-
PDF
- Split View
-
Views
-
Cite
Cite
Pablo Hubacher Haerle, Scepticism About Self-Knowledge of Motives, The Monist, Volume 108, Issue 1, January 2025, Pages 92–104, https://doi.org/10.1093/monist/onae033
- Share Icon Share
Abstract
Many philosophers claim that we have a duty to know our motives. However, prominent theories of the mind suggest that we can’t. Such scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives is based on psychological evidence. I show that this evidence only mandates scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives if we rely on a mistaken assumption which I call ‘the myth of the one true motive’. If we reject this myth, we see that there is space to plausibly interpret the empirical data such that knowledge of one’s motives is difficult, but not impossible.
The so-called motive: another error.
—Friedrich Nietzsche (1954 [1888]), Twilight of the Idols, §6.3.
We want to know who we are. Humans have a strong drive for self-knowledge (Strohminger et al. 2017). Moreover, numerous philosophers claim that we should know ourselves. For instance, Socrates held the Delphic imperative ‘Know Thyself!’ in highest esteem (Moore 2015, 7) and Kant thought that you ought to know “whether the source of your actions is pure or impure” (Kant 2006 [1797], 6:441). Furthermore, Kant, and many philosophers after him, saw the duty for self-knowledge primarily as a duty to know one’s motives (Kant 2006 [1785], 4:407; Ware 2009).
Yet, recent empirical evidence led many philosophers and psychologists to doubt whether we can know the true causes behind our actions. For instance, a popular approach conceives of the mind as consisting of two systems: a conscious part—responsible for reasoning—and an unconscious part—leading us to act and think in spontaneous ways (e.g., Wilson 2002; Doris 2015). Often, it is implied by such a view that what’s really driving our actions lies outside ‘the mind’s eye’ and can only be revealed by psychological experiments, neuronal modelling, or evolutionary theorizing. What we ordinarily say and think about our motives is at best a lucky guess and at worst a misleading fiction (Mercier and Sperber 2011, 2017; Scaife 2014; Chater 2018).
Evidently, if true, such a view renders any duty to know one’s motives problematic. After all, it is widely believed—including by Kant himself (Kant 2006 [1797], 6:380)—that if we ought to do something, we have to be able to do it. Does the duty for self-knowledge collapse, then, because it’s impossible for us to know our motives?
In this paper, I argue against this suggestion. First, I will briefly carve out what a motive is (§1) and what it means to know one (§2). Then, I’ll present paradigmatic pieces of psychological evidence (§3) and show how they have been taken to suggest scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives (§4). Next (§5), I argue that the psychological evidence only mandates such scepticism if we rely on a mistaken assumption which I dub ‘the myth of the one true motive’. According to this myth, there is only one true cause of every action, such that if you fail to pick out that unique cause, you don’t know your motive. Rejecting this myth allows for a reasonable interpretation of the empirical data, on which knowing your motives is hard, but not impossible (§6). As a result, the duty for self-knowledge—understood as an obligation to know one’s motives—remains on a secure basis.
1. What Is a Motive?
Let’s start with this passage by G.E.M. Anscombe:
Consider the statement that one motive for my signing a petition was admiration for its promoter, X. Asked ‘Why did you sign it?’ I might well say ‘Well, for one thing, X, who is promoting it, did . . .’ and describe what he did in an admiring way. I might add ‘Of course, I know that is not a ground for signing it, but I am sure it was one of the things that most influenced me’. (1957 §13, 20)
If the signer is correct in believing admiration to be one of the things that influenced them most, it seems natural to say they have knowledge of their motives. But how did they get such knowledge? And what kind of thing is a motive, anyway?
There are multiple ways to think about motives in philosophy (Anscombe 1957 §13, 20f.; Velleman 1989, 199), psychology (Schultheiss and Brunstein 2010, 308; Thrash et al. 2010; Simler and Hanson 2018, 6ff.), and law (Heering 2015, 45f.; Simester and Sullivan 2019, 138). Some of these senses are very narrow—for instance, certain philosophers see motives as necessarily third-personal terms—while others are rather wide—some psychologists understand motives simply as tendencies to act in response to incentives. The legal understanding is a happy compromise. In law, whether an action was done with intent has important ramifications. It makes all the difference between murder and manslaughter. The motive behind an intentional action, however, is often seen as irrelevant to the law. An illegal action done with a good motive is illegal nonetheless (Heering 2015, 45f.; Simester and Sullivan 2019, 138). Behind this lies the view that motives are deeper reasons for actions, i.e., things that determine intentions to act. In what follows, I adopt this intuitive view. When the signer in Anscombe’s example comes to know what their motive was, they don’t learn whether their signing was intentional. Instead, they learn why they’ve signed in the first place.
Many more things should be said about this account—in particular, how exactly desires and further intentions relate to motives.1 For brevity, I’ll confine myself to one fundamental point: Are motives reasons or causes? Consider how ‘motive’ is used in a detective story. Crucially here, a motive isn’t something that is necessarily acted on. The gardener can have a motive to murder, but it may have been the butler who did it. In that context, a motive is more like a ‘pure rationalization’, expressing that it would have made sense for the agent to act, independently of whether they actually did. Generalizing from this context, you might think of motives as unconnected to causality.
However, the sense of motive relevant for knowledge of one’s motives is not this one. When the signer in Anscombe’s example comes to know their motives, they don’t just learn that it would have made sense for them to act out of admiration. Instead, they know that admiration in fact played some part in bringing about their action. Knowledge of your motives is incompatible with an agnostic stance about what actually led you to act. This shows that a motive, in the sense relevant here, entertains an actual causal connection to whatever it is a motive for.2
Having a somewhat clearer grasp of what motives are, we can now ask what it takes to know them.
2. Two Necessary Conditions
Think back to Anscombe’s example. If admiration played no causal part in the signer’s action, their belief that it influenced them would be false and thus couldn’t amount to knowledge. So, the following seems like a good candidate for a necessary condition on knowledge of one’s motives:
(C1) A motive-belief which amounts to knowledge picks out a causal factor of an action.
As an absolute minimum, a motive-ascription expressing self-knowledge needs to refer to some causal factor in an action. A motive-ascription is falsified if the cited motive has no causal bearing on the action. Obviously, (C1) is merely necessary and by no means sufficient: there are countless causes of any action that have nothing to do with motives at all.
Moreover, we know from epistemology that true belief isn’t enough for knowledge. Instead, we need to have some form of justification. For the time being, I’ll think of justification as imposing a sort of anti-luck condition (Pritchard 2007). Whether this is spelt out in terms of a reliable belief-forming process or along different lines (e.g., evidentialism), doesn’t matter for my purposes. Building on this insight, we can formulate a second necessary condition:
(C2) A motive-belief which amounts to knowledge is justified, i.e., true in a nonlucky way.
Accordingly, we don’t know our motives, if the belief we have only tracks a causal factor by accident. In the next section, I will present research which has been taken to imply that it is not possible to fulfil those necessary conditions.
3. Psychological Evidence
In a seminal article Richard Nisbett and Timothy Wilson (1977) discuss multiple studies where agents are manipulated into choosing certain items. The subjects were influenced in their choices by unconscious biases induced through the experimenters. When asked why they acted, agents came up with motives that had nothing to do with the true causes of their actions. From this, Nisbett and Wilson conclude that “people may have little ability to report accurately on their cognitive processes” (ibid. 247). Instead, they argue that we may be able to infer our motives based on causal theories which can be at most “incidentally” correct (ibid. 233, 253ff.).
Daniel Wegner and Thalia Wheatley (1999) advance a related argument. Drawing on a range of experiments—including the famous trials by Benjamin Libet—they argue that people’s actions are caused by unconscious mechanisms which also cause the feeling of conscious will, including the experience of acting out of a specific motive. However, this experience doesn’t indicate an actual causal factor of an action; instead, it’s a causally irrelevant ‘third variable’ (ibid. 482f.; see Figure 1). The unconscious mechanism is what’s really driving the action, the motive is merely ‘epiphenomenal’ (Thrash et al. 2010, 330).

The unconscious cause leads to the action. The presumed motive has no causal bearing on the action.
An explicit successor of these research programs is the choice-blindness paradigm (Johansson et al. 2005, 2006; Hall et al. 2010). In the choice-blindness framework, subjects choose between two alternatives. Afterwards, they are presented with their ‘choice’ and asked to justify it. Unbeknownst to them, they are given the other alternative. Surprisingly, participants easily come up with reasons for the option they decided against. Now, those avowed motives couldn’t have been causally relevant for their choice, because they justify the alternative they didn’t choose!
4. Scepticism
It’s not hard to see how this evidence has been taken to motivate scepticism about knowledge of our motives. According to the strong sceptic, the evidence is best explained by the postulate that motives don’t exist at all. We fail to meet (C1) because whatever we can consciously avow has nothing to do with the true causes of our actions. Some see Friedrich Nietzsche as a predecessor of this view (Ridley 2018). More recently, psychologist Nick Chater has defended the claim that “the interpretation of the motives of real people is no different from the interpretation of fictional characters” (2018, 4). According to Chater, motive-beliefs can’t be true as their content doesn’t exist in the first place. Instead, our actions are determined by highly context-dependent processes (ibid. 109ff.; Steward et al. 2006). Uncovering a person’s true motives is impossible “not because they are difficult to find, but because there is nothing to find” (Chater 2018, 4).
In the current literature, Chater’s position represents an extreme and many writers favour a weaker position. Wilson (2002), John Doris (2015) and Hugo Mercier and Dan Sperber (2011, 2017) embrace something like weak scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives. On their picture, the evidence isn’t best explained by denying that motives exist. Rather, motive-beliefs are systematically skewed. Accordingly, the weak sceptic allows the occasional motive-belief to pick out an action’s true cause—particularly when the action stems from conscious deliberation. But, there will be many situations where it seems to the subject like an action is caused by conscious deliberation, where in fact it stems from an unconscious cause. While we may sometimes get it right, often, what we take to be truthful ascriptions of motives are nothing more than confabulations.
This nonetheless creates a sceptical problem (Scaife 2014, 480). Such a view puts into question whether the processes behind beliefs about our motives satisfy the anti-luck condition. For simplicity, assume a reliabilist version of (C2). In order to satisfy (C2) we need a reliable process connecting our motive-beliefs to the actual causes of our actions (Paul 2012). If such a reliability constraint holds, there will be a level of detachment between our motive-beliefs and the actual causes of our actions such that even a true belief about our motives fails to amount to knowledge.
Now, I think there is ample reason to believe that many weak sceptics have a picture of the mind where the processes generating our motive ascriptions are not reliable. First, the weak sceptics’ emphasis on the systematic disconnect between what we believe about our motives and the actual causes underlying our actions (e.g., conscious thought vs. adaptive unconscious) by itself suggests such a conclusion. If our motive-beliefs are so systematically detached, it’s extremely plausible to think that the mechanism for ascribing motives doesn’t reliably track causal influences on our actions. Following (C2), however, it would need to do so in order for motive-beliefs to amount to knowledge.
Second, many weak sceptics hold that our practice of ascribing motives to ourselves didn’t evolve to trace causes of our actions. Instead, this practice fulfils a narrative function where we create ourselves (Wilson 2002, 207), express our values (Doris 2015), or manage our reputation (Kurzban 2010; Mercier and Sperber 2011, 2017; Simler and Hanson 2018). This again suggests a sceptical attitude. One would feel pressed to come up with alternative functions, only if one also believed that motive-ascriptions do not reliably fulfil their apparent function.
Third, fulfilling any of these alternative functions will often entail failing to accurately report on our motives. For instance, always telling the truth about one’s motivations is terrible advice for anyone seeking high regard among their peers. Further, values can be expressed without articulating actual causes of actions. Of course, it could be that these alternative functions happen to also track one’s real motives. But it’s unclear why we should believe so. Instead, it is much more plausible that more often than not, telling a narrative, managing my reputation, or expressing my values will not latch on to the true causes of my actions. This, too, suggests that weak sceptics take the processes generating motive-ascriptions to be unreliable.
To conclude, even those authors who don’t deny that we can occasionally get it right, hold a view which implies that (C2) isn’t met: ultimately, we’re too unreliable to know our motives.3 Hence, the weak sceptic is a sceptic after all.
In the next section, I will argue against all forms of scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives.
5. Against Scepticism
Scepticism about our ability to know our motives is a costly position. For a start, it’s deeply implausible. According to the sceptic, when you talk to your friends about your true motives behind your choice of career, you are not speaking about what moved you to become a philosopher instead of an investment banker. Instead, you are doing something completely different, such as argumentatively justifying your actions (Mercier and Sperber 2011, 69), expressing your values (Doris 2015, 143ff.), constructing a fictional narrative (Wilson 2002, 15f.; Chater 2018, 4ff., ch. 6), or preserving your status (Kurzban 2010; Simler and Hanson 2018). Following the sceptic, we’d need to radically reconceive our practices of self-reflection.
Second, such a reconception would have far-reaching consequences. Many deeply important aspects of self-knowledge won’t be available anymore. For instance, various forms of morality place great emphasis on the motives for which an action was conducted. Christian and Kantian moral thought holds that an action ought to be performed with good motives. Subjective consequentialism licenses your action as morally good, if your motive involved a rationally warranted belief that your action would maximize utility. If we can’t know our motives, we have—at least on these pictures of morality—no way of learning about the moral character of our actions (Doris 2015).
Another reason for the importance of knowledge of motives is that it is intimately linked to knowledge of one’s values, goals, and character (Tiberius 2002, 159). Such knowledge is important, among other reasons, because it lets you reliably predict your own behaviour and facilitates collaboration with others (Baumeister 2011; Leuenberger 2021). If we can’t know our motives, our self-knowledge is severely limited and we may be unable to predict, control, and explain ourselves.
The fact that a view has radical and far-reaching consequences is no argument against it. However, the stakes associated with a certain view can be relevant for its justification (Stanley 2005). A position as costly as scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives needs extremely good reasons to be convincing. In the remainder of this section, I aim to show that there aren’t any.
5.1. Replication and justification
First, you might try to avoid scepticism by rejecting the evidence it’s based on. Many results from social psychology have failed to replicate (Open Science Collaboration 2015). Likely this also affects the studies discussed above (§3). After all, they predate awareness of the ‘replication crisis’, rely on notoriously small samples, and employ outdated statistical methods. Thus, it seems like there is an easy answer to the sceptic: simply deny that the evidence is any good.
However, to my knowledge, no failures of replication of the cited studies have come forth. Instead, there are multiple papers defending the studies in Nisbett and Wilson (1977) against irreplicability (Guerin and Innes 1981; Sprangers et al. 1987) and the choice-blindness experiments do replicate (Taya et al. 2014; Lachaud et al. 2022). Thus, I will work with the assumption that the presented evidence is to be taken seriously (Bird 2021). Should it turn out to be faulty, even worse for the sceptic. Until then, let’s consider other replies.
In interpreting the evidence, it’s important to note that in some sense, test subjects in Nisbett-and-Wilson-style studies are right. What test subjects fail to do is to accurately report on their action’s causal history. But they still manage to give justifying reasons. Many interpretations of the empirical evidence tread on an equivocation between the two (Keeling 2018, 2021, 324f.; Ganapini 2020; Andreotta 2021; Levy 2022). If being able to justify one’s actions was sufficient for knowledge of motives, the evidence would fail to support scepticism.
However, this would leave us with something unrecognizable as knowledge of one’s motives. As argued in (§1), when the signer comes to know their motives, they learn more than that they can justify their action with appeal to admiration. Claiming that knowing justifying reasons is the same as knowing one’s motives goes against (C1) and must be seen as a cop-out. We need yet another reply to the sceptic.
5.2. The myth of the one true motive
The inference from the psychological evidence to scepticism rests on a mistaken assumption which I call ‘the myth of the one true motive’. Here’s how Donald Davidson (2001, 18) talks about false motive-beliefs:
[Y]ou may err about your reasons, particularly when you have two reasons for an action, one of which pleases you and one which does not. [...] You may be wrong about which motive made you do it.
Of course, Davidson is right in pointing out that we can be wrong about our motives. Yet, the quotation suggests that there is only one motive that ‘made you do it’.4 However, there seems to be no reason to think that an action can only have one cause. What speaks against multiple motives working together to cause an action?
First, you may think it incompatible with how we ordinarily think about causality, i.e., as a relation with exactly two relata. It’s true that we might intuitively adopt a picture of causality where each effect has exactly one cause. But allowing for one and the same effect to have multiple causes is much more adequate in a complex world. Modern scientific practice in biology or economics supports this (Kincaid 1996; Woodward 2000). The causal relationships under analysis there are far more complex than those assumed in a simple ‘billiard-ball’ picture. Indeed, analysing complex causal networks is the bread and butter of modern-day scientists. Therefore, a narrowly mechanistic framework of causality is a bad reason for believing in the myth of the one true motive.
Second, you may believe in the myth for reasons connecting back to the ethical theories mentioned before (§5.1.). Recall the idea that an action’s moral properties are determined by its motives. The myth of the one true motive ensures that as long as your motives are morally definitive, your actions are as well. Clearly, we want to know if our actions are good or bad. For, it seems that our moral worth as agents turns on it. Accepting the myth of the one true motive satisfies a desire to be morally definitive. However, on a realistic outlook many actions are pervaded by morally laudable and blameworthy motives. And so are we as agents. Most of us have no definitive moral character. Instead, we are inherently ambivalent (Velleman 2005; Kurzban 2010; Strohminger et al. 2017).
Thus, I think the myth of the one true motive is a by-product of a naïve notion of causality and a misguided wish for moral definitiveness. If we reject the myth and realize that motives over- and jointly determine actions, this changes how we can interpret the psychological experiments cited above (§3).
5.3. Revisiting the evidence
Consider again a subject in a Nisbett-and-Wilson-style study. They are asked to choose between two alternatives, they make their choice, and say afterwards “I chose this item because it looked the nicest to me.” If we accept the myth of the one true motive, the finding that subjects are reliably influenced by right-side bias rules out the possibility that the motive they articulate played any causal role in their action.
However, if we allow for codetermination between nonrational influences and motives, this inference isn’t legitimate anymore. As Zina Ward and Edouard Machery (2018) argue, intentional motives and subpersonal effects can both causally contribute to our actions. Such causal over- and joint determination puts into question whether the participants in Nisbett-and-Wilson-style studies are really wrong in their motive-ascriptions. It’s true, they failed to track all the influences of relevant choice effects. Yet, that doesn’t mean that the reasons given had no causal bearing on their action. A subject in a study may truthfully utter “I chose this item because it looked the nicest to me” and this may be knowledge of their motives despite them also being significantly influenced by a right-side bias (Andreotta 2021, 4869). Being under the influence of choice effects doesn’t mean you fall short of (C1), nor (C2); there’s not one thing that made you do it (see Figure 2).

Unconscious cause and knowable motive overdetermine (or jointly determine) an action.
Rejecting the myth of the one true motive reveals that the experimental evidence underdetermines whether we should prefer a sceptical interpretation along the lines of Figure 1, where there is no causal connection between motive and action, over a non-sceptical interpretation represented in Figure 2, where there is a causal connection between motive and action.
Of course, it could be that if test subjects were given more time they would actually choose a different alternative or none at all. But even that doesn’t challenge the claim that in the moment of choice the item they chose looked the nicest to them. Without the myth of the one true motive, the hypothesis that their report is truthful is at least as plausible than the hypothesis that they just made up that reason after the fact.5
Following the framework of Wegner and Wheatley, you might argue for an ‘omitted variable’ driving both the motive-ascription and the action and that’s why we can’t regard the motive as causally relevant (see Figure 1). Also here, the rejection of the myth of the one true motive reveals an alternative reading. It could just as well be that the unconscious effect causes the action through the motive (Thrash et al. 2010, 323ff.). To return to the example used before: a right-side bias could make an object look especially appealing and this misleading appearance could trigger in the subjects a motivation to choose said item. On such an interpretation, it’s not the case that the articulated motive and the actual cause for action stand in a reversed causal ordering. It’s rather that the unconscious cause is just ‘further up’ the causal chain than the avowed motive (see Figure 3). In this case, however, there’s no reason to assume that a subject’s utterance of the form “I chose this because it looked the nicest to me” isn’t expressing knowledge of their motives. As David Lewis (1986) argues, for a causal claim to be true it doesn’t need to capture an event’s whole causal history. It would be absurd to expect someone to cite all causes of their action. Accordingly, I can know my motive, even if that motive is itself brought about by an unconscious cause.

Unconscious cause causing the motive which in turn causes the action.
Let’s apply this reasoning to an example given by Wilson (2002, 106f.):
Suppose, for example, we observe a customer in a fast-food restaurant ask for a chicken sandwich, and we ask her why she ordered what she did. She would probably say something like, “Well, I usually order the burger, fries, and shake, but I felt more like a chicken sandwich and unsweetened iced tea today. They taste good and are a little healthier.” These are precisely the thoughts she was thinking before she asked for the sandwich and thus were responsible for what she ordered—a clear case of conscious causality.
Or is it? Suppose that earlier in the day the fast-food customer encountered someone who was quite obese, which primed issues of weight and self-image, which made her more likely to order food with less fat and calories than the burgers, fries, and shake. The customer was aware of part of the reason she ordered what she did—her conscious thoughts preceding her action—but unaware of what triggered these thoughts.
I’m unsure whether Wilson intends this to illustrate that the customer has no access to her real motives. Plausibly, her encounter with the obese person rendered certain facts about the food options especially salient to her. On the basis of these salient features, the customer makes her choice. In that case, there is nothing wrong with her explanation of why she did what she did. The only possible charge would be that it’s incomplete. But all explanations are. Wilson concedes that actions are unlikely to be “pure” and that she is aware of “part of the reason” why she acted (ibid.). My suggestion is that this is enough to know your motives. To ask for more would be—in a lot of cases—asking for too much.
Again, I’m suggesting that the psychological evidence underdetermines whether we should prefer a sceptical interpretation along the lines of Figure 1, where there is no causal connection between motive and action, over a non-sceptical interpretation represented in Figure 3, where there is a causal connection between motive and action. Accordingly, there is no compelling reason to assume that we are unreliable in forming beliefs about our motives. It’s not clear whether participants in such studies really fail to know their motives; we have no grounds to deny that their beliefs meet (C1) or (C2).
To be clear, even if we adopt such a picture, we can read those studies in a way that does support scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives. However, if we reject the myth of the one true motive, a non-sceptical interpretation of the psychological evidence becomes equally plausible. This undermines scepticism without treading on the ambiguity between causal explanations and rational justification. Scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives starts to look unmotivated, especially given its far-reaching consequences.
What about choice-blindness, though? My argument rests on the idea that the empirical studies give us no reason to disregard what subjects avow as part of the causal chain behind their action—either through over- and joint determination, or by referring to a link ‘higher up’ in the chain. Yet, clearly, this reasoning isn’t available when it comes to choice-blindness. There, causal factors and avowed motives must be completely distinct.
I propose to question how much the choice-blindness findings generalize. Bear in mind how manipulative the experimental contexts are: the participants are consciously tricked and fail to track that trickery. Importantly, many ordinary life circumstances are not like that; we are highly unlikely to be manipulated in such a way outside of an experimental setting. It’s not clear to me that we can infer anything about our general abilities to know our motives from the fact that we are tricked in a highly-deceptive environment. Thus, the external validity of the choice-blindness results isn’t obvious (Sullivan-Bisset and Bortolotti 2021).
Still, the studies surveyed here only represent a small subset of the literature. Therefore, I make no claims about other experiments supporting scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives.6 What I’ve argued is that the evidence base for scepticism is smaller than often assumed. The burden of proof is thus on the sceptic to convincingly present evidence for why we should adopt their position. Until that happens, I conclude that scepticism about knowledge of one’s motives ought to be rejected. What the evidence shows is how easily we are manipulated into forming motives on mistaken beliefs (e.g., that some of the alternatives are better than the others). What it doesn’t show is that we have troubles knowing these motives—on any sensible conception of what such knowledge means.7
6. Concluding Remarks
In this paper, I’ve issued a warning against taking certain psychological studies as proof that we can’t know our motives. I’ve shown how costly such a position is and that if we reject the myth of the one true motive, it starts to look unmotivated.
Nonetheless, I don’t want to deny that knowing one’s motives is difficult. Scepticism is partly attractive because knowing your motives is so hard. Many of our motives run unconsciously. Uncovering them is no easy thing to achieve. Moreover, we have a strong desire to present ourselves in a flattering manner, even to ourselves. This desire makes it likely that when we think about our motives, we are engaged in motivated reasoning skewing our self-inquiry (Kurzban 2010; Simler and Hanson 2018; Williams 2020). If we want to know our motives, thus, we need to keep these two factors in mind and their distorting effects at bay.
If knowledge of one’s motive is hard, don’t we fail to meet (C2)? This worry is exacerbated if we note how weak (C1) and (C2) are. On the picture offered here, it’s possible to know your motives even if all you’re reliably picking out is an insignificant cause. You could think that knowing something which matters very little to how you act can’t constitute knowledge of your motives. Therefore, you might be in favour of a further necessary condition:
(C3) A motive-belief which amounts to knowledge picks out a relevant causal factor of an action.
If (C3) is in place, scepticism seems more plausible again. If anything, the evidence shows that the most relevant causes are often hidden from our view; position effects have a much higher predictive power than the motives people can articulate.
I’m not completely convinced by (C3). Perhaps all we can do in trying to know our motives is register factors that are, causally speaking, pretty minor. Still, there might be a lot of value in that. But even if we do add (C3), there are more ways of avoiding scepticism.
First, it’s not clear that difficulty and unreliability are as closely connected. Certain activities—such as climbing a hard mountain route—can be difficult without often provoking failure. Instead, their difficulty is grounded in the amount of effort needed. Knowledge of one’s motives might be hard because of the care it requires, and not because of frequent failure.
Second, even if psychological evidence established the unreliability of one process, this doesn't have to be the only one. In the cited studies the participants were mostly forced to rely on solitary introspection. They had little time and no dialogue partners available. As a result, the methods of self-inquiry they could draw on were severely confined. In real life, however, there are a lot of methods we can use in trying to know our motives. You can talk to your friends, go to therapy, write into your diary, meditate, etc. (Vazire and Mehl 2008; Thrash et al. 2010). Any of these processes are likely to be more reliable than sole introspection under a heavy time constraint.
So, even if we make the conditions for knowledge of one’s motives more demanding, there are good reasons to think that they can be met. In some sense, knowing your motives is a lot like science. Both in science and in introspection, we need to draw on a variety of methods to gather a trustworthy evidence base. Also, we need to take great care in establishing and solidifying theories about different causes and how much they matter. I develop the idea of coming to know one’s motives as a ‘science of the self’ elsewhere (Hubacher Haerle ms.).
Knowledge of your motives is like many valuable things in life—it requires a great deal of effort. With respect to a Kantian obligation for self-knowledge this means that the attack fuelled by recent psychological evidence can be deflected. Fulfilling our duty to know our motives may be quite hard, but it is not impossible.8
REFERENCES
———.
———.
———.
———.
Footnotes
I do this in more detail elsewhere (Hubacher Haerle ms).
Accordingly, I am committed to causalism about action-explanation (see §2). However, this is perfectly compatible with the view that any causal explanation presupposes a rationalizing explanation; we can think of ‘pure rationalizations’ as constraining the space of causal action-explanations (von Wright 1998, 149).
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to further spell out the reasons for why weak sceptics are still sceptics. This argument likely carries over to internalist theories of justification too. Most internalists are committed to take evidence as a means to truth (Kelly 2016, §3) that’s closely connected to conscious experience (Conee and Feldman 2008). It’s questionable whether, on the picture offered by the weak sceptic, what we ordinarily draw on in order to know our motives can be considered evidence in that sense.
While this passage suggests that, the idea that an action can have multiple causes is easily integrated into a Davidsonian picture.
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for asking me to clarify this point.
I do take my argument also to apply to the studies led by David McClelland (Thrash et al. 2010) and Michael Gazzaniga (Wilson 2002, 99ff.; Chater 2018, ch. 6).
It may well be that these findings raise problems for other aspects of self-knowledge, such as first-person authority (Scaife 2014; Levy 2022). However, they don’t attack the possibility of knowing our motives.
I’m indebted to Richard Holton, Jessie Munton, Tatiana Sitnikova, Dan Williams, and an anonymous reviewer for invaluable feedback. Ancestors of this paper have benefitted from comments by Rhea Blem, Demetra Brady, Angela Breitenbach, Michael Müller, Jordan Scott, and Paulina Sliwa. Also, I am thankful to Michał Barcz, Paula Keller, Will Hornett, Joane Marner, Kyle van Oosterum, Cecily Whitely, Aiden Woodcock, and audiences in Cambridge and Vienna for helpful discussion. This research was supported by the Boustany Foundation and the Swiss Study Foundation.