-
PDF
- Split View
-
Views
-
Cite
Cite
Jason Ralph, Jamie Gaskarth, A Pragmatist critique of progressive realism in foreign policy, International Affairs, Volume 101, Issue 2, March 2025, Pages 623–641, https://doi.org/10.1093/ia/iiaf001
- Share Icon Share
Abstract
How might pragmatism inform foreign policy? In the United Kingdom's policy sphere, pragmatism is often conflated with realism to mean either a philosophical acceptance of the way the world is, or a prudential awareness that progressive change is difficult but still possible. David Lammy's advocacy of ‘progressive realism’ as a foreign policy ethos seems to favour the latter; yet, we see two problems with Lammy's formulation for progressive foreign policy. First, shackling pragmatism to realism could result in progressive opportunities being missed. Second, as a means towards (or a check on) progressive ends, realist pragmatism risks assuming the undemocratic position that those ends are given (by western powers) and beyond (multilateral) dialogue. We argue that a policy informed by philosophical Pragmatism avoids these risks because unlike realists (and International Relations realists) these Pragmatists are more aware of the constructed and processual (rather than essential and fixed) nature of social problems. In that awareness they will be: 1) less sceptical and more creative in the pursuit of progress; 2) less inclined to compromise on multilateral practices; and 3) more committed to the democratization of those practices as a method of uncovering and solving practical problems. We apply this three-part definition of ‘progressive Pragmatism’ to two hard cases confronting UK foreign policy: the challenge of global governance in a multipolar system and Russia's aggression against Ukraine. Lammy claims his realism is not ‘cynical’. We argue he can better protect progressivism against realist cynicism if he pairs it with Pragmatism.
What does it mean to be a pragmatist, and how does pragmatism inform foreign policy? These are important questions in the United Kingdom's context due to the recent ‘pragmatic’ turn of both Labour and Conservative politicians in the foreign policy sphere. The background to this move is a sense that history is moving in a different direction from the immediate post-Cold War trajectory. Instead of a future characterized by democratic peace, we are seeing the global renewal of great power competition. UK policy-makers thus see international order as ‘contested and volatile’.1 In his foreword to the Integrated review refresh 2023, then-Prime Minister Rishi Sunak stated that Russia's invasion of Ukraine, and China's more aggressive stance towards its neighbours, were ‘threatening to create a world defined by danger, disorder and division—and an international order more favourable to authoritarianism’.2 In response to this shift, Sunak argued the UK should stand up ‘to our competitors, not with grand rhetoric but with robust pragmatism’.3 Similarly, Labour's then foreign policy spokesperson David Lammy (from 2024 Secretary of State for Foreign, Commonwealth and Development Affairs) argued that the UK's ‘foreign policy must put pragmatism over ideology’,4 and the party's defence spokesperson, John Healey (who became Secretary of State for Defence), asserted that ‘Britain needs a national strategy, which is relentlessly pragmatic’.5
For these individuals, pragmatism boils down to recognizing the limits of British influence and avoiding ideological positions.6 Pragmatism in this sense could be a synonym for philosophical realism, i.e. accepting the way the world is; or a synonym for prudential realism, i.e. accepting that progressive change is difficult but still possible. Lammy has favoured the latter, framing Labour foreign policy as ‘progressive realism’. Here, pragmatism/realism is a means to a progressive end. Indeed, Lammy writes that foreign policy involves ‘using realist means to pursue progressive ends’, including taking ‘pragmatic steps’ to improve relations with other states. He rejects the notion that ‘idealism has no place in foreign policy’ but argues that policy-makers should be ‘realistic about the state of the world and the country's role in it’.7
Our argument as set out in this article is that there are potential problems in the pairing of progressivism and realism (and in the conflation of realism with pragmatism). Firstly, Lammy's pragmatism/realism could become so restraining that it misses progressive opportunities to promote democracy. In other words, by overemphasizing the need for stable relations with increasingly powerful authoritarian regimes, it loses its progressive edge. Secondly, seeing pragmatism/realism as a means towards (or a check on) progressive ends risks assuming the undemocratic position that those ends are given (by western powers) and beyond (multilateral) dialogue. This second danger is of course exposed by longstanding post-colonial critiques that ‘progressivism’ is little more than a revamp of western imperialism.8 We further argue that to avoid these potential problems pragmatism need not, and should not, be conflated with realism. Indeed, when pragmatism—rather than realism—is paired with progressivism it alerts progressive policy-makers to these two risks.
To make this argument we offer a definition of pragmatism that is separate from realism. To do this we draw on philosophical Pragmatism, a way of thinking that emerged in the United States in the late nineteenth century.9 This approach might seem far removed from the UK's foreign policy concerns in the twenty-first century, but it has nonetheless recently influenced British International Relations (IR) theory.10 It is important for a foreign policy audience, we argue, because it helps us understand that pragmatism is not just a statement on the means towards a fixed end, it is a statement about the constitution of those ends. In short, philosophical Pragmatism takes seriously the claim that we live in a culturally diverse, but constantly evolving, global society. That demands a degree of epistemic fallibilism. Particular cultures (and their state representatives) should not assume they know the ideal end-point of history. Those ideals can only command epistemic authority if they emerge from inclusive and deliberative (democratic) dialogue.
This influences foreign policy ends in the following way: unlike realists, who generally take cultural and political pluralism as fixed, and thus argue that the ends of foreign policy should be conservative (i.e. limited to advancing the national interest in the context of international order), Pragmatists see much stronger potential for progress, built on more fluid arrangements of democratic dialogue between a variety of local, national and international communities. This is a vision of inclusive global decision-making infused with a democratic ethos. Put like this, Pragmatism protects progressive politicians against the risks associated with the realist label, because Pragmatism itself is a progressive idea.
To make this argument, we structure the article as follows. The first section demonstrates how pragmatism and realism are often conflated in everyday foreign policy discourse before drawing on philosophical Pragmatism to better define progressive foreign policy in the contemporary age.11 The main point here is that while Pragmatists share the realists' sense of prudence, recognizing the occasional need to compromise with authoritarian regimes to avoid the harmful consequences of ideological conviction, Pragmatists see greater scope for democratic progress, since even apparently fixed aspects like state identities are in a constant process of (re)constitution. Consequently, they are less predisposed than realists to settle for a non-democratic order in the name of an unsatisfactory and false stability.
The second section demonstrates how this Pragmatist commitment to a democratic ethos relates to authoritarian regimes who, because they control the actions of a large proportion of the world's population, are necessarily part of any solution to global problems like climate change. Importantly, Pragmatists are committed to democracy as a means of cultivating global solidarity out of pluralism and channelling power (through multilateral organizations) to solve shared problems. In the current context of challenges to global cooperation, that means a commitment to democratic practices between (as well as within) nations. In foreign policy terms, that involves not just supporting the multilateral institutions of the liberal international order, but also a commitment to democratizing them in ways that cultivate the global public will. In the third and fourth sections we elaborate on how these arguments play out in two ‘hard cases’: responding to Russia's invasion of Ukraine and reforming global governance. We choose these cases as they entail engaging with authoritarian states, through cooperation or conflict, in ways that test the relationship between progressives, realists and Pragmatists.
Pragmatism and realism in foreign policy discourse
In everyday foreign policy discourse, pragmatism is synonymous with a sense of realism. To be pragmatic is to accept the world as it is and to compromise on a vision of the world as one would like it to be. Thus, former British foreign secretary Lord Carrington defined himself as a pragmatist because he found ‘that the gulf between what is theoretically desirable and what is practically attainable is so wide that it is sensible to concentrate almost exclusively upon the latter’.12 The ‘theoretically desirable’ in this sense is often represented in terms of idealistic/realistic binaries. Values that are realistically attainable within a state—such as governance by the rule of law and justice where this is violated—are dismissed as idealistic and beyond the reach of foreign policy. For instance, another former Conservative foreign secretary, Lord Howe, advocated pragmatism because ‘foreign policy is very often not justiceable. Even if it is, justice isn't enforceable’.13
When pragmatism is used as a synonym for instrumentality, this kind of idealistic/realistic binary is also conflated with another binary: that of values/interests. If, for example, we are unable to defend and promote wider values such as justice (or democracy) through our foreign policy, then the only practical thing to do is to promote the national interest. The ‘pragmatic pursuit of the national interest’ is, in this way, set against other more ambitious goals, such as ‘upholding a system of international order’.14 These sentiments resonate with realism as a tradition of thinking in IR, with its emphasis on the survival of states, regardless of their internal make-up, in a morally and politically diverse international society. From George Kennan's devastating critique of First World War Wilsonianism to John Mearsheimer's more recent writings on the ‘delusions’ of liberal ‘dreamers’, realists have attacked policies based on what they see as a misplaced commitment to ideals.15
Our contention is that philosophical Pragmatism leads us to challenge these binaries, particularly definitions of pragmatism that see it as antithetical to the ‘ideological’ influence of democracy on foreign policy. We offer three points to support this argument. Firstly, and at its most basic level, philosophically informed Pragmatism rejects any foreign policy based on philosophical realism—the conservative argument that we should not aim for progress in international relations because tragedy is a persistent fact of international life.16 The philosophical Pragmatism of John Dewey, for instance, emerged from the Darwinian view that the things we see in front of us, and the situations we find ourselves in, have evolved to be that way.17 Pragmatists work, in other words, with a ‘processual’ rather than fixed ontology.18 To hold fixed notions of international relations and political possibility is, in this sense, unrealistic. In fact, doing so signals an ideological (rather than pragmatic) conservatism.
Of course, many realists would reject attempts to portray them as ideologues (and past realists like Hans Morgenthau acknowledged the state system was not eternal).19 However, a conservative predisposition can lead realist politicians to miss the progressive moment—as Henry Kissinger did with the human rights diplomacy of the 1970s.20 A Pragmatist perspective, sensitive to the social processes by which identities, interests and situations are constructed, is more likely to identify the scope for progressive change.21 Dewey's student Sidney Hook captured this when he criticized the apparent ‘heroism’ of the realist who makes the tough decision to compromise on one's own preferred values because of the necessity created by the tragic moment. Unlike realism, Pragmatism can be
more serious, even more heroic … because it does not resign itself to the bare fact of tragedy or take easy ways out at the price of truth …. It does not conceive of tragedy as a preordained doom, but as one in which the plot to some extent depends upon us, so that we become creators of our own tragic history. We cannot then palm off altogether the tragic outcome upon the universe in the same way as we can with a natural disaster.22
This, we argue, is important to guard against the conservative implication of pairing realism with progressivism. Pragmatists would resist the politician's misjudged (or instrumental) invocation of realism as a reason why they cannot support democratic values at the local, national, international and global levels.
The second way philosophical Pragmatism rejects being used as a synonym for realism is its commitment to democracy as a means of problem-solving. As noted, it is common in foreign policy discourse to identify democracy as an end held by western liberal societies. In consequence, realists generally tell us that in a politically and culturally pluralistic world that end is beyond reach; or, at least, its pursuit usually backfires to make things worse. Pragmatism is sensitive to cultural and political pluralism. Since the social processes that construct political morality are bounded, we cannot assume an Archimedean point of moral objectivity, nor should moral philosophy waste its time searching for it.23 But philosophers should be grounded and engaged in improving lived experiences (rather than setting abstract standards); they do that by solving problems through an immanent critique of existing practice. It is here that democracy retains its importance. Democracy is valued as a practical method of uncovering and solving problems, not as an abstract ideology or identity to assert moral hierarchy over another.
This influences foreign policy discourse because it brings in a ‘decentred’ conception of democracy. The well-known realist critique of the liberal internationalist's commitment to ‘democracy promotion’ focuses on democracy as an internal characteristic of certain (western or westernized) states. Pragmatists value democratic practices at that level. They also recognize, however, that a foreign policy that aims to democratize other states is difficult because, as Mearsheimer puts it, nationalism is ‘an enormously powerful political ideology’.24 When liberals come up against that ideology their good intentions backfire. It does not follow, however, that democratic practices are irrelevant to foreign policy when nationalism is a powerful influence. The democratic ethos is still valuable as a method that helps to uncover and solve problems that emerge in relations between nations. Pragmatists thus share the realist's concern that foreign policy ethics be formulated within the context of cultural and political pluralism, but they also argue that should be done by first adopting a democratic sense of fallibilism and reflexivity, and then committing to a process of deliberation.25 That is, states—including western states—should accept the provinciality of their preferred ideological position and should not assume that they alone know how best to govern the world's problems. They need not hide their preferred position, but they should ‘test’ its problem-solving potential in an inclusionary dialogue, the aim of which is to both identify and solve the problems of what Dewey called ‘associated living’ (i.e. problems created by interdependence).26 Here, the willingness to (pragmatically) compromise is fundamental to the inclusive and deliberative (i.e. democratic) process of global problem-solving.27 Pragmatism is thus endogenous to, not a replacement for, democratic practice.
Foreign policy discourse more commonly labels this process ‘multilateralism’. For the Pragmatist, however, multilateralism will not necessarily be progressive if states approach it with a realist attitude that puts an exclusionary conception of the national interest ahead of one that helps solve collective problems. Multilateralism only delivers the progressive goal of identifying and solving the problems of associated living if it can mobilize political will. It maximizes that possibility by being inclusive (i.e. democratic) so that the affected nations and peoples (Deweyan ‘publics’) feel part of the solution.28 Liberals have begun to recognize this, as well as the subsequent need to reform the unwarranted exclusionary hierarchies of the western-led international order, citing a Deweyan form of democracy to support that case.29
A willingness to (pragmatically) participate in and accept the outcomes of deliberative multilateralism resonates too with recent thinking in progressive foreign policy circles. We are cautious about the ‘progressive realist’ label for the reasons noted above. However, Nick Bisley and colleagues' progressive reading of E. H. Carr's realism has some overlap with what we prefer to call progressive Pragmatism. While Bisley and colleagues underplay the importance of democracy as a deliberative practice between states, their emphasis on the ‘redistributive logic’ in Carr's work and progressive aspiration for a more ‘egalitarian, democratic and ecologically sustainable world order’ resonates with philosophical Pragmatism.30 Likewise, Jonathan Gilmore's recent discussion of progressive foreign policy seeks to move away from ‘the primacy of exclusionary and neatly compartmentalized national communities’, the effect of which is to disregard democratization at the interstate level. His emphasis is on a foreign policy of ‘co-production’ between states and non-state actors and wider ‘publics’, which aligns with philosophical Pragmatism's desire for inclusivity in global governance.31
Progressive Pragmatism on the risks and benefits of inclusivity
This leads to a third way, in which the philosophical Pragmatist warns against the conflation of progressivism and realism. Clearly the Pragmatist's focus on practical problem-solving maps on to the use of the term ‘pragmatism’ in everyday foreign policy discourse. Indeed, it chimes with the realist critique of the role ideological conviction plays in international relations. It is better for international relations, the realist would say, if states put ideological differences to one side and concentrate on finding practical solutions to actual problems. It is important to acknowledge at this stage, however, the familiar dilemma in progressive foreign policy thinking that also challenges Pragmatists: how to relate to authoritarian regimes who pursue oppressive policies at home, but nevertheless ‘represent’ (at least in formal legal terms) and ‘mobilize’ (in political terms) significant portions of humanity. Is it not fundamentally anti-democratic, and therefore regressive, to legitimize these regimes by recognizing their place in multilateral forums and (re)distributing power to their benefit? The contradictions to which such questions allude are illustrated, for instance, by the perverse outcomes of elections to the United Nations Human Rights Council (UNHRC), which often see regimes accused of human rights abuses elected to positions designed to hold human rights abusers to account.32 Does not democracy demand that we deny such regimes the social recognition and legitimacy they gain from multilateral practice by excluding them from international organizations? Are proposals that are based around the ‘league of democracies idea’ more progressive?
Progressive Pragmatists, we argue, would recognize the challenge. At the same time, they would see as impractical the desire to purify international arrangements of hypocrisy. Such arrangements can in fact expose hypocrisy in ways that mobilize reflexive and reformed behaviour.33 An approach committed only to working with like-minded democracies can, moreover, be self-defeating. Ostracizing authoritarian regimes does not always improve the lives of ordinary people in authoritarian states. Moreover, global problems cannot be solved by liberal democracies alone. Reconstructing ideological blocs risks reviving civilizational hierarchies, which may provoke nationalist and authoritarian backlashes against progressive agendas.34 A Pragmatist ethos thus focuses on practical ways of promoting progressive values even though they might lead to positions that appear compromised and outcomes that are suboptimal. In this respect, the progressivism of the philosophical Pragmatist resonates with the non-perfectionist ethics and the never-ending task of finding workable solutions to multiple problems.35
There is a danger with this argument, of course. If, instead of accepting the need for creative diplomacy, the Pragmatist resigns themselves to the perversity of the UNHRC, the ‘reality’ of a Russian sphere of influence in eastern Ukraine or the ongoing occurrence of crimes against humanity, and does so because they accept ‘that's just the way the world is’, then at that moment their position not only stops being progressive but also stops being Pragmatist.36 At that point, the Pragmatist becomes a realist. We are not claiming progressive Pragmatism is a comfortable ethos, nor that progress toward a better world is linear. But the non-perfectionist ethic of progressive Pragmatism sees in the uncomfortable situation a reason to reflect rather than give up. It sees the need to reimagine the problem and to rethink strategy.
For example, one reason for the perverse outcomes at the UNHRC is the fact that human rights (as a practice rather than a moral end) is perceived to be less helpful for improving lived experiences in the developing world than the Chinese model of development aid.37 Such an argument would surely cause progressive Pragmatists in the UK and elsewhere to reflect on the wisdom of cutting international aid programmes while simultaneously advocating human rights. As part of that self-reflection, policy-makers need to democratize the deliberative process, which involves including non-state as well as state actors. The encouraging thing about the recent turn to pragmatism/realism in UK foreign policy is that it has shown signs of moves in that very direction. Former UK Foreign Secretary James Cleverly, for instance, acknowledged that ‘the voice of the poor is not always being heard. Even on matters that directly concern them.’38 Similarly, Lammy argued that the UK had to ‘once again become a leader in development’ by building ‘long-term win–win partnerships’ based on trade ‘rather than following an outdated model of [aid-based] patronage’.39 The main point here, however, is that Pragmatism is less predisposed than realism to drop a progressive commitment to democracy. This is because, as noted above, while realists see democracy as a moral value internal to states, pragmatists view democratic practices (i.e. inclusion and deliberation at all levels) as effective forms of problem solving that are not confined to state boundaries. Specific situations may demand ‘invidious choices’ be made.40 But in that context the Pragmatist will be committed to creatively ‘squaring the circle’ of promoting democracy at all levels of human interaction.
Before illustrating these differences between progressive Pragmatism and progressive realism with two ‘hard cases’ for British foreign policy, it is worth recapping the three main points introduced in the first part of the article. Firstly, philosophical Pragmatism rejects foreign policy based on philosophical realism, or the conservative argument that we should not aim for progress in international relations because tragedy is a persistent fact of international life. By pairing his realism with progressivism, Lammy is clearly rejecting its conservative implications. We argue, however, that Pragmatism provides a better basis for progressive foreign policy, being grounded in empirical reality but seeing this as in constant flux and so open to positive change. It is this openness to change that makes it resistant to a needless conservativism.41
Secondly, Pragmatism is progressive because it sees in democratic practices the means to resolve the problems that emerge from associated living at all levels of social interaction. In this respect, it remains progressive while sharing the realist's rejection of moralism. Again, Lammy's realism seemingly rejects moralism; it is willing to include authoritarian regimes in multilateral processes to solve global problems. We argue, however, that by pairing progressivism with Pragmatism, British foreign policy would be more conscious of the benefits of a reflexive, inclusionary and deliberative (i.e. democratic) multilateralism. That guards against the kind of conservative realism that legitimizes unwarranted international hierarchies.
Thirdly, the Pragmatist commitment to democratic practice operates at all levels of human interaction. Democratizing multilateral forums by including marginalized (including non-democratic) states helps mobilize international solidarity in the face of global problems, but that can itself be exclusionary of publics not represented by the states system. Again, we argue that by pairing this kind of progressivism with Pragmatism, British foreign policy can guard against the realist's state-centric (and elitist) approach to multilateral problem-solving. To illustrate how these three points, which in our view constitute progressive Pragmatism, help guide British foreign policy, we apply them to policy in two hard cases: responding to Russia's invasion of Ukraine, and global governance in the face of climate change.
Progressive Pragmatism and managing conflict
Russia's full-scale invasion of Ukraine in 2022, following military intervention in 2014 and years of subversion, has resulted in humanitarian, economic and energy crises, impinged on sovereignty, threatened European security, brought forth alleged acts of genocide and atrocities against civilians, and heightened the risk of nuclear war with regular threats of nuclear retaliation. At stake were important progressive norms like national self-determination, democracy, international law, peace and human rights. This was a key test of British foreign policy, and in this case we believe the UK's response was consistent with progressive Pragmatism—with some caveats. These caveats are important when thinking about the way in which the conflict is fought and how it will be concluded, for these are considerations that will have an impact on the strength and sustainability of the peace going forward.
To recall, the UK laid the groundwork for supporting Ukrainian self-defence from 2015 via Operation Orbital, which provided training for more than 22,000 troops.42 As the emerging intelligence picture in 2021/22 suggested Russia intended to intervene en masse, UK and US policy-makers sought to deter Russia by engaging in ‘prebuttal’; releasing intelligence on Russia's plans, undermining Russian disinformation efforts and giving notice of the consequences of invasion.43 Once the intervention launched on 24 February 2022, the UK was in the vanguard of supplying Ukraine with the means for its defence. It provided 5,000 next-generation light anti-tank weapons, vital in repelling the initial assault.44 The UK was the first state to commit to supplying main battle tanks when it promised 14 Challenger 2 tanks, on 14 January 2023—prompting allies such as Germany and the United States to make their own contributions. It pledged in May 2023 to send Ukraine Storm Shadow cruise missiles,45 enabling dramatic and often successful attacks on strategic targets such as the Black Sea fleet, Kerch bridge and command posts across the various fronts. Meanwhile, between June 2022 and November 2023 the UK trained 50,000 Ukrainian troops as part of the ongoing UK-led Operation Interflex.46
Providing this level of assistance was, we argue, consistent with a progressive Pragmatist foreign policy.47 Defending Ukrainian self-determination and democracy are progressive aims—provided they reflect the desires of the Ukrainian people.48 It was not certain prior to the invasion that Ukraine would have the will to resist, but groundwork like Operation Orbital provided the means. Once Ukraine's population demonstrated that will, it made sense for the UK to meet its obligations under the Budapest memorandum (1994) and assist its government. The question then became how to do so without risking the escalation of violence both horizontally (to other parts of Europe, especially NATO members) and vertically (to the use of nuclear weapons). Gradually increasing support was a logical strategy to test Russian reactions and manage that risk—aligning with the experimental approach of Pragmatism.
The threat of escalation was real, and here a Pragmatist concern for managing the consequences of power overlapped with the realist's ethic of prudence. Russian President Vladimir Putin had issued nuclear threats prior to February 2022, and in September he suggested that Russia would ‘use all the means at our disposal’ to defend conquered territories.49 Thus, there was a non-trivial risk of nuclear escalation that had to be factored into the UK's response. UK policy was prudent, as it navigated a Pragmatic course between the extremes of direct confrontation with Russia or acquiescence in aggression. In doing so, it also maintained cross-party support at home.
It did not have to be that way. Significant voices were advocating different paths. For example, immediately following the invasion Tobias Ellwood, the chair of the House of Commons defence select committee, called on NATO to enforce a no-fly zone in support of Ukrainian defensive action.50 Both the defence of a sovereign state under international law and the responsibility to protect civilians from atrocity crimes were cited as justification for taking such an action.51 Although the aims of this policy could be seen as progressive (to defend Ukrainian self-determination and international law, as well as democratic and humanitarian values), in practice, no-fly zones usually require the elimination of ground-to-air missile defences, the establishment of air dominance and continuous policing of the air space.52 Thus, it would likely have involved direct confrontation between the UK and Russian forces (with attendant risks of war between nuclear powers). For this reason, we as Pragmatists consider this to be an imprudent course of action.
The argument that the UK and NATO should move one step closer to nuclear exchange with Russia in the name of humanitarian intervention strikes us as odd.53 We accept, however, that those seeking to defend democracy in Ukraine might disagree while still claiming to be Pragmatic. The issue is a disagreement on empirics rather than ethos. Both sides might be exercising judgement in context, and some might have believed direct military exchanges between NATO and Russia would not risk escalation to a nuclear level. There is scope within a shared ethos for disagreement on empirical matters and political judgement: after all, the original philosophical Pragmatists who entered public debate on the use of force reached different positions.54 We would add, however, that what keeps the progressive a Pragmatist (and not an ideologue) is a determination to examine the predispositions—e.g. militarist, or liberal interventionist—they bring to the deliberative process of assessing consequences. What Dewey called ‘conscientious reflection’ helps decision-makers avoid being unduly influenced by inappropriate habits, emotions, norms or narratives, and facilitates deliberation in the public interest.55 In that sense, progressive Pragmatism forestalls the realist critique that progressive foreign policy inevitably elides into liberal internationalism.56
Here our progressive Pragmatist position aligns with Lammy's progressive realism. Lammy explicitly rejects Blairite ‘liberal interventionism’ while arguing that ‘the United Kingdom must continue supporting Ukraine’.57 Realism, however, could pull British foreign policy in a different direction. For well-known realist voices like Mearsheimer, the ‘taproot of the trouble’, was less Russian imperialism than it was ‘a larger [western] strategy to move Ukraine out of Russia's orbit and integrate it into the West’.58 From this perspective, the alleged mistakes that were made prior to 2014—including the West's backing of the pro-democracy movement in Ukraine—were repeated prior to 2022.59 Increased military cooperation between the West and Ukraine, and NATO's June 2021 recommitment to the 2008 Bucharest Declaration, which stated that Ukraine would become a member of the alliance, are all cited as western incitements.60 Since Russia is always going to be more committed to this issue, and more capable of bringing force to bear in its neighbourhood than outside powers, western powers should have accepted a Russian sphere of influence—or so the argument goes.
Despite some characterizations, Mearsheimer's realism is other-regarding. He argues that the war has been an ‘unmitigated disaster’ for Ukrainians. Their fate, which is to suffer war or live peacefully under Russian domination, is an example of what Stephen Walt calls the ‘enduring relevance’ of tragic realism.61 This kind of realism, however, is fundamentally at odds with our three-point definition of progressive Pragmatism. Firstly, the implication that one should accept a Russian sphere of influence as a fact of life needlessly restricts the policy options that were (and are) available to defend Ukrainian self-determination and democracy.62 Secondly, this particular definition of (neo-)realism tends to impose abstract language (e.g. ‘orbit’) in ways that silence the lived experience of ‘publics’—e.g. the Ukrainian people—who are necessarily part of any solution to the problems of European insecurity. In this respect, the ‘peace’ proposed by this kind of realism is neither democratic (it is in fact elitist) nor is it stable.63 Nor is it realistic in a practical sense, since it overlooks the negative consequences of a great power peace which rewards aggression while denying self-determination.64 To be sure, nothing in a progressive Pragmatist ethos rules out a negotiated settlement to the Ukraine conflict if the circumstances are right. Progressive Pragmatists, however, would be concerned if, in the name of realism (or opportunity costs), UK foreign policy imposed a peace on the Ukrainian people and their government.65 Lammy's progressive realism does not suggest that, but our point is that by attaching progressive policies to ‘realism’—rather than ‘Pragmatism’—UK policy is more likely to take that turn.
A final point follows on from our three-part definition of progressive Pragmatism. While the focus of Lammy's progressive realism is understandably the defence of Ukrainian democracy, progressive Pragmatism extends our thinking beyond this to question how a strategy for sustainable peace might tackle the root cause of European insecurity. Whether that cause lies in Russian insecurity or Russian imperialism, both of these have been socially constructed through interactions with the western ‘Other’.66 How that Other defends Ukrainian democracy—and defend Ukrainian democracy it should—will influence the prospect of reintegrating a future Russia into a more stable European security community. It might seem idealistic, utopian even, to consider a future where Russia is integrated into such a community.67 But then the 1970s peace and democracy movements, working under the cover of superpower detente, were also dismissed as utopian when they asserted to heads of state that their Cold War practices were anachronistic in the context of a growing cosmopolitan consciousness. That was until their ideas of ‘common security’ took root in a Russian elite that was looking to recover from governance failures and a more democratic civil society began to emerge.68 That possibility—however remote it might be, given the current imperialist character of the Russian state—challenges progressive Pragmatists in search of better security practice. Progressive processual interaction in this instance involves opposing Russian imperialism while ‘esteeming’ (or ontologically securing) those aspects of the Russian Self that recognize the Ukrainian Self.69 It involves, in other words, supporting everyday relational work to rebuild transnational solidarities across a Europe that includes a future Russia.70 Again, our point here is that tragic realism does not even think in these terms. Its elitist and state-centric conception of peace might for that reason lead progressives to forget this political possibility. That is why we argue Pragmatism is a better partner than realism for foreign policy progressives.
Progressive Pragmatism and global governance
Multilateralism has been the mainstay of progressive foreign policy in the UK.71 It is also valued by those who draw foreign policy guidance from philosophical Pragmatism. This is because, as we noted above, multilateralism expands the community of inquiry, helping to discover the problems that emerge from associated living on a global scale and to mobilize the political solidarity that is necessary to solve them. In this way, the UN is still valued as the international forum that best approximates, at least in scope, a global public. The problem is that the UN is imbued with state hierarchies operating to protect the special interests of some at the expense of others. Hierarchy is not necessarily inconsistent with the idea of the public interest. There is, however, a profound sense that the permanent members of the UN Security Council (UNSC), charged with a responsibility for international peace and security, do not have the power to meet that challenge—or that they have the power, but are acting irresponsibly.
This is the problem (and opportunity) of growing multipolarity in the face of mounting global challenges. The rise of China and India, along with the growing significance of middle powers like Indonesia, Turkey, Brazil, South Korea, Mexico and Japan, is decentring power from its traditional European concentration; and yet three of the five permanent members of the UNSC are located in Europe, and these three play an extensive role in the Council's working practices.72 New and emerging powers are elected to the UNSC, but the two-year term limit is restrictive. The progressive Pragmatist response should be to commit to UNSC reform as a way of better aligning that institution with this new distribution of power.
Interestingly, Lammy's realism seems to have restrained the progressive approach to this issue. The UN does not feature in his ‘case’ for progressive realism. That stands in stark contrast to the Pragmatism of his Conservative predecessor, James Cleverly, who stated the UK ‘wants to welcome Brazil, India, Japan and Germany as permanent members of the UN Security Council, alongside permanent African representation’.73 Rather, Lammy's focus for reform lies on watering down the veto of permanent members in a way that is clearly directed at Russia.74
Despite its place in progressive (if not realist) hearts, however, Pragmatism is not ideological about the UN's place in global governance. Global governance is adapting via the expansion of global clubs and shifting agendas and leadership. This has an impact on global responses, which may cause unease for progressives, but it also opens new modes of addressing shared challenges. For instance, India's hosting of the G20 in 2023 demonstrated its emergence as a more powerful actor with its own priorities. The set of watered-down ‘generalized principles’ proposed in the G20's statement on the situation in Ukraine was disappointing, relative to the need to condemn and defeat Russian aggression (see above).75 Yet the stress on development, through green financing and digital public infrastructure, showed how new leadership can lead to innovation and policies that reflect a wider set of needs. 76 The inclusion of the African Union also bolstered the G20's claim to represent a range of actors in the global economy.
A progressive Pragmatist foreign policy can thus be open-minded in its approach to global governance and assess each forum in terms of its problem-solving value. That said, there are important considerations informing such judgements. The ‘minilateralism’ of diplomatic clubs may make problem-solving appear easier, but that could be a false benefit if these arrangements do not see the problem in its entirety. Minilateralism was defined by Moisés Naim as ‘the smallest possible number of countries needed to have the largest possible impact on solving a particular problem’. Naim calculated that, in climate governance, the ‘magic number’ was 20, because the world's top 20 carbon polluters account for around 75 per cent of global emissions.77 The problem, as Robyn Eckersley noted, was that the obstacles to a comprehensive climate agreement lay within the group of major emitters. In that sense, excluding the lower-emitting states would do little to address the problem (and would reduce political pressure to find a solution from the broader group of those adversely affected).78
How does this relate to Lammy's progressive realism? Lammy's realism involves ‘the pursuit of ideals without delusions about what is achievable’.79 Such an approach might lead to a preference for minilateral arrangements, because they are more likely to ‘achieve’ consensus than inclusionary multilateral arrangements. The difficulties that Eckersley identifies plague this kind of realism, however. By excluding those affected by a problem in order to achieve consensus, it in fact does not even recognize the problem it is meant to be solving. If Naim's definition was applied to climate governance, for example, the concerns of small island states would be excluded and both ‘the problem’ and ‘the solution’ would be constituted in ways that could hardly be described as progressive. A progressive Pragmatist foreign policy would take this critique of diplomatic clubs seriously and guard against it in a way progressive realism might not. As noted in our three-point definition of progressive Pragmatism, it would stress the value of democratizing multilateral governance so that ‘publics’ (i.e. those affected by a practice such as carbon emissions) are included in the processes that constitute the problem and the solution. The critique applies equally to those proposals to reform the G7 into a D10 of ‘leading democracies’ and to expand the BRICS grouping80 into an anti-liberal club. It risks defining governance in ideological terms, rather than its political usefulness in addressing global challenges.81
Of course, the UN, at least through its Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC) remains the centrepiece of global climate governance. But here too a progressive Pragmatist foreign policy would aim to reform the exclusionary hierarchies that stand in the way of problem-solving action. The hope of the UNFCCC is that the ‘pledge and review’ process of its annual Conference of the Parties (COP) ratchets up state ambition to slow the rate of global warming. The issue, well illustrated at COP26, which was held in Glasgow in 2021, is how private interests are represented at the COP: with a clear imbalance of power working against public interests. For example, the refusal at Glasgow to eliminate fossil fuel subsidies, which amounted to US$5.9 trillion in 2020, was linked to the presence of the fossil fuel industry at the conference.82 Indeed, it was reported that not only did this industry have the largest delegation at the summit, but it was ‘larger than the combined total of the eight delegations from the countries worst affected by climate change in the past 20 years’.83 In that context, inclusive multilateralism among states is not going to meet the challenge of climate change. This is because states are themselves influenced by special interests bent on defending current (but unsustainable) practices.
The progressive Pragmatist answer to the problem is not to abandon inclusive multilateralism, but to democratize it. In this instance, a progressive Pragmatist foreign policy would seek to democratize the COP by encouraging equal participation from renewable energy suppliers; or by forming alliances with the countries worst affected by climate change to balance the power of the fossil fuel industry. Unfortunately, recent UK foreign policy has taken a regressive step in this regard. Delays in phasing out combustion engine vehicles, the lifting of rules to improve energy efficiency and a slower transition to lower-emission heat pumps led Parliament's Climate Change Committee to doubt the UK's ability to meet its pledges.84 That weakens the UK's position as a leader in the COP process. It is difficult to shame states for not committing to tackle the problem when they can reasonably dismiss those efforts as hypocrisy. This also points to another problem. Both the main parties argued prior to the 2024 general election that UK governments will not address the climate change challenge if they do not take the electorate with them, but here again the progressive Pragmatist answer is more democracy rather than ‘realistic’ compromise.85 Instead of dividing publics by framing the issue in terms of another front in a generational culture war, collective solidarity and purpose can be forged through inclusive and deliberative practices, perhaps following Gilmore's model of citizen assemblies, allowing non-elite publics to contribute to discussion.86
Conclusion
Our aim in this article has been to develop a Pragmatist foreign policy ethos. This is difficult because of the way pragmatism (with a lower case p) is understood in everyday foreign policy discourse. It is generally conflated with being realistic about one's influence and prudently tailoring one's ends to fit available means. In that respect, pragmatism is often used interchangeably with realism and the ethic of consequence (rather than conviction) it holds in relation to power. We noted in this context how this definition of pragmatism has informed recent foreign policy discourse, not least the articulation of progressive realism by the current UK foreign secretary, David Lammy. 87 Our concern with this marriage of progressive goals and realism was twofold: that the latter could in practice influence policy-makers too strongly, so that they miss progressive opportunities as and when they arise; and secondly, because realism is a means to a progressive end, policy-makers may assume that those ends are given and not subjects for democratic discussion. One can argue that, as foreign secretary, Lammy has steered policy in a progressive direction. Dropping UK objections to International Criminal Court involvement in the Gaza situation and suspending some arms export licences to Israel can be cited to support this claim.88 That does not mean, however, that the risks we point to are not real.
To mitigate these risks, we have argued that a progressive foreign policy is better paired with the guidance that emerges from philosophical Pragmatism. This is for three reasons. Unlike realists, Pragmatists are more aware of the constructed and processual (rather than essential and fixed) nature of social problems. In that awareness, they will be 1) less sceptical and more creative in the pursuit of progress; 2) less inclined to compromise on multilateral practices, and 3) more committed to the democratization of those practices as a method of uncovering and solving practical problems. Lammy's realism appears on paper to be conscious of all this. After all, he writes that ‘realism without a sense of progress can become cynical and tactical’.89 Indeed, our hope is that UK foreign policy does not adopt the realist's cynicism towards progress. Our point, however, is that Lammy might better protect progressivism against the conservative pull of realism if he paired it with Pragmatism.
Footnotes
HM Government, Ministry of Defence, Defence in a competitive age, CP 411 (London: The Stationery Office, 2021), https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/defence-in-a-competitive-age; Ministry of Defence, Defence's response to a more contested and volatile world, CP 901 (London: The Stationery Office, 2023), https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/defence-command-paper-2023-defences-response-to-a-more-contested-and-volatile-world. (Unless otherwise noted at point of citation, all URLs cited in this article were accessible on 11 Dec. 2024.)
HM Government, Cabinet Office, Integrated review refresh 2023: responding to a more contested and volatile world, CP 811 (London: The Stationery Office, 2023), https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/integrated-review-refresh-2023-responding-to-a-more-contested-and-volatile-world.
HM Government, Prime Minister's Office, The Rt Hon. Rishi Sunak MP, ‘PM speech to the Lord Mayor's Banquet: 28 November 2022’, 2022, https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/pm-speech-to-the-lord-mayors-banquet-28-november-2022.
David Lammy, Britain reconnected: a foreign policy for security and prosperity at home (London: Fabian Society, 2023), p. 14.
Rt Hon. John Healey MP, ‘Healey: “Britain needs a national strategy which is relentlessly pragmatic”’, speech at the Royal United Services Institute, 7 Feb. 2023, https://labourlist.org/2023/02/healey-britain-needs-a-national-strategy-which-is-relentlessly-pragmatic.
Healey, ‘Britain needs a national strategy’; see also Lammy, Britain reconnected.
David Lammy, ‘The case for progressive realism: why Britain must chart a new global course’, Foreign Affairs, May/June 2024, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/united-kingdom/case-progressive-realism-david-lammy. Lammy uses the term ‘realism’ to suggest empiricism and prudence, rather than any formal connection with realist International Relations theory. In doing so, Lammy echoes Nick Bisley et al., ‘For a progressive realism: Australian foreign policy in the 21st century’, Australian Journal of International Affairs 76: 2, 2022, pp. 138–60 at p. 141, https://doi.org/10.1080/10357718.2022.2051428. For a criticism that Lammy's realism lacks a strategy for achieving progressive ends, see Seán Molloy, ‘Opinion—Labour's embrace of realism: progressive or problematic?’, E-International Relations, 2 May 2024, https://www.e-ir.info/2024/05/02/opinion-labours-embrace-of-realism-progressive-or-problematic.
Ratna Kapur, ‘Human rights in the 21st century: taking a walk on the dark side’, Sydney Law Review 48: 4, 2006, pp. 665–87, https://classic.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/SydLawRw/2006/29.html.
We use the upper-case Pragmatism to denote the philosophical school of thought.
Despite its American origins, this brand of philosophical Pragmatism has heavily influenced British International Relations theorizing. See Chris Brown, Practical judgement in international political theory: selected essays (Abingdon and New York: Routledge, 2010); Molly Cochran, Normative theory in International Relations: a pragmatic approach (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press 1999); Joe Hoover, Reconstructing human rights: a pragmatist and pluralist inquiry into global ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2016); Jason Ralph, On global learning: pragmatic constructivism, international practice and the challenge of global governance (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press 2023).
On the common confusion of everyday and philosophical Pragmatism, see Carol Nicholson, ‘Education and the pragmatic temperament’, in Alan Malachowski, ed., The Cambridge companion to pragmatism (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2013), pp. 263–5. On the use of philosophical Pragmatism in foreign policy studies, see David Milne, ‘Pragmatism or what? The future of US foreign policy’, International Affairs 88: 5, 2021, pp. 935–51, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-2346.2012.01112.x; Shane J. Ralston, ‘Obama's pragmatism in international affairs’, Contemporary Pragmatism 8: 2, 2011, pp. 81–98, https://doi.org/10.1163/18758185-90000203; Ulrich Franke and Gunther Hellmann, ‘American pragmatism in foreign policy analysis’, in Oxford research encyclopedia of politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017); Ana E. Juncos, ‘Resilience as the new EU foreign policy paradigm: a pragmatist turn?’, European Security 26: 1, 2017, pp. 1–18, https://doi.org/10.1080/09662839.2016.1247809.
As cited in John Coles, Making foreign policy: a certain idea of Britain (London: John Murray, 2000), p. 48. Foreign policy studies using the term ‘pragmatism’ in similar ways include: Manjari Chatterjee Miller and Kate Sullivan de Estrada, ‘Pragmatism in Indian foreign policy: how ideas constrain Modi’, International Affairs 93: 1, 2017, pp. 27–49, https://doi.org/10.1093/ia/iiw001; Ludmilla Selezneva, ‘Post-Soviet Russian foreign policy: between doctrine and pragmatism’, European Security 11: 4, 2002, pp. 10–28, https://doi.org/10.1080/09662830208407545.
Interview with author, London, 10 May 2006.
Olivia O'Sullivan and Bronwen Maddox, Three foreign policy priorities for the next UK government: a case for realistic ambition (London: Royal Institute of International Affairs, 2024), https://doi.org/10.55317/9781784136062.
George F. Kennan, American diplomacy, 1900–1950 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951); John J. Mearsheimer, The great delusion: liberal dreams and international realities (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2018). See also Patrick Porter, The false promise of liberal order: nostalgia, delusion and the rise of Trump (Cambridge, UK: Polity, 2020); Stephen M. Walt, The hell of good intentions: America's foreign policy elite and the decline of US primacy (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2018).
Ralph, On global learning, pp. 103–27. On tragedy as a persistent fact of international life, see John J. Mearsheimer, The tragedy of great power politics (New York: W. W. Norton, 2001); Richard Ned Lebow, The tragic vision of politics: ethics, interests, and orders (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
John Dewey, The influence of Darwin on philosophy, and other essays in contemporary thought [1910] (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1965), pp. 1–19.
Emanuel Adler, World ordering: a social theory of cognitive evolution (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press 2019).
Seán Molloy, The hidden history of realism: a genealogy of power politics (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006).
Barbara Keys, ‘Congress, Kissinger, and the origins of human rights diplomacy’, Diplomatic History 34: 5, 2010, pp. 823–51, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-7709.2010.00897.x.
Ralph, On global learning, pp. 121–6.
Sidney Hook, ‘Pragmatism and the tragic sense of life’, Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association 33: 1959–60, pp. 5–26 at pp. 20–21, https://doi.org/10.2307/3129513.
John Dewey, The quest for certainty: a study of the relation of knowledge and action (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1929); John Dewey, Reconstruction in philosophy [1920] (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1948).
Mearsheimer, The great delusion, p. 3.
Ralph, On global learning, pp. 150–3.
John Dewey, Democracy and education: an introduction to the philosophy of education (New York: Macmillan, 1916).
Ralph, On global learning, pp. 150–3.
John Dewey, The public and its problems (New York: Henry Holt and Co., 1927).
‘The liberal international project has travelled from the eighteenth century to our own time through repeated crises, upheavals, disasters and breakdowns—almost all of them worse than those appearing today. Indeed, it might be useful to think about liberal international order the way John Dewey thought about democracy—as a framework for coping with the inevitable problems of modern society’: G. John Ikenberry, ‘The end of liberal international order?’, International Affairs 94: 1, 2018, pp. 7–23, https://doi.org/10.1093/ia/iix241; see also G. John Ikenberry, A world safe for democracy: liberal internationalism and the crises of global order (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2020).
Nick Bisley et al., ‘For a progressive realism’. See also Paul Howe, ‘The Utopian realism of E. H. Carr’, Review of International Studies 20: 3, 1994, pp. 277–97, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0260210500118078; Molloy, The hidden history of realism, pp. 51–74; Molloy, ‘Opinion—Labour's embrace of realism: progressive or problematic?’.
Jonathan Gilmore, ‘Conceptualizing good global statehood: progressive foreign policy after the populist moment’, International Theory 15: 1, 2023, pp. 79–105 at p. 96, https://doi.org/10.1017/S1752971922000057; see also Roberto Frega, ‘Pragmatism and democracy in a global world’, Review of International Studies 43: 4, 2017, pp. 720–41, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0260210517000080.
Micah McCartney, ‘China remains on UN Human Rights Council despite opposition’, Newsweek, 11 Oct. 2023, https://www.newsweek.com/china-un-human-rights-council-election-1833296.
Thomas Risse, Stephen C. Ropp and Kathryn Sikkink, eds, The power of human rights: international norms and domestic change (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999); Thomas Risse, Stephen C. Ropp and Kathryn Sikkink, eds, The persistent power of human rights: from commitment to compliance (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2013).
Jack Snyder, Human rights for pragmatists: social power in modern times (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2022).
Arnold Wolfers defines non-perfectionist ethics as when we ‘make the best moral choice that circumstances permit’, Discord and collaboration: essays on international politics (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1962), p. 50.
Van Jackson, ‘Left of liberal internationalism: grand strategies within progressive foreign policy thought’, Security Studies 31: 4, 2022, pp. 553–92 at pp. 579–80, https://doi.org/10.1080/09636412.2022.2132874.
Yu-Jie Chen, ‘China's challenge to the international human rights regime’, NYU Journal of International Law and Politics, vol. 51, 2019, pp. 1179–222, https://nyujilp.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/09/NYI403.pdf.
HM Government, Foreign, Commonwealth & Development Office and Rt Hon. James Cleverly MP, ‘Multilateral reform: Foreign Secretary's speech at Chatham House London Conference 2023’, 29 June 2023, https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/multilateral-reform-foreign-secretarys-speech-29-june-2023.
Lammy, ‘The case for progressive realism’.
Molloy, ‘Opinion—Labour's embrace of realism’.
Jackson, ‘Left of liberal internationalism’, p. 592.
HM Government, Prime Minister's Office and Rt Hon. Boris Johnson MP, ‘UK to offer major training programme for Ukrainian forces as Prime Minister hails their victorious determination’, 17 June 2022, https://www.gov.uk/government/news/uk-to-offer-major-training-programme-for-ukrainian-forces-as-prime-minister-hails-their-victorious-determination.
Dan Lomas, ‘Ukraine and intelligence prebuttal: a quick postmortem’, RUSI blog, 24 Feb. 2022, https://rusi.org/explore-our-research/publications/commentary/ukraine-and-intelligence-prebuttal-quick-post-mortem.
David Brown and Tural Ahmedzade, ‘What weapons are being given to Ukraine by the UK?’, BBC News, 15 May 2023, https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-europe-61482305.
Timothy Wright, ‘UK to supply Storm Shadow missile to Ukraine’, International Institute for Strategic Studies, 16 May 2023, https://www.iiss.org/online-analysis/online-analysis/2023/05/uk-to-supply-storm-shadow-missile-to-ukraine.
HM Government, Ministry of Defence, Rt Hon. Grant Shapps MP and Rt Hon. Rishi Sunak MP, ‘30,000 Ukrainian recruits trained in largest UK military training effort since Second World War’, 10 Nov. 2023, https://www.gov.uk/government/news/30000-ukrainian-recruits-trained-in-largest-uk-military-training-effort-since-second-world-war.
See also Megan A. Stewart, Jonathan B. Petkun and Mara R. Revkin, ‘The progressive case for American power’, Foreign Affairs, July/August 2024, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/united-states/progressive-case-american-power.
John Stuart Mill, ‘A few words on non-intervention’ [1859], New England Review 27: 3, 2006: pp. 252–64 at p. 262.
Max Seddon, ‘Why Vladimir Putin toned down his nuclear rhetoric’, Financial Times, 1 Nov. 2023, https://www.ft.com/content/d98446ac-b56e-4f1d-bfa9-ebaed4e26884.
Harry Lambert, ‘Tobias Ellwood: The UK should support a no-fly zone over Ukraine’, New Statesman, 25 Feb. 2022, https://www.newstatesman.com/politics/uk-politics/2022/02/tobias-ellwood-the-uk-must-support-a-no-fly-zone-over-ukraine.
For calls for a no-fly zone in Canada, see Nick Boisvert and Brennan MacDonald, ‘Ukraine's former president calls for NATO no-fly zone, says country is “fighting for Canada”’, CBC News, 3 March 2022, https://www.cbc.ca/news/politics/poroshenko-no-fly-zone-1.6370760. In the UK, see Dan Sabbagh and Rowena Mason, ‘Tory MP says Ben Wallace is defeatist in ruling out Ukraine no-fly zone’, Guardian, 2 March 2022, https://www.theguardian.com/politics/2022/mar/02/uk-defence-secretary-ukraine-russia-no-fly-zone-ben-wallace. In the US, see Jordan Williams and Brett Samuels, ‘Debate over Ukraine no-fly zone heats up’, The Hill, 3 April 2022, https://thehill.com/policy/defense/596942-why-the-us-and-nato-refuse-to-declare-a-no-fly-zone-for-ukraine.
Stephen Losey, ‘Here's why a no-fly zone over Ukraine is off the table’, Defense News, 1 March 2022, https://www.defensenews.com/air/2022/03/01/heres-why-a-no-fly-zone-over-ukraine-is-off-the-table.
Jason Ralph, ‘Ukraine and the Responsibility to Protect: the consequences for the vulnerable (and the not yet vulnerable) should be front and centre of our reasoning’, European Centre for the Responsibility to Protect, 8 March 2022, https://ecr2p.leeds.ac.uk/ukraine-and-the-responsibility-to-protect-the-consequences-for-the-vulnerable-and-the-not-yet-vulnerable-should-be-front-and-centre-of-our-reasoning.
For instance, the classical American philosophical Pragmatists John Dewey and Jane Addams would both be described as progressive, but they differed on the policy question of US entry into World War I. See Molly Cochran and Cornelia Navari, eds, Progressivism and US foreign policy between the world wars (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2017); Ralph, On global learning, pp. 23–6.
Ralph, On global learning, pp. 86–97. On the influence of emotions on western policy-making, see Rita Floyd and Mark Webber, ‘Making amends: emotions and the western response to Russia's invasion of Ukraine’, International Affairs 100: 3, 2024, pp. 1149–69, https://doi.org/10.1093/ia/iiae074.
Emma Ashford, ‘Stuck on the left with you: the limits of partisanship in US foreign policy’, Security Studies 32: 2, 2023, pp. 382–8 at p. 385, https://doi.org/10.1080/09636412.2023.2200971.
Lammy, ‘The case for progressive realism’.
John J. Mearsheimer, ‘Why the Ukraine crisis is the West's fault: the liberal delusions that provoked Putin’, Foreign Affairs, Sept./Oct. 2014, https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/russia-fsu/2014-08-18/why-ukraine-crisis-west-s-fault. For an alternative view, see Kseniya Oksamytna, ‘Imperialism, supremacy, and the Russian invasion of Ukraine’, Contemporary Security Policy 44: 4, 2023, pp. 497–512, https://doi.org/10.1080/13523260.2023.2259661.
For a processual (or practice-based) account of the mistakes prior to 2014 see Vincent Pouliot, International security in practice: the politics of NATO–Russia diplomacy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010). Pouliot recalls how, during the period of NATO–Russia cooperation, western practitioners saw themselves as the ‘teachers’ of Russian diplomats, who were represented as ‘irrational and emotional’. Predictably Russian diplomats ‘despised’ NATO's ‘self-attributed role as a teacher’, and this experience contributed to a resurgence of the ‘great power’ habitus.
John J. Mearsheimer, ‘The causes and consequences of the Ukraine crisis’, speech at the European Union Institute, The National Interest, 23 June 2023, https://nationalinterest.org/feature/causes-and-consequences-ukraine-crisis-203182; Isaac Chotiner, ‘Why John Mearsheimer blames the U.S. for the crisis in Ukraine’, New Yorker, 1 March 2022, https://www.newyorker.com/news/q-and-a/why-john-mearsheimer-blames-the-us-for-the-crisis-in-ukraine.
Stephen M. Walt, ‘An International Relations theory guide to the war in Ukraine’, Foreign Policy, 8 March 2022, https://foreignpolicy.com/2022/03/08/an-international-relations-theory-guide-to-ukraines-war.
Mearsheimer, The tragedy of great power politics. Richard Ned Lebow argues that Mearsheimer's preconceptions lead him to exaggerate the extent to which NATO ‘posed a strategic threat to Russia’: Richard Ned Lebow, ‘International Relations theory and the Ukrainian War’, Analyse & Kritik 44: 1, 2022, https://doi.org/10.1515/auk-2022-2021, p. 130. See also Janina Dill, ‘The moral muddle of blaming the West for Russia's aggression’, Public Ethics, 6 April 2022, https://www.publicethics.org/post/the-moral-muddle-of-blaming-the-west-for-russia-s-aggression.
On the undemocratic dangers of abstract theorizing in this instance, see Jan Dutkiewicz and Jan Smolenski, ‘Epistemic superimposition: the war in Ukraine and the poverty of expertise in International Relations theory’, Journal of International Relations and Development, vol. 26, 2023, pp. 619–31, https://doi.org/10.1057/s41268-023-00314-1.
For a different realist calculation of the importance of respecting self-determination, including the need to avoid imposing alliance membership on the process of German reunification, see Philip Zelikow and Condoleezza Rice, Germany unified and Europe transformed: a study in statecraft (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995).
Glanville and Pattison argue that the West should, given the opportunity cost of military aid, ‘continue to provide some limited military aid, with reductions in military assistance made on a careful, gradual basis and, as far as is feasible, in conjunction with efforts to negotiate peace’: Luke Glanville and James Pattison, ‘Ukraine and the opportunity costs of military aid’, International Affairs 100: 4, 2024, pp. 1571–90, https://doi.org/10.1093/ia/iiae122. We see problems to the extent that a peace negotiated under these terms would benefit the Russian position leading, in practice, to a realist-type imposition.
Jason Ralph, ‘Securing the self, embracing anxiety, or nurturing growth? How the pragmatism of Dewey, James, and Mead speaks to ontological security studies’, Global Studies Quarterly 4: 2, 2024, https://doi.org/10.1093/isagsq/ksae032.
Emanuel Adler, ‘Seeds of peaceful change: the OSCE's security community building model’, in Emanuel Adler and Michael Barnett, Security communities (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 119–60.
Matthew Evangelista, Unarmed forces: the transnational movement to end the Cold War (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2002); Daniel C. Thomas, The Helsinki effect: international norms, human rights, and the demise of communism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001); Patricia Chilton, ‘Mechanics of change: social movements, transnational coalitions, and the transformation processes in Eastern Europe’, Democratization 1: 1, 1994, pp. 151–81, https://doi.org/10.1080/13510349408403385.
On esteem as part of a process of mutual recognition that helps to realize and secure the Self, see the Pragmatist-inspired Axel Honneth, The struggle for recognition: the moral grammar of social conflicts (Cambridge, UK: Polity, 1995).
On the ‘relational work’ of the feminist Pragmatist Jane Addams, see Molly Cochran, ‘The “newer ideals” of Jane Addams's progressivism: the realistic utopia of cosmopolitan justice’, in Cochran and Navari, Progressivism and US foreign policy. For evidence of this work in the region, see Veronika L. Sharova, ‘Feminism as an antiwar strategy and practice: the case of Belarus, Russia, and Ukraine’, Studies in East European Thought 74: 4, 2022, pp. 521–34, https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-022-09520-y.
David Held and David Mepham, eds, Progressive foreign policy (Cambridge, UK: Polity, 2007).
Umut Aydin, ‘Emerging middle powers and the liberal international order’, International Affairs 97: 5, 2021, pp. 1377–94, https://doi.org/10.1093/ia/iiab090; Ahmad Rizky Mardhatillah Umar, ‘The rise of the Asian middle powers: Indonesia's conceptions of international order’, International Affairs 99: 4, 2023, pp. 1459–76, https://doi.org/10.1093/ia/iiad167.
HM Government, Foreign, Commonwealth & Development Office and Rt Hon. James Cleverly MP, ‘British foreign policy and diplomacy: Foreign Secretary's speech, 12 December 2022’, 12 Dec. 2022, https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/foreign-secretarys-speech-12-december-2022.
Lammy, Britain reconnected, p. 35.
Patrick Wintour, ‘Watered-down G20 statement on Ukraine is sign of India's growing influence’, Guardian, 10 Sept. 2023, https://www.theguardian.com/world/2023/sep/10/watered-down-g20-statement-on-ukraine-is-sign-of-indias-growing-influence.
Chietigj Bajpaee, ‘The G20 showcases India's growing power. It could also expose the limits of its foreign policy’, Chatham House expert comment, 7 Sept. 2023, https://www.chathamhouse.org/2023/09/g20-showcases-indias-growing-power-it-could-also-expose-limits-its-foreign-policy.
Moisés Naim, ‘Minilateralism: the magic number to get real international action’, Foreign Policy, 21 June 2009, https://foreignpolicy.com/2009/06/21/minilateralism.
Robyn Eckersley, ‘Moving forward in the climate negotiations: multilateralism or minilateralism?’, Global Environmental Politics 12: 2, 2012, pp. 24–42, https://doi.org/10.1162/GLEP_a_00107.
Lammy, ‘The case for progressive realism’.
From 2010 the BRICS intergovernmental organization comprised Brazil, Russia, India, China and South Africa. In January 2024 Egypt, Ethiopia, Iran and the United Arab Emirates acceded to full membership of the group, which subsequently became known as ‘BRICS+’.
The UK's inclusion of China in discussions on the regulation of artificial intelligence illustrates the point. Prime Minister Rishi Sunak recognized this and was supposedly keen for Chinese involvement, since China had already become a leader in the area: Rafael Behr, ‘Rishi Sunak's vanity jamboree on AI safety lays bare the UK's Brexit dilemmas’, Guardian, 1 Nov. 2023, https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2023/nov/01/rishi-sunaks-ai-safety-britains-brexit-dilemmas-elon-musk; Arthur Holland Michel, Recalibrating assumptions on AI: towards an evidence-based and inclusive AI policy discourse (London: Royal Institute of International Affairs, 2023), https://doi.org/10.55317/9781784135621.
Lesley Hughes and Wesley Morgan, ‘Good COP, bad COP: climate wins and losses from Glasgow’, Sydney Morning Herald, 14 Nov. 2021, https://www.smh.com.au/politics/federal/good-cop-bad-cop-climate-wins-and-losses-from-glasgow-20211114-p598rq.html.
Matt McGrath, ‘COP26: fossil fuel industry has largest delegation at climate summit’, BBC News, 8 Nov. 2021, at https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/science-environment-59199484.
Abby Wallace, ‘Government advisers to Rishi Sunak: you've put UK climate goals at risk’, Politico, 12 Oct. 2023, https://www.politico.eu/article/government-adviser-climate-change-committee-british-prime-minister-rishi-sunak-uk-goals-risk.
HM Government, Prime Minister's Office and Rt Hon. Rishi Sunak MP, ‘PM speech on net zero: 20 September 2023’, 20 Sept. 2023, https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/pm-speech-on-net-zero-20-september-2023; Chris Mason and Paul Seddon, ‘Keir Starmer: Labour ditches £28bn green investment pledge’, BBC News, 8 Feb. 2024, https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-politics-68232133.
Gilmore, ‘Conceptualizing good global statehood’, p. 98.
Lammy, ‘The case for progressive realism’.
Noah Keate, ‘UK drops objection to ICC arrest warrant for Netanyahu’, Politico, 26 July 2024, https://www.politico.eu/article/uk-drops-objection-icc-issuing-arrest-warrant-benjamin-netanyahu; HM Government, Foreign, Commonwealth & Development Office and Department for Business and Trade, Rt Hon. Jonathan Reynolds MP and Rt Hon. David Lammy MP, ‘UK suspends around 30 arms export licences to Israel for use in Gaza over international humanitarian law concerns’, 2 Sept. 2024, https://www.gov.uk/government/news/uk-suspends-around-30-arms-export-licences-to-israel-for-use-in-gaza-over-international-humanitarian-law-concerns.
Lammy, ‘The case for progressive realism’.
Author notes
An early draft of this paper was presented at the International Studies Association 2023 annual conference in Montreal. We would like to thank Sassan Gholiagha for his comments. In addition we would like to thank all the anonymous reviewers for their rigorous engagement. Jamie Gaskarth is an Associate Editor of International Affairs; this article was accepted for publication prior to his appointment.