. .
Increased 5-HT2A receptors in the temporal cortex of parkinsonian patients with visual hallucinations
.
Mov Disorders
2010
;
25
:
1399
408
.

Ishai
A
.
Seeing faces and objects with the “mind’s eye”
.
Arch Ital Biol
2010
;
148
:
1
9
.

Jack
BN
,
Le Pelley
ME
,
Han
N
et al. .
Inner speech is accompanied by a temporally-precise and content-specific corollary discharge
.
NeuroImage
2019
;
198
:
170
80
.

Keogh
R
,
Pearson
J
.
The perceptual and phenomenal capacity of mental imagery
.
Cognition
2017
;
162
:
124
32
.

Koenig-Robert
R
,
Pearson
J
.
Why do imagery and perception look and feel so different?
.
Philos Trans R Soc Lond, B, Biol Sci
2021
;
376
:20190703.

Kosslyn
SM
.
Mental images and the brain
.
Cogn Neuropsychol
2005
;
22
:
333
47
.

Kosslyn
SM
,
Alpert
NM
,
Thompson
WL
et al. .
Visual mental imagery activates topographically organized visual cortex: PET investigations
.
J Cogn Neurosci
1993
;
5
:
263
87
.

Kosslyn
SM
,
Thompson
WL
.
When is early visual cortex activated during visual mental imagery?
Psychol Bull
2003
;
129
:
723
46
.

Lawrence
SJD
,
van Mourik
T
,
Kok
P
et al. .
Laminar organization of working memory signals in human visual cortex
.
Curr Biol
2018
;
28
:
3435
40.e4
.

Lee
MG
,
Hassani
OK
,
Alonso
A
et al. .
Cholinergic basal forebrain neurons burst with theta during waking and paradoxical sleep
.
J Neurosci
2005
;
25
:
4365
9
.

Lee
S-H
,
Kravitz
DJ
,
Baker
CI
.
Disentangling visual imagery and perception of real-world objects
.
NeuroImage
2012
;
59
:
4064
73
.

Linde-Domingo
J
,
Treder
MS
,
Kerrén
C
et al. .
Evidence that neural information flow is reversed between object perception and object reconstruction from memory
.
Nat Commun
2019
;
10
:179.

Magnin
M
,
Rey
M
,
Bastuji
H
et al. .
Thalamic deactivation at sleep onset precedes that of the cerebral cortex in humans
.
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA
2010
;
107
:
3829
33
.

Manford
M
,
Andermann
F
.
Complex visual hallucinations. Clinical and neurobiological insights
.
Brain
1998
;
121
:
1819
40
.

Marks
DF
.
Visual imagery differences in the recall of pictures
.
Br J Psychol
1973
;
64
:
17
24
.

Martinez-Conde
S
,
Macknik
SL
,
Hubel
DH
.
The role of fixational eye movements in visual perception
.
Nat Rev Neurosci
2004
;
5
:
229
40
.

Marx
E
,
Deutschländer
A
,
Stephan
T
et al. .
Eyes open and eyes closed as rest conditions: impact on brain activation patterns
.
NeuroImage
2004
;
21
:
1818
24
.

Marx
E
,
Stephan
T
,
Nolte
A
et al. .
Eye closure in darkness animates sensory systems
.
NeuroImage
2003
;
19
:
924
34
.

Matthews
NL
,
Collins
KP
,
Thakkar
KN
et al. .
Visuospatial imagery and working memory in schizophrenia
.
Cogn Neuropsychiatry
2014
;
19
:
17
35
.

Merabet
LB
,
Maguire
D
,
Warde
A
et al. .
Visual hallucinations during prolonged blindfolding in sighted subjects
.
J Neuro-Ophthalmol
2004
;
24
:
109
13
.

Michaiel
AM
,
Parker
PRL
,
Niell
CM
.
A hallucinogenic serotonin-2A receptor agonist reduces visual response gain and alters temporal dynamics in mouse V1
.
Cell Rep
2019
;
26
:
3475
83.e4
.

Nichols
DE
.
Psychedelics
.
Pharmacol Rev
2016
;
68
:
264
355
.

Pearson
J
.
The human imagination: the cognitive neuroscience of visual mental imagery
.
Nat Rev Neurosci
2019
;
20
:
624
34
.

Pearson
J
,
Kosslyn
SM
.
The heterogeneity of mental representation: ending the imagery debate
.
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA
2015
;
112
:
10089
92
.

Popham
SF
,
Huth
AG
,
Bilenko
NY
et al. .
Visual and linguistic semantic representations are aligned at the border of human visual cortex
.
Nat Neurosci
2021
;
24
:Article 11.
1628
36
.

Powers
AR
,
Kelley
M
,
Corlett
PR
.
Hallucinations as top-down effects on perception
.
Biol Psychiatry
2016
;
1
:
393
400
.

Pruitt
TA
,
Halpern
AR
,
Pfordresher
PQ
.
Covert singing in anticipatory auditory imagery
.
Psychophysiology
2019
;
56
:e13297.

Rao
ML
,
Gross
G
,
Strebel
B
,
Halaris
A
,
Huber
G
,
Bräunig
P
,
Marler
M
.
Circadian rhythm of tryptophan, serotonin, melatonin, and pituitary hormones in schizophrenia
.
Biological Psychiatry
1994
;
35
:
151
63
. doi:

Reichert
DP
,
Seriès
P
,
Storkey
AJ
.
Charles Bonnet syndrome: evidence for a generative model in the cortex?
PLoS Comput Biol
2013
;
9
:e1003134.

Richardson
JE
.
Vividness and unvividness: reliability, consistency, and validity of subjective imagery ratings
.
J Mental Imagery
1988
;
12
:
115
22
.

Schifferstein
HNJ
.
Comparing mental imagery across the sensory modalities
.
Imagin Cogn Pers
2009
;
28
:
371
88
.

Schooler
JW
,
Smallwood
J
,
Christoff
K
et al. .
Meta-awareness, perceptual decoupling and the wandering mind
.
Trends Cogn Sci
2011
;
15
:
319
26
.

Scott
M
.
Corollary discharge provides the sensory content of inner speech
.
Psychol Sci
2013
;
24
:
1824
30
.

Seillier
L
,
Lorenz
C
,
Kawaguchi
K
et al. .
Serotonin decreases the gain of visual responses in awake macaque V1
.
J Neurosci
2017
;
37
:
11390
405
.

Sheehan
PW
.
A shortened form of Betts’ questionnaire upon mental imagery
.
J Clin Psychol
1967
;
23
:
386
9
.

Shine
JM
,
Keogh
R
,
O’Callaghan
C
et al. .
Imagine that: elevated sensory strength of mental imagery in individuals with Parkinson’s disease and visual hallucinations
.
Proc Biol Sci
2015
;
282
:20142047.

Smallwood
J
.
Mind-wandering while reading: attentional decoupling, mindless reading and the cascade model of inattention
.
Lang Linguist Compass
2011
;
5
:
63
77
.

Spagna
A
,
Hajhajate
D
,
Liu
J
et al. .
Visual mental imagery engages the left fusiform gyrus, but not the early visual cortex: a meta-analysis of neuroimaging evidence
.
Neurosci Biobehav Rev
2021
;
122
:
201
17
.

Sulfaro
AA
,
Robinson
AK
,
Carlson
TA
(
2023
).
Comparing mental imagery experiences across visual, auditory, and other sensory modalities
. bioRxiv.

Switras
JE
.
An alternate-form instrument to assess vividness and controllability of mental imagery in seven modalities
.
Percept Mot Skills
1978
;
46
:
379
84
.

Talamini
F
,
Vigl
J
,
Doerr
E
et al. .
Auditory and visual mental imagery in musicians and non-musicians
.
Music Sci
2022
;
2
:10298649211062724.

Teunisse
RJ
,
Zitman
FG
,
Cruysberg
JRM
et al. .
Visual hallucinations in psychologically normal people: Charles Bonnet’s syndrome
.
Lancet
1996
;
347
:
794
7
.

VanRullen
R
,
Reddy
L
.
Reconstructing faces from fMRI patterns using deep generative neural networks
.
Commu Biol
2019
;
2
:193.

Vredeveldt
A
,
Hitch
GJ
,
Baddeley
AD
.
Eyeclosure helps memory by reducing cognitive load and enhancing visualisation
.
Mem Cognit
2011
;
39
:
1253
63
.

Wais
PE
,
Rubens
MT
,
Boccanfuso
J
et al. .
Neural mechanisms underlying the impact of visual distraction on retrieval of long-term memory
.
J Neurosci
2010
;
30
:
8541
50
.

Walpola
IC
,
Muller
AJ
,
Hall
JM
et al. .
Mind-wandering in Parkinson’s disease hallucinations reflects primary visual and default network coupling
.
Cortex
2020
;
125
:
233
45
.

Waters
F
,
Collerton
D
,
Ffytche
DH
et al. .
Visual hallucinations in the psychosis spectrum and comparative information from neurodegenerative disorders and eye disease
.
Schizophr Bull
2014
;
40
:
S233
S245
.

Whitford
TJ
,
Jack
BN
,
Pearson
D
et al. .
Neurophysiological evidence of efference copies to inner speech
.
eLife
2017
;
6
:e28197.

Wunderlich
G
,
Suchan
B
,
Volkmann
J
et al. .
Visual hallucinations in recovery from cortical blindness: imaging correlates
.
Arch Neurol
2000
;
57
:
561
5
.

Xie
S
,
Kaiser
D
,
Cichy
RM
.
Visual imagery and perception share neural representations in the alpha frequency band
.
Curr Biol
2020
;
30
:
2621
2627.e5
.

Yasue
I
,
Matsunaga
S
,
Kishi
T
et al. .
Serotonin 2A receptor inverse agonist as a treatment for parkinson’s disease psychosis: a systematic review and meta-analysis of serotonin 2A receptor negative modulators
.
J Alzheimer’s Dis
2016
;
50
:
733
40
.

Zago
S
,
Corti
S
,
Bersano
A
et al. .
A cortically blind patient with preserved visual imagery
.
Cogn Behav Neurol
2010
;
23
:
44
8
.

Zeman
AZJ
,
Della Sala
S
,
Torrens
LA
et al. .
Loss of imagery phenomenology with intact visuo-spatial task performance: a case of ‘blind imagination’
.
Neuropsychologia
2010
;
48
:
145
55
.

Author notes

This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted reuse, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.