Abstract

Carbon prices are the most cost-effective instrument to reduce CO|$_2$| emissions, but there is strong political opposition to raising them to the efficient level. Therefore, additional efforts of consumers, firms and local governments are required. We study how different regulatory regimes affect moral behaviour and show that a carbon tax complements voluntary efforts to reduce emissions, while cap and trade discourages them. The opportunity to invest in offsets increases welfare, while the option to buy and delete emission rights induces more emissions and reduces welfare. Furthermore, cap and trade shifts the burden of adjustment to poor consumers and has dysfunctional incentive effects.

The consensus view among economists is that the most efficient way to combat climate change is to put a price on carbon. Many countries engage in carbon pricing, either by taxing CO|$_2$| emissions (price regulation) or by implementing an emission trading system (‘cap and trade’, quantity regulation). But, in almost all countries actual carbon prices are insufficient to achieve the ambitious climate goals of the Paris agreement, and there is strong political opposition to raising them. Therefore, it becomes increasingly clear that additional efforts are required. In particular, the many voluntary contributions of consumers, firms and local governments play an important role in mitigating climate change. The IPCC (2022, p. TS-98) estimates that these efforts can reduce emissions by 40%–70% until 2050. This raises the question of how carbon pricing and the efforts of climate-conscious agents interact. It turns out that this crucially depends on whether carbon pricing is implemented by using price regulation (a carbon tax) or quantity regulation (cap and trade).

In this paper, we assume that some consumers (firms, local governments) are morally concerned consequentialists (e.g., utilitarians), who are willing to reduce their consumption of the polluting good if their behaviour affects the total level of emissions. Furthermore, we assume that there is a political constraint on the emission price. No matter whether this price is a carbon tax or a permit price determined by a market for emission permits, it cannot be higher than some upper bound |$\bar{p}$|⁠, because a higher price would cause political unrest. We show that, under these two assumptions, price regulation (i.e., a carbon tax) complements voluntary efforts to reduce emissions and encourages consumers to consume less of the polluting good. Quantity regulation (i.e., cap and trade) on the other hand discourages morally motivated consumers to reduce emissions and may even induce them to increase consumption and pollute more.1

The problem of cap and trade is the so-called ‘waterbed effect’. The total amount of emissions is fixed by the number of emission permits issued by the regulator. If morally motivated agents reduce their emissions voluntarily, for example by saving energy, by investing in solar panels or by using the train rather than a short-distance flight, they cannot reduce the overall level of emissions because total emissions are solely determined by the number of emission permits. The mechanism is as follows: if consumers reduce, e.g., their energy consumption then the power companies burn less fossil fuels and therefore need fewer emission permits. This reduction in the demand for permits reduces the permit price. Because the supply of permits is fixed and completely price inelastic, the price must fall up to the point where these permits are bought by some other companies that use them to increase their pollution. This is the waterbed effect: if the water level is pushed down in one area of the bed, the water level in other areas must rise, because the quantity of water in the bed is fixed.

In our model rational consumers understand this effect. They know that, with quantity regulation, reducing their consumption has no effect on total emissions. Because they are consequentialists, they will not engage in additional consumption reductions despite their moral concerns about pollution. With price regulation, on the other hand, the emission price does not adjust if consumption is reduced, so every reduction in consumption reduces total emissions one to one. This encourages climate-conscious consumers to consume less of the polluting good. These different reactions of consumers to price and quantity regulation do not matter if the regulator is unconstrained: the first-best allocation can be implemented in both regimes. But, if the regulator is politically constrained to keep the carbon price below a threshold then the effects of the different regimes on moral behaviour do have an effect: consumption of the harmful good is strictly lower under price than under quantity regulation even though the carbon price is the same in both regimes.

Reducing consumption is not the only way that climate-conscious agents can reduce pollution. They can also invest in offsets, such as planting trees, restoring moors or carbon capture and storage, which also reduces greenhouse gases in the atmosphere.2 Furthermore, if there is an emissions market, it is possible to buy and delete emission rights that effectively reduce total emissions.3 We allow for these actions in our model. While offsets have a positive effect, it turns out that the possibility of buying and deleting emission rights induces consumers to increase consumption and pollution, which reduces welfare.

The main result of the paper is that, with an upper bound on the emission price, material social welfare (that ignores moral utility) is always higher with price regulation than with quantity regulation. This is because only price regulation induces climate-conscious consumers to consume less of the polluting good. But there is also a downside to price regulation. Morally concerned consumers suffer from violating a social norm. This is not the case with quantity regulation. A consumer who knows that her actions cannot have any effect on total emissions does not have to be morally concerned about her actions.

In Section 3 we look at the distributional consequences of price and quantity regulation. We assume that there are two groups of consumers, rich and poor, and that the rich have a lower marginal utility of money. With quantity regulation, consumers only care about the price of the polluting good. If the marginal utility of money is sufficiently small for the rich, they do not reduce their consumption but rather buy and delete emission permits. Thus, the burden of adjustment is borne entirely by poor consumers who cannot afford to buy and delete emission permits but have to reduce their consumption. With price regulation, on the other hand, both consumer groups are morally motivated to reduce their consumption. Thus, the two groups bear the burden of emission reductions more equally.

In Section 4 we allow for uncertainty. In a canonical paper, Weitzman (1974) showed that quantity regulation can be superior to price regulation if uncertainty about the price is less harmful than uncertainty about the quantity. However, in his model there is no upper bound on the emission price. Thus, with uncertainty, total emissions are sometimes inefficiently high and sometimes inefficiently low. In contrast, in our model the upper bound on the emission price implies that total emissions are always too high. The regulator must guarantee that the emission price never exceeds |$\bar{p}$|⁠. Thus, with quantity regulation, he will choose the number of permits such that in the worst possible state of nature the emission price is just equal to |$\bar{p}$|⁠. In all other states it will be lower. In contrast, with price regulation, the emission price is always equal to |$\bar{p}$|⁠. Thus, in expectation consumers will consume more with quantity regulation than with price regulation. This holds even if there are no moral preferences.

In Section 5 we relax the assumptions of consequentialism and rationality. Some consumers have non-consequentialist moral convictions, and some do not understand the waterbed effect. We look at the interaction of selfish consumers and two different types of consumers with moral preferences: consequentialists (‘utilitarians’) as described above and deontologists (‘Kantians’), who consider it their moral duty to follow an ethical norm no matter what the consequences. Kantians behave in the same way under price and under quantity regulation. They are observationally equivalent to ‘naïve’ utilitarians, i.e., to consequentialists who do not understand that with an emissions market their actions cannot affect total emissions. We ask how a political (or educational) campaign that increases the share of morally concerned consumers (or reduces the share of naïve consumers) affects the utility of the different groups. With price regulation, an increase of morally motivated consumers reduces emissions and benefits both selfish and moral consumers. With quantity regulation, an increase of the share of Kantian consumers leaves total pollution unaffected but reduces the emissions price. This benefits selfish consumers, while Kantian consumers are worse off. Thus, Kantians have no material interest in convincing other consumers to behave morally and nobody wants to explain to naïve utilitarians how the emissions market works.

In the formal model we restrict attention to the consumption decisions of individual consumers. However, consumers also affect the decisions of firms and governments. For example, many firms want to become ‘carbon neutral’ either because they want to appeal to climate-conscious consumers and employees or because the are owned by climate-conscious investors. Similarly, (regional) governments engage in significant efforts to reduce carbon emissions in addition to carbon pricing. Section 6 concludes by arguing that these additional efforts are wasted under quantity regulation, but can yield a significant contribution to mitigating climate change with price regulation.

All proofs are relegated to Appendix A3. In Appendices A1 and A2, we conduct some additional robustness checks. There we allow for imperfect competition and we consider the case of a constant-returns-to-scale offset technology that may be available in the future if carbon capture and storage becomes economical at a large scale.

Our paper is related to four strands of the literature. First, there is a large literature on the efficient regulation of negative externalities (Baumol and Oates, 1988). This literature goes back to Pigou (1920), who first proposed to use taxes (price regulation) to internalise negative externalities. The idea of quantity regulation through cap and trade is implicit in Coase (1960) and spelled out formally by Montgomery (1972). In a seminal paper Weitzman (1974) compared price and quantity regulation in a model with uncertainty regarding the costs and benefits of abatement.4 His analysis has been extended in many directions, e.g., to stock pollutants (Hoel and Karp, 2002), commitment and flexibility (Requate, 2005) and political economy issues (Helm, 2005). Surveys on this literature are offered by Hepburn (2006) and Goulder and Schein (2013).5 To the best of our knowledge, our paper is the first to consider how the presence of morally motivated agents affects this trade-off.

Second, there is a literature discussing the interaction of different policy instruments (Fankhauser et al., 2010; Goulder et al., 2012). This literature shows that different policy measures can be (perfect) substitutes, so adding one instrument to another may have very little or no effect. For example, if a pollution tax is imposed on a good that is already covered by cap-and-trade regulation then the tax will be fully offset by a reduction of the permit price and does not have any additional effect on aggregate emissions (Goulder, 2013). Perino (2015) considered a general equilibrium model with two sectors, one of which is regulated by cap and trade and one that is regulated by a tax. He showed that voluntary climate action may increase total emissions due to leakage to the other sector. While this literature studies the interaction of different instruments in an inefficient policy mix, we consider the interaction of one type of regulation (either price or quantity regulation) with the moral preferences of consumers. We analyse how the intrinsic (moral) motivation of climate-conscious consumers is affected by the chosen policy instrument and how it affects the efficiency of regulation.

Third, our paper is related to the behavioural and experimental economics literature. Pollution and climate change is a leading example of a public good problem. There is an extensive literature in experimental economics showing that social preferences mitigate public good problems.6 In our paper, consumers do not have social preferences about the consumption or income of others but moral concerns about the environment. They suffer if their own consumption departs from the social norm. Therefore, closely related to our work is the economic literature on how social norms affect behaviour (Bénabou and Tirole, 2006; Krupka and Weber, 2013; Bénabou et al., 2018). In particular, several empirical papers of that literature show that social norms have an important impact on decisions affecting the environment (Nyborg et al., 2006; Allcott and Rogers, 2014; Schwirplies and Ziegler, 2016; Jakob et al., 2017). In a lab experiment, Ockenfels et al. (2019) directly investigated whether an emissions tax performs better than a cap-and-trade system for reducing carbon emissions. They found that an emissions tax yields more abatement than cap and trade, which confirms our theoretical results. Finally, there is a discussion on whether markets erode social responsibility and moral concerns (Sandel, 2012; Bartling et al., 2015; Sutter et al., 2020; Dewatripont and Tirole, 2022). In our paper, it is not the market per se that affects moral behaviour but the type of market mechanism. We consider two market instruments, price and quantity regulation, and show that price regulation fosters moral behaviour, while quantity regulation renders it irrelevant.

Finally, there is a recent and quickly growing literature that incorporates morally motivated individuals in economic models with environmental externalities. For example, Eichner and Pethig (2020) derived optimal environmental taxes when consumers are concerned about the environment. Ambec and De Donder (2022) assumed that consumers derive a warm glow from consuming a green product. They compared a tax to a pollution standard and asked which policy measure is more cost effective taking firms’ strategic reactions into account. Grafton et al. (2017) studied the interaction of Kantian and selfish consumers, building on the notion of Kantian equilibrium introduced by Roemer (2010; 2015). Aghion et al. (2020) showed that there is a complementarity between product-market competition and consumers’ environmental concerns. Firms choose greener innovations when consumers care more strongly about their carbon footprint, and the more so, the stronger market competition is. None of the aforementioned papers contrasts price regulation (environmental tax) with quantity regulation (cap and trade).

1. The Model

Consider an economy with two consumption goods, a good X that pollutes the environment with greenhouse gas emissions and a numéraire good Y that involves no externalities. Each consumption unit of X generates one unit of emissions. Both goods are produced at constant marginal costs. The unit production cost of good X is |$c\gt 0$|⁠; the unit production cost of the numéraire good Y is normalised to 1. There is no uncertainty and there is perfect competition so that all goods are sold at marginal cost. In Section 4 we consider the effects of uncertainty and in Appendix A2 we allow for imperfect competition.

The negative externalities can be mitigated by reducing consumption (and thereby emissions) or by offsetting emissions, e.g., by planting trees, restoring moors, etc. One unit of the offset good Z reduces emissions by one unit. The offset good is produced with cost function |$k(z)$| with |$k^{\prime }(z)\gt 0$| for |$z\gt 0$|⁠, and |$k^{\prime \prime }(z)\gt 0$|⁠. The offset good is also produced by a competitive industry and thus the equilibrium price is |$q=k^{\prime }(z)$|⁠. Firms are owned by consumers, which implies that the profits of the offset industry |$\pi _Z=qz-k(z)$| are part of consumers’ income.

There is a continuum of identical consumers with wealth m and material utility function
where x and y denote the amounts consumed of goods X and Y, respectively. Let |$v^{\prime }(x)\gt 0$| and |$v^{\prime \prime }(x)\lt 0$|⁠. Consumers suffer from the environmental damage |$D(\cdot )$| that is caused by aggregate consumption |$\bar{x}$| net of aggregate offsets |$\bar{z}$|⁠. We assume that |$D(\cdot )$| is a continuous function with the following properties: for |$\bar{x}\gt \bar{z}$|⁠, it holds that |$D^{\prime }(\cdot ) \gt 0$| and |$D^{\prime \prime }(\cdot ) \gt 0$|⁠, while for |$\bar{z}\ge \bar{x}$|⁠, we have |$D(\cdot )\equiv 0$|⁠. To guarantee that all optimisation problems have an interior solution, we assume that |$v^{\prime }(0)=+\infty$|⁠, |$\lim_{x\rightarrow \infty} v{^{\prime}}(x)=0$|⁠, |$k^{\prime }(0)=0$| and |$D^{\prime }(0)=0$|⁠. In Section 3, we allow for consumers that are heterogeneous regarding their marginal rates of substitution between the two consumption goods.

1.1. Material Welfare

Material social welfare is defined as material utility minus production costs. Note that, due to quasi-linear utility, the amount consumed of the numéraire good Y equals income minus expenditures for consumption of good X and offsets Z. Thus, material welfare is given by
(1)
where |$\tilde{m}$| is total income (including income from profits). There is a unique interior solution for the first-best levels of consumption, |$x^{*}\gt 0$|⁠, and offsets, |$z^{*}\gt 0$|⁠, that is uniquely characterised by the first-order conditions7
(2)
(3)
This implies that

1.2. Regulation

The regulator has two instruments to deal with harmful emissions. First, he can reduce aggregate consumption by either imposing a consumption tax (price regulation, |$R=P$|⁠) or by introducing an emissions market where a fixed number of emission permits (⁠|$\bar{E}$|⁠) is traded (quantity regulation, |$R=Q$|⁠). We denote the tax as well as the permit price by p. Revenues from emission pricing are redistributed lump sum to consumers. Note that, with price regulation, the total amount of emissions is determined by the consumption decisions of all consumers, while with quantity regulation, the total amount of emissions is fixed. The emissions price will always adjust such that the total amount of emissions is exactly |$\bar{E}$|⁠.

Second, the regulator can mitigate emissions by buying offsets financed by (lump-sum) taxation. Let the number of offsets purchased by the government be |$z^G$| and the number of offsets bought by consumers |$z^C$|⁠, with |$\bar{z}=z^G+z^C$|⁠.

1.3. Moral Preferences and Total Welfare

We depart from the standard model by assuming that consumers have moral concerns about pollution. They incur a moral cost if their emissions harm the environment. In the basic model, we assume that all consumers are ‘moral consequentialists’ (e.g., utilitarians) who base the moral judgement of an action on its consequences. In Section 5, we allow for heterogeneous moral convictions (selfish consumers, consequentialists and deontologists). Moral concerns are modelled as follows. The consumer compares her consumption level x to a social norm that is determined endogenously. The social norm consumption level |$x_0$| is a weighted average of the socially efficient consumption level |$x^{*}$| and the average actual consumption level in society |$x^R$|⁠, which depends on the regulatory regime |$R\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$|⁠, i.e.,
If |$\alpha = 1$|⁠, the norm is fully ‘injunctive’ and requires that everybody should consume the socially efficient quantity |$x^{*}$| that maximises material social welfare. If |$\alpha =0$|⁠, the norm is purely ‘descriptive’, i.e., the consumers shall not consume more of X than everybody else does.8 Actual social norms are somewhere in between.

If the consumer consumes more than the social norm |$x_0^R$| prescribes, she suffers a moral cost, i.e., her utility is reduced by |$\beta ^R [x-x_0^R]^+$|⁠, where |$[x-x_0^R]^+ = \max \lbrace 0, x-x_0^R\rbrace$| and |$R\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$|⁠. Because consumers are consequentialists they suffer from the moral cost only if their consumption actually affects overall pollution. This is the case with price regulation, but not with quantity regulation. Thus, with price regulation, |$\beta ^R = \beta \gt 0$|⁠, while with quantity regulation, we have |$\beta ^Q=0$|⁠.

The consumer may compensate for her wrong doing by offsetting some of her emissions (⁠|$z\ge 0$|⁠) at price q. Furthermore, if there is an emissions market, she can buy and delete emission rights (⁠|$e\ge 0$|⁠) at price p that reduces the total amount of emissions by e. This increases her utility by |$\beta \lbrace \min \lbrace e+z, [x-x_0^R]^+\rbrace$|⁠. Thus, the total utility function of a consumer is given by
(4)
with |$\beta ^P=\beta$|⁠, |$\beta ^Q=0$| and |$e=0$| in the case of price regulation. A consumer’s income is initial wealth (m) plus profits from firms producing offsets plus net transfers from the government; |$\tilde{m}=m+q \bar{z}-k(\bar{z}) +(p\bar{x}- q z^G)$|⁠.

Recall that there is a continuum of consumers. Thus, the effect that each consumer has on the damage experienced by herself is negligible and is ignored by the consumer. However, the aggregate marginal utility loss of all consumers is given by |$D^{\prime }(\cdot ) \gt 0$|⁠, which is not negligible, but equal to the marginal social cost of carbon. To illustrate, if a consumer emits one additional ton of CO |$_2$| then she will ignore how this additional consumption affects her own utility via the damage function |$D(\cdot )$|⁠. However, the utility loss aggregated over all consumers is equal to the social cost of carbon and is not ignored by the consumer. A moral consequentialist feels responsible for the environmental damage that she imposes on all other consumers, but she ignores the negligible effect on herself.9

If consumers have moral concerns, we have to distinguish between material social welfare as defined in(1) and total social welfare that includes the moral feelings of consumers:
(5)

We are mainly interested in material welfare and assume that this is what the regulator wants to maximise, but we also consider the effects of regulation on total welfare. Note that in the first best there is no difference between material and total welfare.

 
Observation 1.

Total social welfare(5)and material social welfare(1) coincide at consumption level|$x^{*}$|and total offsets|$z^{*}$|⁠, defined by(2) and(3).

If everybody consumes |$x^{*}$|⁠, people do not suffer from consuming too much and they cannot increase moral utility by buying offsets.

1.4. Consumer Demand

The consumer’s demand for offsets and/or emission rights is always given by a corner solution. If a consumer’s moral concerns |$\beta$| are lower than the price for offsets or emission permits, she prefers not to compensate her consumption at all. If, on the other hand, her moral concerns are higher, she completely offsets her moral wrong doing.10 With price regulation,
With quantity regulation, the consumer can compensate her emissions either by buying offsets at price q or by buying and deleting emission rights at price p. Because these are perfect substitutes, she will never engage in the more expensive of the two options. The total amount of compensations purchased is
with |$z^Q=0$| for |$q\gt p$| and |$e^Q=0$| for |$p\gt q$|⁠.
In the following we restrict attention to the case where in both regulatory regimes average consumption is larger than the consumption level required by the social norm, i.e., |$x^R\ge x_0^R$|⁠.11 The consumer’s demand for the consumption good depends on whether she will buy offsets/emission rights. With price regulation, buying and deleting emission rights is not an option and she will not buy offsets if |$\beta \lt q$|⁠. In this case the first-order condition (FOC) for her optimal consumption decision is given by
If, on the other hand, |$\beta \ge q$|⁠, the consumer fully offsets her wrong doing by choosing |$z^P=x-x^0$|⁠. Note that this makes the choice of z—indirectly—a function of x. The consumer anticipates that she will fully offset her consumption that eliminates the moral cost but increases the price of good X to |$c+p+q$|⁠. Thus, her optimal consumption is given by
With quantity regulation, the demand for good X is derived similarly. If |$\beta \lt \min \lbrace p,q\rbrace$|⁠, the consumer will not buy offsets nor will she buy and delete emission rights. Furthermore, she knows that her consumption decision has no effect on total emissions. Therefore, the FOC for her optimal consumption is
If, on the other hand, |$\beta \ge \min \lbrace p,q\rbrace$|⁠, the consumer either buys offsets or emission rights (whatever is cheaper) to compensate for the emissions caused by her consumption. In this case we have
Let |$\pi$| denote the sum of the ‘prices’ (including the moral price) that the consumer considers in her consumption decision, and define the consumer’s moral demand |$\hat{x}(\pi )$| by
Then we can summarise this discussion in the following lemma.
 
Lemma 1.
The consumer’s demand functions for the consumption good under price and under quantity regulation are given by
and her demand functions for offsets and/or buying and deleting emission rights are
with|$z^Q = 0$|if|$p\lt q$|and|$e^Q=0$|if|$q \lt p$|⁠.

1.5. Implementing the First Best

If the regulator is not constrained in his choice of p or |$\bar{E}$|⁠, it is not difficult to implement the first-best allocation |$(x^{*},z^{*})$|⁠. With price regulation, a sufficiently high emission tax implements |$x^P=x^{*}$|⁠. With quantity regulation, the number of emission permits |$\bar{E}$| can be set equal to |$x^{*}$|⁠. This directly implements the optimal amount of X (if no consumer buys and deletes emission rights). Note that if all consumers choose |$x^{*}$|⁠, the social norm is |$x_0=x^{*}$|⁠, so all consumers comply with the norm. A consumer who consumes |$x=x^{*}$| has no incentive to purchase offsets or to buy and delete emission rights, i.e., |$0=e^Q=z^C\lt z^{*}$|⁠. Thus, the first-best allocation is attainable only if the regulator purchases the optimal amount of offsets |$z^G=z^{*}$|⁠.

 
Proposition 1.

If the emission price is unconstrained, the regulator can implement the first best by buying offsets|$z^G=z^{*}$|and

  • either price regulation that sets the emission price to|$p^{*}\in [D^{\prime }(x^{*})-\beta , \ D^{\prime }(x^{*})]$|for|$k^{\prime }(z^{*})\ge \beta$|and|$p^{*}\in [D^{\prime }(x^{*})-q, \ D^{\prime }(x^{*})]$|for|$k^{\prime }(z^{*})\lt \beta$|⁠, or

  • quantity regulation that restricts the number of emission permits to|$\bar{E}= x^{*}$|⁠.

2. Second-Best Optimal Regulation

We now assume that there is a political constraint on the emission price p.

 
Assumption 1.
No matter whether there is price or quantity regulation, the regulator is constrained to implement an emission price p that satisfies
(6)

This constraint is due to political reasons. Many countries are finding it difficult if not impossible to raise carbon prices to the appropriate level. In the United States carbon pricing is considered politically toxic and the Biden administration has basically given up on raising the current taxes on energy consumption. In France, the ‘yellow vest’ movement forced the Macron administration to largely roll back its increase of fuel taxes. In Switzerland, the electorate rejected a proposed increase of the carbon price in 2021. One reason why carbon pricing is so unpopular is that it is directly reflected in the price for gasoline, which is one of the most visible of all consumption prices.12

Note that constraint (6) implicitly imposes an upper bound on |$\beta$| and requires that |$\beta \lt D^{\prime }(x^{*}-z^{*})=k^{\prime }(z^{*})$|⁠. If |$\beta$| was larger than this upper bound, moral concerns would be sufficient to implement the first best even if there is a constraint on the emission price.

Assumption 1 implies that the first-best allocation cannot be implemented with carbon pricing. In particular, there will always be too much consumption of the harmful good, |$x\gt x^{*}$|⁠. In the main part of the paper we focus on this distortion only, i.e., we allow the regulator to purchase the (second-best) optimal number of offsets. This requires that the efficient number of offsets is sufficiently small that the regulator can buy them without massive tax increases that would infuriate (part of) the electorate. This is the case if the marginal cost of producing the offset increases quickly, so the efficient amount of offsets is limited and small.13

 
Proposition 2.

Suppose that Assumption1holds. Under price regulation, the regulator chooses|$p=\bar{p}$|⁠. Under quantity regulation, he fixes the number of emission permits|$\bar{E}$|such that the resulting permit price is|$\bar{p}$|⁠.

The second-best optimal amount of offsets|$z^R=\hat{z}(x^R)$|depends on the consumption level|$x^R$|⁠, |$R\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$|⁠, and is implicitly defied by
For any|$x^R \gt x^{*}$|⁠, consumers will not purchase any offsets, so|$\hat{z}$|will be bought entirely by the regulator.

The intuition for Proposition 2 is straightforward. The regulator will guarantee that the second-best amount of offsets is produced. This drives up the marginal cost of offsets and therefore the price q so much that consumers will not buy them. Note, however, that, with quantity regulation, consumers may purchase emission permits. Given that the regulator buys the second-best optimal level of offset |$\hat{z}(x)$|⁠, material welfare is a concave function of x that is maximised at |$x^{*}$|⁠. Because of Assumption 1, |$x^{*}$| cannot be implemented. Therefore, the regulator wants to reduce x as much as possible, which is achieved by setting |$p=\bar{p}$| under price regulation and by choosing a number of permits |$\bar{E}$| such that the resulting permit price is exactly |$\bar{p}$|⁠. Given Proposition 2 we can now focus on |$p=\bar{p}$| and |$z=\hat{z}(x)$|⁠.

The next proposition describes consumer behaviour under optimal price and quantity regulation, respectively.

 
Proposition 3.

For any|$\beta \gt 0$|that satisfies Assumption1, consumption differs between a regime with price regulation and one with quantity regulation.

  • With price regulation, the optimal consumption level is given by
    and consumers do not buy any offsets.
  • With quantity regulation, the optimal consumption level is given by
    Consumers do not buy any offsets, but they may buy and delete emission rights
    The regulator sets

Optimal consumption is decreasing in|$\beta$|under price regulation, but weakly increasing in|$\beta$|with quantity regulation. Furthermore,

The proposition shows that consumption is decreasing in |$\beta$| with price regulation, but increasing in |$\beta$| with quantity regulation. The intuition for the case of price regulation is straightforward. If consumers are more strongly concerned about pollution, they will consume and pollute less, because consumption becomes (morally) more expensive. It may be more surprising that the opposite result holds with quantity regulation if |$\beta \ge \bar{p}$|⁠. The reason is as follows. On the one hand, consumers know that, with quantity regulation, their consumption decision has no effect on total pollution, so moral concerns do not induce them to consume less. On the other hand, consumers feel good about buying and deleting emission permits. If |$\beta \ge \bar{p}$|⁠, they do so, and the more they consume, the more permits they buy and delete. Thus, if |$\beta$| increases, they derive more utility from this compensation, so they will consume more in order to compensate more. However, the regulator anticipates this behaviour. He has to make sure that the permit price will not exceed |$\bar{p}$|⁠. Thus, the regulator chooses the number of permits such that the additional demand for permits by consumers who want to buy and delete them will be met without the price exceeding |$\bar{p}$|⁠. Thus, in equilibrium, buying and deleting emission rights does not reduce consumption, but increases it.

To evaluate the total effect on emissions, we have to take the offsets into account that are bought by the regulator. The next proposition shows that the effect of regulation on consumption goes in the same direction as the effect on net emissions, i.e., consumption minus offsets.

 
Proposition 4.
For any|$\beta \gt 0$|⁠, optimal price regulation implements an emission level|${\cal E}^P=x^P-z^P$|that is inefficiently high but strictly smaller than the level of emissions|${\cal E}^Q=x^Q-z^Q$|under optimal quantity regulation, i.e.,

The intuition for this proposition is that, even though a higher consumption level induces the regulator to invest more in offsets, the slope of the increase in offsets is less than one. Hence, more consumption implies a higher level of total emissions.

We are now in a position to evaluate material and total social welfare under the two regulatory regimes.

 
Proposition 5.

The regulatory regime effects social welfare as follows.

  • Material social welfare(1) is unambiguously higher with price regulation than with quantity regulation, i.e.,
  • The difference in material welfare is strictly increasing in|$\beta$|⁠,
  • Total social welfare(5) is higher with price than with quantity regulation if and only if
    This is always the case if the social norm is sufficiently descriptive, i.e., |$\alpha$| is sufficiently small.

Proposition 5(i) shows that material social welfare is strictly higher with price regulation than with quantity regulation. Furthermore, by Proposition 5(ii), the more important moral concerns of consumers are, the more pronounced is the advantage. Price regulation complements moral motivations and induces consumers to pollute less. Quantity regulation has the exact opposite effect. In equilibrium, it induces morally motivated consumers to pollute more, the more they are concerned about the environment.

Proposition 5(iii) considers total social welfare that includes the moral feelings of consumers. With price regulation, climate-conscious consumers suffer from violating the social norm. This is not the case with quantity regulation. A consumer who knows that her actions cannot have any effect on total emissions does not have to be morally concerned about her actions. Furthermore, with quantity regulation, consumers can derive positive utility from buying and deleting emission permits. Thus, if these feelings are very strong, total social welfare may be larger under quantity than under price regulation. However, if |$\alpha$| is sufficiently small, i.e., if the norm is sufficiently descriptive, this cannot be the case. In the extreme case where |$\alpha =0$| there are no moral feelings in equilibrium because everybody is choosing the same consumption level that equals the social norm. In this case material and total social welfare coincide.

3. Distributional Effects

We now distinguish two different types of consumers, called rich (r) and poor (p). We assume that both consumer groups have quasi-linear utilities as in (4), but that the rich have a lower marginal utility of money:14
with |$i\in \lbrace r,p\rbrace$|⁠, |$0<\delta := \delta _r \lt \delta _p:= 1$|⁠. The lower marginal utility of money implies that the rich consume more of the harmful good and their utility is less affected by a price increase. This reflects the common observation that wealthy people often do not react much to the prices of the goods they consume. They do not care whether a plastic bag in the supermarket costs an additional fifty cents, they drive an SUV even if fuel consumption is more expensive and they do not give up on vacations to far away destinations just because the flight costs a few hundred dollars more. However, all consumers are affected by moral concerns. It is not obvious whether the rich have stronger or weaker moral concerns than the poor. It could be argued that wealth is correlated with education and that better educated people are more climate conscious. It could also be argued that the rich got rich because they have fewer moral concerns. We do not take a position on this but simply assume that both types of consumers have the same |$\beta$|⁠. We assume that |$\delta \bar{p}\lt \beta \lt \bar{p}$|⁠. For the rich, the perceived maximum price is lower than the moral concern, while it is higher for the poor.

Assumption 1 implies that the regulator will set |$p=\bar{p}$| and choose |$\bar{E}$| such that the resulting permit price is |$\bar{p}$|⁠.15 Furthermore, by Proposition 2, consumers will not buy any offsets, so we can ignore them in their consumption decisions in the following. In this section we are interested in whether the poor or the rich adjust their consumption more under price as compared to quantity regulation. Let |$\Delta _i^j := x_i^N - x_i^j$| denote the adjustment of consumption of consumer group |$i\in \lbrace r,p\rbrace$| under regulation |$j\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$| as compared to the level of consumption |$x_i^N$| that they would choose if there was no regulation. The next proposition characterises these adjustments.16

 
Proposition 6.

Let|$\delta \bar{p}\lt \beta \lt \bar{p}$|⁠. With price regulation both consumer groups reduce their consumption as compared to a situation without regulation, i.e., |$\Delta _p^P \gt 0$|and|$\Delta _r^P \gt 0$|⁠. In contrast, with quantity regulation, the poor reduce their consumption, |$\Delta _p^Q \gt 0$|⁠, while the rich increase it, |$\Delta _r^Q \lt 0$|⁠.

The effect of price regulation is straightforward. The emission price increases the perceived price for both types of consumers, so they will both consume less. The effect of quantity regulation is more involved. Consider first the consumption choices of poor consumers. With no regulation, they perceive the price to be |$c+\beta$| because they have moral concerns and they can affect the total amount of emissions. With quantity regulation, they understand that they cannot affect total emissions, but they have to pay |$\bar{p} \gt \beta$|⁠. Thus, their perceived price increases and they consume less. Now consider the rich. They will increase their consumption as compared to the case of no regulation for two reasons. First, they understand that their consumption does not affect total pollution with quantity regulation, so moral concerns no longer reduce their consumption. Second, because |$\delta \bar{p} \lt \beta$|⁠, they will compensate for their emissions by buying and deleting emission permits. On the one hand, this increases the perceived price by |$\delta \bar{p}$|⁠, because for every unit of X, they will buy an additional emission permit in order to delete it. On the other hand, it increases their utility by |$\beta \gt \delta \bar{p}$|⁠, which reduces the perceived price by |$\beta$|⁠. The overall effect of quantity regulation on the perceived price is negative, and thus they will consume more.

Proposition 6 has some important policy implications. First, the political constraint on the pollution price |$\bar{p}$| is usually determined by poor consumers who suffer more from higher prices than the rich. With quantity regulation, the rich do not reduce their consumption at all but rather increase it, so all the adjustment has to be done by the poor. This makes quantity regulation very ineffective. The larger the fraction of the rich, the smaller the effect of quantity regulation. Second, if the poor see that the rich increase their consumption and ‘buy themselves out’ by buying and deleting emission permits, they may feel that it is unfair that the entire adjustment burden has to be borne by them. To be sure, the poor also benefit from the revenues of emission pricing that are redistributed lump sum to all consumers. Nevertheless, emission pricing is politically more acceptable if the rich and the poor share the burden of adjustment, as they do with price regulation.

4. Uncertainty

In a canonical paper, Weitzman (1974) compared price and quantity regulation in a world with uncertainty. He showed that quantity regulation outperforms price regulation if fluctuations in price are less harmful than fluctuations in quantity of emissions. In contrast, in our set-up quantity regulation always yields a lower level of material efficiency. In this section we show that our results are strengthened if we allow for uncertainty.

Suppose that the benefit from consuming good X is |$\theta v(x)$|⁠, where |$\theta \gt 0$| is a state of nature that is unknown ex ante and distributed according to cumulative distribution function (CDF) |$F(\theta )$| on |$[\underline{\theta }, \bar{\theta }]$|⁠. The state |$\theta$| shifts the marginal abatement cost curve (opportunity costs of reduced consumption). A consumer’s ex post utility is
where the social norm |$x_0^R(\theta )=(1-\alpha )\bar{x}(\theta )+\alpha x^{*}(\theta )$| depends on |$\theta$| and on the regulatory regime |$R\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$|⁠. Material welfare in state |$\theta$| is
The first-best levels of consumption and offsets are characterised by the following first-order conditions:
Differentiating the equation system with respect to |$\theta$| shows that |$dx^{*}/d\theta \gt dz^{*}/d\theta \gt 0$|⁠.

The time structure is as follows. First, the regulator sets the tax p or the quantity of emission permits |$\bar{E}$| without knowing state |$\theta$|⁠. Then the state of nature materialises and is publicly observed. Finally, consumers and the regulator make their purchasing decisions of goods X and Z.

Because the regulator has to fix the price or the quantity before the uncertainty is resolved, he cannot implement the efficient emission level |$x^{*}$| even if there is no upper bound on the emission price p. Sometimes emissions will be too high and sometimes they will be too low. If the marginal damage function is (almost) linear in emissions, a price |$p \approx D^{\prime }(\cdot )$| achieves (almost) the first best and price regulation is optimal. On the other hand, if the marginal damage function is highly convex because of a tipping point at some emission level |$\check{x}$| so that |$x^{*}(\theta )$| is just below |$\check{x}$| for all |$\theta$|⁠, then quantity regulation that sets the quantity just below the tipping point is optimal. This is the famous result of Weitzman (1974). However, with a sufficiently low price cap on p, this result no longer holds, and price regulation is always optimal.

We assume that, for any state |$\theta$|⁠, the price cap |$\bar{p}$| is too low to implement the first-best allocation.

 
Assumption 2.

For all|$\theta \in [\underline{\theta }, \bar{\theta }]$|⁠, |$p\le \bar{p}\le D^{\prime }(x^{*}(\underline{\theta })-z^{*}(\underline{\theta }))-\beta$|⁠.

The next result establishes that, with Assumption 2, price regulation always yields lower consumption and higher material welfare than quantity regulation, independent of the distribution of the state of the world.

 
Proposition 7.

Suppose that there is ex ante uncertainty about|$\theta \in [\underline{\theta }, \bar{\theta }]$|distributed according to some CDF|$F(\theta )$|that affects marginal utility and thereby marginal abatement cost.

  • For any realisation of|$\theta$|⁠, the amount consumed of good X under price regulation is lower than the amount under quantity regulation but higher than the first-best amount, i.e.,
  • Expected material welfare is strictly higher with price than with quantity regulation, i.e.,

To understand the intuition for this result, note that Assumption 2 implies that emissions are always inefficiently high. The regulator has to fix |$\bar{E}$| such that the price never exceeds |$\bar{p}$|⁠. Thus, in most states the emission price will be lower than |$\bar{p}$|⁠. This implies that in these states consumption is higher than under price regulation even if there are no moral concerns. Thus, the introduction of uncertainty unambiguously strengthens our result.

Consumption Decisions of Different Consumer Types.

Table 1.
Consumption Decisions of Different Consumer Types.
SharePrice regulationQuantity regulation
Kantians and naïve utilitarians|$\lambda ^K$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$|
Sophisticated utilitarians|$\lambda ^U$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|
Selfish|$1-\lambda$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|
Total1|$x^P =\lambda \hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$x^Q= \lambda ^K \hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$|
consumption|$+$||$(1-\lambda ) \hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$||$+ (1-\lambda ^K) \hat{x}(c +\bar{p})$|
SharePrice regulationQuantity regulation
Kantians and naïve utilitarians|$\lambda ^K$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$|
Sophisticated utilitarians|$\lambda ^U$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|
Selfish|$1-\lambda$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|
Total1|$x^P =\lambda \hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$x^Q= \lambda ^K \hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$|
consumption|$+$||$(1-\lambda ) \hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$||$+ (1-\lambda ^K) \hat{x}(c +\bar{p})$|
Table 1.
Consumption Decisions of Different Consumer Types.
SharePrice regulationQuantity regulation
Kantians and naïve utilitarians|$\lambda ^K$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$|
Sophisticated utilitarians|$\lambda ^U$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|
Selfish|$1-\lambda$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|
Total1|$x^P =\lambda \hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$x^Q= \lambda ^K \hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$|
consumption|$+$||$(1-\lambda ) \hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$||$+ (1-\lambda ^K) \hat{x}(c +\bar{p})$|
SharePrice regulationQuantity regulation
Kantians and naïve utilitarians|$\lambda ^K$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$|
Sophisticated utilitarians|$\lambda ^U$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|
Selfish|$1-\lambda$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$||$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|
Total1|$x^P =\lambda \hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$||$x^Q= \lambda ^K \hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta )$|
consumption|$+$||$(1-\lambda ) \hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$||$+ (1-\lambda ^K) \hat{x}(c +\bar{p})$|

5. Selfish, Kantian and Naïve Consumers

Welfare economics is based on the assumptions of rational choice and consequentialism, so it is natural to start out with a model in which all consumers are fully rational and moral consequentialists. However, in the real world many consumers are not familiar with the functioning of an emissions market and may fail to understand that their behaviour cannot affect total emissions. They are ‘naïve’ in the sense that they do not see any difference between price and quantity regulation. Furthermore, consumers who are morally concerned need not be consequentialists. Many consumers are better described as deontologists (e.g., Kantians) who aspire to follow an ethical rule or a moral duty, independently of what the consequences of this action are.17

In this section, we allow for different moral convictions and degrees of rationality. We assume that a fraction |$1-\lambda$| of consumers is selfish and has no moral concerns. These consumers simply maximise their material utility. The remaining fraction |$\lambda$| consists of two types of morally concerned consumers—consequentialists as in Section 2 and deontologists—who follow an ethical rule: ‘You shall not consume more than the social norm’. We assume that deontologists are as equally morally strict as consequentialists, so they follow the same social norm |$x_0^R = \alpha x^{*} +(1-\alpha ) x^R$|⁠, but, to a deontologist this social norm applies no matter what the consequences. For concreteness, we call consequentialists ‘utilitarians’ and deontologists ‘Kantians’.

Furthermore, there are naïve utilitarians who do not understand the functioning of an emissions market and believe that any reduction of their emissions reduces total emissions by exactly this amount. In our model Kantian consumers and naïve utilitarian consumers are observationally equivalent.18 Let the share of Kantians and naïve utilitarians in the population be |$\lambda ^K\ge 0$| and the share of sophisticated utilitarians |$\lambda ^U \ge 0$|⁠, |$\lambda ^K + \lambda ^U = \lambda \lt 1$|⁠. To avoid uninteresting case distinctions, we restrict attention to the case where |$\beta \lt \bar{p}$|⁠, so buying and deleting emission rights is not an issue.

With price regulation, all morally concerned consumers choose consumption level |$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p}+\beta )$|⁠, while selfish consumers consume more and choose |$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|⁠. This gives rise to total emissions |$x^P= \lambda \hat{x}(c+\bar{p}+\beta ) + (1-\lambda ) \hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|⁠.19 With quantity regulation, sophisticated utilitarian consumers act like selfish consumers, so their consumption is |$\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|⁠. Selfish, Kantian and naïve utilitarian consumers do not change their behaviour as compared to a regime with price regulation. Thus, total consumption and pollution is given by |$x^Q=\lambda ^K \hat{x}(c+\bar{p} + \beta ) + (1-\lambda ^K) \hat{x}(c +\bar{p})$|⁠. The social planner will set the quantity of emission permits |$\bar{E}$| such that |$\bar{E} = x^Q(\bar{p})$|⁠, which gives rise to emission price |$\bar{p}$|⁠. Because utilitarians consume more under quantity regulation while all others do not change their behaviour, total emissions are higher with quantity than with price regulation, as in Section 3.

The focus of this section is on the effects of a political or educational campaign that changes the composition of the population. For example, a new report of the IPCC or a political movement (e.g., ‘Fridays for Future’) may raise the awareness of climate change and turn some selfish consumers into climate-conscious consumers. The government could also make an effort to better explain the functioning of an emissions market to the public, thereby reducing the share of naïve consumers. Because these campaigns change the preferences of some part of the population, we cannot compare social welfare before and after the policy change. However, we can assess how consumers who did not change their type are affected, which gives rise to important distributional effects.

 
Proposition 8 (Price regulation).

Suppose that the share of climate-conscious consumers|$\lambda$|increases. With price regulation, all consumers (both selfish and moral) who did not change their type benefit from the conversion of some selfish to moral consumers.

If a selfish consumer gets morally concerned, she consumes less and total pollution is reduced. The consumption choices of selfish and climate-conscious consumers who did not change their type are unaffected, but both types benefit from the reduction of pollution. There is also a negative effect on all consumers because tax revenues go down and less money can be redistributed. Furthermore, moral types are adversely affected because the social norm gets stricter. However, under Assumption 1, these effects are dominated by the positive effect of less pollution.

Consider now the case of quantity regulation and assume that the number of emission rights |$\bar{E}$| is fixed.20

 
Proposition 9 (Quantity regulation).

Suppose that the share of morally concerned consumers|$\lambda$|increases and that|$\beta \lt \bar{p}$|⁠.

  1. If the share of sophisticated utilitarians|$\lambda ^U$|increases, there is no effect.

  2. If the share of Kantian and naïve utilitarian consumer|$\lambda ^K$|increases, the demand for emission permits is reduced. Because the supply of emission permits is fixed, total pollution is unaffected, but the pollution price goes down. Selfish and sophisticated utilitarian consumers unambiguously benefit from the price decrease, while Kantian and naïve utilitarian consumers are strictly worse off.

With a fixed emission cap, an increase in the share of Kantian consumers cannot affect total pollution, but it does affect the permit price p. A decrease in p has three effects: it reduces the amount |$px$| that consumers have to pay for their consumption x, it reduces the lump-sum redistribution |$p\bar{x}$| that each consumer gets and it affects the individual consumption decisions. At the margin, the last effect is positive but has a second-order effect on utility due to the envelope theorem. Because selfish and sophisticated utilitarian consumers consume more than |$\bar{x}$|⁠, they benefit from the price reduction, while Kantian and naïve utilitarian consumers consume less than |$\bar{x}$| and therefore lose out.

These propositions show that, with price regulation, total emissions are reduced and everybody benefits if the population gets more climate conscious. With quantity regulation, however, only selfish and sophisticated utilitarian consumers benefit, while Kantian and naïve utilitarian consumer lose out, and there is no effect on total emissions. Thus, quantity regulation gives rise to perverse incentive effects: Kantian consumers have no material interest to convince selfish consumers to follow their moral duty, and nobody wants to educate naïve utilitarians about the functioning of the emissions market.

6. Conclusions

Many consumers are morally concerned about their carbon footprint. They are prepared to voluntarily reduce emissions by saving energy, investing in renewables or changing their consumption patterns. With an emission tax (price regulation) climate action by climate-conscious consumers reduces total emissions. In contrast, with cap and trade (quantity regulation) these efforts do not affect total pollution and are discouraged. The difference between price and quantity regulation is amplified if consumers can compensate for their emissions by buying and deleting emission permits or by investing in offsets.

Our analysis applies not only to consumption decisions of consumers. Many firms are pressured by their customers, employees and shareholders to make substantial efforts to reduce carbon emissions. For example, Blake Morgen listed 101 multinational companies that are committed to becoming carbon neutral in the near future on Forbes.com in 2019.21 Similarly, many (regional) governments are pressured by voters to make significant efforts to reduce CO2 emissions. The European Green Deal and the climate action of the Biden administration are prominent examples. In addition, many US states impose clean energy standards to reduce non-renewable energy consumption and to increase the production of renewable energy. In the EU, several countries heavily subsidise the production of solar and wind energy. Germany alone has spent about 300 billion Euros since 2001 to subsidise renewable energy, and it wants to spend another 40 billion Euros to shut down all coal-fired power stations until 2038. These initiatives are often on top of cap-and-trade systems, such as the Regional Greenhouse Gas Initiative and the Western Climate Initiative in North America or the Emissions Trading System (ETS) in the EU, and so have little or no effect on total emissions. However, as long as the carbon price is too low, additional carbon action is urgently needed to achieve the two-degree goal. With cap and trade, these additional efforts are largely wasted and discouraged. With price regulation, these measures would be more effective and, as we show, voters would have a stronger incentive to push for them.

Furthermore, quantity regulation gives rise to dysfunctional distribution and incentive effects. It shifts the burden of adjustment to the poor while the rich buy themselves out and may even increase their consumption. Climate action of morally concerned agents lowers the carbon price and thereby subsidises consumption of those who are less environmentally conscious. There are no incentives for Kantian consumers to convince selfish consumers to become climate conscious and for selfish consumers to educate ‘naïve’ consumers about the functioning of cap and trade. In contrast, with price regulation, rich and poor households have similar incentives to reduce their carbon emissions. Furthermore, everybody benefits if agents are motivated to take climate action. These are powerful arguments in favour of price regulation that policymakers should take into account.

Appendix A

A1. Affordable Offsets at a Large Scale

So far, we assumed that the scope for offsets is small. In this section, we briefly consider the case where offsets can be produced with constant returns to scale at a constant unit cost |$\bar{q}$|⁠. This case might become relevant in the future when the technology for carbon capture and storage matures. Note that, if |$\bar{q} \lt \bar{p}$|⁠, the carbon price would be inefficiently high, so in this case the political constraint would no longer be binding. Thus, we restrict attention to the more interesting case where |$\bar{q}\ge \bar{p}$|⁠. Furthermore, we assume that the regulator can buy only a limited amount of offsets |$\bar{z}^G$|⁠. If he wanted to buy more, he would have to raise taxes, which would infuriate the electorate.

 
Assumption A1.

Offsets can be produced with constant marginal cost|$\bar{q} \ge \bar{p}$|⁠. No matter whether there is price or quantity regulation, the regulator is constrained to buy a limited number of offsets|$\bar{z}^G$|that is inefficiently small.

Assumptions 1 and A1 imply that the regulator will set |$p=\bar{p}$| under price regulation, he will set |$\bar{E}$| such that the resulting permit price is |$\bar{p}$| under quantity regulation and he will always buy the maximum amount of offsets |$z^G = \bar{z}^G$|⁠.

With quantity regulation, consumers will not buy offsets, but rather buy and delete emission permits that are equally efficient and cheaper.22 Thus, the analysis of quantity regulation remains unchanged.

With price regulation, however, consumers will buy offsets if |$\beta \ge \bar{q}$|⁠. By Lemma 1 we have
and
Note that consumption of X decreases with |$\beta$| as long as |$\beta \lt \bar{q}$| and stays constant for |$\beta \ge \bar{q}$|⁠. The reason is that consumers do not reduce their consumption, but buy offsets if |$\beta \ge \bar{q}$|⁠. Consumption is independent of |$\beta$| for |$\beta \ge \bar{q}$|⁠, and so is the number of offsets bought. The possibility to buy offsets increases the efficiency of price regulation because the social cost of reducing consumption beyond |$x(c+\bar{p} +\bar{q})$| is higher than the social cost of buying offsets. For this reason, we get the same qualitative results as in Propositions 4 and 5.
 
Proposition A1.
Suppose that Assumptions1 and A1hold. For any|$\beta \gt 0$|⁠, optimal price regulation implements an emission level|${\cal E}^P$|that is inefficiently high but strictly smaller than the level of emissions|${\cal E}^Q$|under optimal quantity regulation, i.e.,
Furthermore, because price regulation is more efficient if consumers can buy offsets at a constant price|$\bar{q} \le \beta$|⁠, the welfare comparison of Proposition5continues to hold.

A2. Imperfect Competition

We now consider the effect of imperfect competition. Suppose that good X is produced by symmetrically differentiated firms that are able to charge a markup |$\mu ^R \gt 0$|⁠, so the monetary price for good X is |$c+\mu ^R + \bar{p}$|⁠. Note that the markup may depend on the regulatory regime |$R\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$|⁠. The reason is that, depending on the type of regulation, the consumer faces a different ‘moral price’ that depends on her moral concerns |$\beta ^R$|⁠. We assume that the moral price (including the markup) is always too low to implement the welfare optimal consumption level. Furthermore, we assume that, with quantity regulation, there is perfect competition on the emissions market. The following proposition shows that our main result still holds under a weak condition.

 
Proposition A2.

Suppose that good X is produced by symmetrically differentiated firms that charge markup|$\mu ^R(\beta )$|in regulatory regime|$R\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$|in equilibrium. If|$-1 \lt d\mu ^P/d\beta$|and|$d\mu ^Q/d\beta \lt 1$|then|$x^{*} \lt x^P \lt x^Q$|and|$W^M(x^P, z^P) \gt W^M(x^Q,z^Q)$|⁠.

Note that, with price regulation, an increase in |$\beta$| has the same effect as an increase in an excise tax imposed on consumption. Thus, |$d\mu ^P/d\beta \gt -1$| requires that firms do not reduce the price of the good by more than the tax increase, so the effective price paid by consumers goes up because of the tax. With quantity regulation, an increase in |$\beta$| has the same effect as an increase in a subsidy on consumption (if |$\beta \gt \bar{p}$|⁠; otherwise, there is no effect). Thus, |$\mu ^Q/d\beta \lt 1$| requires that firms do not increase the price by more than the increase in subsidy. Thus, the effective price paid by consumers goes down because of the subsidy. This second condition is of course equivalent to the first condition on a tax increase. This condition is empirically very plausible and satisfied in many oligopoly models.23

Thus, the only effect of market power is that it increases the price and thus reduces the consumption of good X without affecting the ordering. This brings quantities closer to the first-best quantity, but price regulation still outperforms quantity regulation.

A3. Proofs

 
Proof of Lemma 1.

The result follows directly from the analysis preceding the lemma.

 
Proof of Proposition 1.

The result follows directly from Lemma 1 and the definitions of |$x^{*}$| and |$z^{*}$|⁠.

 
Proof of Proposition 2.
Consider the second-best amount of offsets |$\hat{z}$|⁠. Note that
(A1)
Thus, for |$x^R\gt x^{*}$|⁠, we have |$\hat{z}(x^R)\gt z^{*}$|⁠. This implies that |$q=k^{\prime }(\hat{z}(x))\gt k^{\prime }(z^{*})\gt \beta$|⁠, where the final inequality follows from Assumption 1. Hence, if the regulator chooses |$z^G$| optimally for any |$x^R\gt x^{*}$| implemented by the regulation, no consumer buys offsets. This follows directly from |$q\gt \beta$|⁠.
If the regulator chooses z optimally given |$x^R$|⁠, material welfare,
is solely a function of |$x^R$|⁠. From the envelope theorem, it follows that
and using (A1), we get
Material welfare |$W^M(x^R,\hat{z}(x^R))$| is a strictly concave function of |$x^R$| that is maximised at |$x^R=x^{*}$|⁠, where |$\hat{z}(x^{*})=z^{*}$|⁠. Thus, the regulator is interested in implementing the lowest feasible |$x^R$|⁠. Under price regulation, this is achieved by setting |$p=\bar{p}$|⁠. Under quantity regulation, he sets the number of emission permits |$\bar{E}$| so that the resulting permit price is |$\bar{p}$|⁠.
 
Proof of Proposition 3.
Consider price regulation first. By Proposition 2 we know that the regulator sets |$p=\bar{p}$| and buys the second-best optimal amount of offsets, while consumers do not buy any offsets. Thus, demand for good X is given by
The higher the moral concerns of consumers (higher |$\beta$|⁠), the lower is consumption of the harmful good. Since all consumers are identical, the norm violation is given by
Now, consider quantity regulation. The regulator chooses |$\bar{E}$| such that the resulting permit price is |$\bar{p}$|⁠. By similar arguments as above, |$q\gt \beta$| and thus consumers do not purchase offsets, but they may buy and delete emission permits:
Anticipating this, the consumer’s demand for good X is
Consumption is independent of |$\beta$| until |$\beta =\bar{p}$|⁠. Thereafter consumption is increasing with |$\beta$|⁠. The consumer anticipates that she will buy and delete one emission permit for every additional unit of consumption. The cost of this is |$\bar{p}$|⁠, but the benefit is |$\beta \ge \bar{p}$|⁠. Thus, the larger |$\beta$|⁠, the more the consumer enjoys buying and deleting emission rights and so the more she will consume. Note that |$x_0^Q=\alpha x^{*} + (1-\alpha ) \hat{x} (c+2\bar{p} -\beta )$|⁠, so we can write
The regulator sets the total number of emission rights such that |$p=\bar{p}$|⁠, i.e.,
Substituting |$e^Q$| and rearranging yields

Note that, for |$\beta \lt \bar{p}$|⁠, the total number of emission rights is unaffected by |$\beta$|⁠. However, if |$\beta \ge \bar{p}$|⁠, the total number of emission rights increases with |$\beta$|⁠.

 
Proof of Proposition 4.

By (A1), a higher x leads to a higher z. The increase in z due to an increase in x, however, is less than 1. This leads to the ordering provided in the proposition.

 
Proof of Proposition 5.

Part (i) follows from the observation that |$W^M(x,\hat{z}(x))$| is a strictly concave function that is maximised at |$x^{*}$|⁠, and the ordering of the consumption levels provided by Proposition 3.

Part (ii).Note that |$x^P=\hat{x}(c+\bar{p}+\beta )$| is a decreasing function in |$\beta$|⁠. Moreover, |$x^Q=\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$| for |$\beta \lt \bar{p}$| and |$x^Q=\hat{x}(c+2\bar{p}-\beta )$| for |$\beta \ge \bar{p}$|⁠. Thus, |$x^Q$| is a (weakly) increasing function in |$\beta$|⁠. The result then follows from the arguments made in part (i).

Part (iii) follows directly from the definition of total social welfare (5).

 
Proof of Proposition 6.

Recall that |$\hat{x}(\pi )$| is the optimal consumption of a consumer who faces the perceived price |$\pi$|⁠. We distinguish three cases.

  1. No regulation. If there is no regulation, the emission price is |$p=0$| and there is no quantity constraint. Consumers know that they can affect emissions with their consumption. The perceived price for the poor is |$\pi =c+\beta$|⁠, while it is |$\pi = \delta c + \beta$| for the rich. Thus,
  2. Price regulation. With price regulation, the perceived price for the poor is |$\pi =c+\bar{p}+\beta$|⁠, while for the rich it is |$\pi =\delta (c+\bar{p})+\beta$|⁠, so we have
  3. Quantity regulation. With quantity regulation, the perceived price for the poor is |$\pi =c+\bar{p}$|⁠. The rich will buy and delete emission rights in order to compensate emissions, so their perceived price is |$\pi =\delta (c+2\bar{p})-\beta$|⁠. Thus we have

With price regulation we get
Both consumer groups reduce their consumption because the perceived price increases. However, with quantity regulation we get
Because |$\beta \lt \bar{p}$|⁠, the poor perceive a higher price and reduce their consumption, while the rich will buy and delete emission permits and increase their consumption. This follows from |$\delta \bar{p} \lt \beta$|⁠, which implies that |$\delta c+ \beta \gt \delta (c+\bar{p}) \gt \delta (c + \bar{p}) - (\beta - \delta \bar{p}) = \delta (c+2\bar{p}) - \beta$|⁠.
 
Proof of Proposition 7.

Assumption 2 implies that |$\beta \lt k^{\prime }(z^{*}(\underline{\theta }))$|⁠. If the regulator purchases the second-best amount of offsets |$z^G=\hat{z}(\bar{x},\theta )=\text{arg}\max _{\bar{z}} W^M(\bar{x},\bar{z}|\theta )$| then |$q\gt \beta$|⁠. This implies that consumers never purchase any offsets.

Let |$x^R=x^R(p,\theta )$| be the amount consumed under regulation R for permit price/tax |$p\le \bar{p}$|⁠. Expected material welfare is
(A2)
The integrand of the above expression is a strictly concave function in |$x^R$| that is maximised at |$x^R=x^{*}(\theta )$|⁠. Note that, for |$x^R=x^{*}(\theta )$|⁠, we have |$\hat{z}=z^{*}(\theta )$|⁠.
Under price regulation, the demanded quantity |$x^P(p,\theta )$| is implicitly defined by
(A3)
The quantity |$x^P(p,\theta )$| is decreasing in p and increasing in |$\theta$|⁠. Under Assumption 2, the consumed amount is too high from a welfare point of view for any |$\theta$|⁠. Thus, the regulator optimally specifies |$p=\bar{p}$|⁠.
Under quantity regulation, the amount consumed of good X, |$x^Q(p,\theta )$|⁠, solves
(A4)
Demand for good X is decreasing in p and increasing in |$\theta$|⁠. While consumers do not purchase offsets in equilibrium, they may buy and delete emission permits under quantity regulation. By Lemma 1, a consumer’s demand for emission permits is
Demand for good X is too high from a welfare point of view. Thus, the regulator will choose |$\bar{E}$| as low as possible so that |$p\le \bar{p}$| in any state |$\theta$|⁠. The demand for emission permits is |$E(p,\theta )=x^Q(p,\theta )+e^Q(p,\theta )$|⁠. Let the market clearing price be |$p^{*}(\theta )$|⁠, i.e., |$E(p^{*}(\theta ),\theta )=\bar{E}$|⁠. Since demand varies with the state of nature, the condition |$p^{*}(\theta )\le \bar{p}$| implies that, with quantity regulation, the permit price is often strictly lower than the upper bound.

The two statements of the proposition now follow readily.

  • From (A3) and (A4), it follows directly that, for any given price |$p\le \bar{p}$|⁠, |$x^P(p,\theta )\lt x^Q(p,\theta )$| for all |$\theta$|⁠. Furthermore, demand is always decreasing in the price and the equilibrium permit price |$p^{*}(\theta )\le \bar{p}$|⁠, while the emission tax is always equal to |$\bar{p}$|⁠. This increases the difference between |$x^P(\theta , \bar{p})$| and |$x^Q(\theta ,p^{*}(\theta ))$|⁠. Finally, by Assumption 2, it holds that |$x^{*}(\theta )\lt x^P(\bar{p},\theta )$| for all |$\theta$|⁠.

  • Ex post material welfare—the integrand of (A2)—is strictly concave in |$x^R$| and maximised at |$x^R=x^{*}(\theta )$|⁠. Thus, part (i) directly implies that ex post material welfare is strictly higher under price than quantity regulation for any state |$\theta$|⁠. Hence, expected material welfare is also higher.

 
Proof of Proposition 8.
Share |$\lambda$| chooses |$x^m:=\hat{x}(c+\bar{p}+\beta )$| and share |$1-\lambda$| chooses |$x^s:=\hat{x}(c+\bar{p})$|⁠, with |$x^s\gt x^m$|⁠. Total consumption is
An increase in |$\lambda$| reduces the consumption of those selfish consumers that have been turned into moral consumers. It does not affect the consumption decisions of consumers who did not change type. Material welfare is given by
The regulator purchases the second-best amount of offsets, |$\hat{z}(x^P)$|⁠, implicitly defined by |$D^{\prime }(x^P-\hat{z})=k^{\prime }(\hat{z})$|⁠. Note that |$d\hat{z}/d x^P\in (0,1)$|⁠. With |$x^P\gt x^{*}$| we have |$\hat{z}(x^P)\gt z^{*}$|⁠, which implies that |$q=k^{\prime }(\hat{z}(x^P))\gt k^{\prime }(z^{*})\gt \beta$|⁠. Hence, consumers do not purchase offsets.
The utility of selfish consumers is
The effect of an increase in |$\lambda$| on those selfish consumers that stay selfish is
Recall that |$k^{\prime }(\cdot )-D^{\prime }(\cdot )=0$| by the definition of |$\hat{z}$| and that |$D^{\prime }(\cdot )-\bar{p}\gt 0$| by Assumption 1. A reduction of aggregate consumption affects selfish consumers because it reduces the tax revenues that are redistributed lump sum to consumers and it reduces pollution. Furthermore, it induces the regulator to buy more offsets that have to be paid for by lump-sum taxes. However, due to the envelope theorem, this latter effect is of second order.
The utility of moral (K and U) consumers is
(A5)
We assumed that |$\alpha \gt [x^s-x^m]/[x^s-x^{*}]$| so that |$x^m\gt x^P_0$| (see footnote 19). Differentiation of (A5) with respect to |$\lambda$| yields
Note that |$k^{\prime }(\cdot )-D^{\prime }(\cdot )=0$| by the definition of |$\hat{z}$| and that |$D^{\prime }(\cdot )-\bar{p}-\beta \gt 0$| by Assumption 1. The effect on moral consumers (U and K) is similar to that on selfish (S) consumers. There is an additional effect because the reduced aggregate consumption makes the social norm stricter, which has an additional negative effect on the utility of moral consumers. However, the total effect is still positive.
 
Proof of Proposition 9.

The amount of emission permits is fixed to |$\bar{E}=x^Q(\bar{p})$|⁠. This implies that (i) total consumption is fixed, (ii) the regulator does not have to adjust |$z^G=\hat{z}(\bar{E})$| and (iii) thus that net emissions are also constant. The social norm does not change either. The only effect of an increase of |$\lambda ^K$| is that it affects the emission price p.

Note that |$q=k^{\prime }(\hat{z}(\bar{E}))\gt k^{\prime }(z^{*})\gt \beta$| and that we assumed that |$\beta \lt \bar{p}$|⁠. Thus, consumers neither purchase offsets nor emission permits. Share |$\lambda ^K$| chooses |$x^m=\hat{x}(c+p+\beta )$| and share |$1-\lambda ^K$| chooses |$x^s=\hat{x}(c+p)$|⁠. Let |$p^Q$| be the market clearing permit price, i.e.,
(A6)
Implicit differentiation of (A6) with respect to |$\lambda ^K$| yields
We consider a marginal increase in |$\lambda ^K$| so that |$\bar{p}\gt p^Q\gt \beta$|⁠.
The utility of selfish and sophisticated utilitarian consumers is
We differentiate the above expression with respect to |$\lambda ^K$| and obtain
Note that |$v^{\prime }(x^s)=c+p^Q$| by the definition of |$x^s$|⁠.
The utility of Kantian and naïve utilitarian consumers is
Differentiating the above expression with respect to |$\lambda ^K$| yields
To obtain the final line, we used the fact that |$\bar{E}=\lambda ^K x^m+(1-\lambda ^K)x^s$| and that, by the definition of |$x^m$|⁠, it holds that |$v^{\prime }(x^m)=c+p^Q+\beta$|⁠.
 
Proof of Proposition A1.

The proof follows the lines of the proofs of Propositions 4 and 5.

 
Proof of Proposition A2.

Note first that, for any consumed quantity of good X, the government buys the second-best optimal amount of offsets |$\hat{z}(x)$|⁠. As in Section 2, this leads to a price q for good Z that is so high that |$z^C=0$| (irrespective of the regulatory regime).

By Lemma 1, the demand for good X under price regulation is
and under quantity regulation is
where |$\mu ^R$| is the equilibrium markup charged by firms under regulatory regime |$R\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$|⁠. The markup |$\mu ^R$| depends on the regime because the regime affects the ‘moral price’ paid by consumers and thereby the relevant section of the demand curve |$\hat{x}(\cdot )$| at which firms choose their markup.

Note that if |$\beta =0$| then there is no difference in the demand function between price and quantity regulation and the equilibrium markup must be the same. For |$\beta \gt 0$|⁠, we have |$x^P(\beta ) \lt x^Q(\beta )$| if and only if |$\mu ^P+\beta \gt \mu ^Q -\max \lbrace \beta -\bar{p},0\rbrace$|⁠. Two cases have to be distinguished.

  • If |$\beta \lt \bar{p}$|⁠, we have |$x^P(\beta ) \lt x^Q(\beta )$| if and only if |$\mu ^P+\beta \gt \mu ^Q$|⁠. Note that in this case |$\mu ^Q$| is independent of |$\beta$| while |$\mu ^P$| may vary with |$\beta$|⁠. However, if |$d\mu ^P/d\beta \gt -1$|⁠, it must be the case that |$x^P(\beta )$| decreases with |$\beta$| (starting at |$\beta =0$|⁠) while |$x^Q(\beta )$| stays constant. Therefore, |$x^P(\beta ) \lt x^Q(\beta )$|⁠.

  • If |$\beta \ge \bar{p}$|⁠, we have |$x^P(\beta ) \lt x^Q(\beta )$| if and only if |$\mu ^P+\beta \gt \mu ^Q - (\beta -\bar{p})$|⁠. By (i) we know that at |$\beta =\bar{p}$| we have |$x^P(\beta ) \lt x^Q(\beta )$|⁠. If |$d\mu ^P/d\beta \gt -1$| then |$x^P(\beta )$| decreases as |$\beta$| further increases. Furthermore, if |$d\mu ^Q/d\beta \lt 1$| then |$x^Q(\beta )$| increases as |$\beta$| increases. Therefore, as |$\beta$| increases, the difference between |$x^Q(\beta )$| and |$x^P(\beta )$| gets larger.

Thus, the ordering of quantities is not affected by the introduction of market power. The remaining question is whether this also holds for material welfare. Note that firms are owned by consumers. Thus, firms’ profits increase consumers’ income one to one. Therefore, the only effect of market power on material welfare is the reduced consumption of good X. By the proof of Proposition 2 we know that |$d W^M(\bar{x},\hat{z}(\bar{x}))/d\bar{x} \lt 0$| for |$\bar{x}\gt x^{*}$|⁠. We can therefore conclude that
This completes the proof.

Footnotes

1

We use the terms ‘climate-conscious’, ‘morally motivated’ and ‘morally concerned’ consumers interchangeably.

2

According to the IPCC (2022, AR 6 WG III, Box TS. 10, p. TS-94) the estimated mitigation potential for direct air carbon capture and storage (DACCS) is moderate to large despite its limited current deployment. Moreover, the IPCC points out that ‘removing CO2 from the atmosphere and durably storing it [...] is necessary to achieve net zero CO2 and GHG emissions [...]’.

3

While private households cannot directly purchase emission permits on most emission trading markets, there exist several organisations that offer to buy and delete permits on their behalf. For the EU ETS, such buy and delete programs for carbon emissions are offered by Carbonkiller (https://carbonkiller.org/en), Compensators (www.compensators.org), 50ZERO (https://50zero.eu/) or ForTomorrow (www.fortomorrow.eu/en).

4

The optimal mixture of the two instruments is analysed, among others, by Roberts and Spence (1976), Pizer (2002), Mandell (2008) and Ambec and Coria (2013).

5

Goulder (2013), Schmalensee and Stavins (2017) and Narassimhan et al. (2018) provided overviews and evaluations of real-world cap-and-trade systems.

6

For surveys of this literature, see Ledyard (1995) and Chaudhuri (2011).

7

Material welfare is a strictly concave function. To see this, note that |$\partial ^2 W^M/\partial \bar{x}^2\lt 0$|⁠, |$\partial ^2 W^M/\partial \bar{z}^2\lt 0$|⁠, and

The imposed Inada conditions ensure that |$0\lt z^{*}\lt x^{*}$|⁠.

8

The distinction between injunctive and descriptive norms goes back to Cialdini et al. (1990). They defined a descriptive norm as ‘what most other people do’. In contrast, ‘injunctive norms specify what ought to be done’. This should not be confused with the legal definition of an ‘injunctive norm’.

9

For additional supportive philosophical arguments, see Tiefensee (2019).

10

If |$\beta =q$| (⁠|$\beta =p$|⁠, respectively) the consumer is indifferent whether or not to purchase offsets (whether or not to buy and delete emission rights). Without loss of generality we assume that she chooses to compensate in this knife-edge case.

11

If aggregate consumption |$x^R\lt x_0^R =\alpha x^{*} + (1-\alpha ) x^R$| then we have |$x^R \lt x^{*}$|⁠, so consumers consume too little. In this case the regulator would lower the emission tax or increase the number of emission permits up to the point where |$x^R = x^{*}$|⁠.

12

See Carattini et al. (2018; 2019) for a discussion of why carbon pricing is so unpopular.

13

A modest role for offsets seems to be the realistic case at the current state of technology. The space required to plant trees or restore moors is limited and the opportunity cost of using land for this purpose increases rapidly. However, it is conceivable that at some point in the future it becomes possible to use carbon capture and storage at a large scale and at an affordable cost. Therefore, in Appendix A1 we consider the case where the marginal cost of producing offsets is constant and sufficiently small, so that it would be efficient to have a ‘large’ amount of offsets.

14

Alternatively, we could have assumed that the rich have a higher marginal utility from consuming good X and higher moral concerns |$\beta$|⁠.

15

Note that, for rich consumers, an even higher price p is necessary to implement the respective optimal consumption level.

16

Strictly speaking, the result requires that the poor, who consume less than the rich and thus less than average consumption, consume more than the social norm. Let the consumption of type |$i\in \lbrace r,p\rbrace$| under regime |$R\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$| be |$x^R_i$|⁠. Fraction μ of the population is poor and fraction |$1-\mu$| is rich, so that average consumption is |$\bar{x}^R=\mu x_p^R+(1-\mu ) x_r^R$|⁠. The welfare optimal average consumption is |$x^{*}=\mu x_p^{*}+(1-\mu )x_r^{*}$|⁠, where |$x_i^{*}$| is implicitly defined by |$v^{\prime }(x_i^{*})=\delta _i c+D^{\prime }(x^{*}-z^{*})$|⁠. If the norm is sufficiently injunctive (⁠|$\alpha$| sufficiently large) and there are not too many rich consumers (μ is large), then |$x^P_p\gt x^0=\alpha x^{*}+(1-\alpha )\bar{x}^R$|⁠. Note that if this holds then, for all |$R\in \lbrace P,Q\rbrace$|⁠, it holds that |$x^0\lt x^j_p\lt x_r^j$|⁠.

17

Kantian decision makers are also analysed by Roemer (2010) and Alger and Weibull (2016).

18

For Kantian consumers, it does not matter whether they are naïve or sophisticated.

19

This assumes that |$x \gt x_0$| for all morally concerned consumers, which is the case if |$\alpha$| is sufficiently large:

20

An increase in the number of Kantian consumers reduces the emission price. Thus, the regulator could respond by reducing the number of emission rights. However, many existing emissions markets fixed the number of emission rights for many years. For example, in the European Emissions Trading System the amount is fixed until 2030.

22

If |$\bar{p} = \bar{q}$|⁠, consumers are indifferent. In this case we assume that they will buy and delete emission permits.

23

For example, it is always satisfied in symmetric Cournot models for any demand functions as long as the the stability conditions for a Cournot equilibrium hold. See Vives (1999, p. 104).

Notes

We would like to thank Stephan Klasen whose ‘Farewell Lecture’ in Göttingen inspired this paper. We are grateful for comments made by the editor, Steffen Huck, three anonymous referees, Helmut Bester, Friedrich Breyer, Paul Heidhues, Frikk Nesje, Grischa Perino, Jean Tirole, Jonas von Wangenheim, seminar and conference participants in Amsterdam, Basel, Bayreuth, Berlin, Bielefeld, Duisburg, Hamburg, Munich, Portsmouth, Zürich, the Bavarian Micro Day, Meeting of Theoretischer Ausschuss, and the CESifo Conference on Energy and Climate Economics. Financial support by Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft through CRC-TRR 190 (project number 280092119) is gratefully acknowledged.

References

Aghion
P.
,
Bénabou
R.
,
Martin
R.
,
Roulet
A.
(
2020
).
‘Environmental preferences and technological choices: Is market competition clean or dirty?’
,
Working Paper 26921, National Bureau of Economic Research
.

Alger
I.
,
Weibull
J.W.
(
2016
).
‘Evolution and Kantian morality’
,
Games and Economic Behavior
, vol.
98
, pp.
56
67
.

Allcott
H.
,
Rogers
T.
(
2014
).
‘The short-run and long-run effects of behavioral interventions: Experimental evidence from energy conservation’
,
American Economic Review
, vol.
104
(
10
), pp.
3003
37
.

Ambec
S.
,
Coria
J.
(
2013
).
‘Prices vs quantities with multiple pollutants’
,
Journal of Environmental Economics and Management
, vol.
66
(
1
), pp.
123
40
.

Ambec
S.
,
De Donder
P.
(
2022
).
‘Environmental policy with green consumerism’
,
Journal of Environmental Economics and Management
, vol.
111
,
102584
.

Bartling
B.
,
Weber
R.A.
,
Yao
L.
(
2015
).
‘Do markets erode social responsibility?’
,
The Quarterly Journal of Economics
, vol.
130
(
1
), pp.
219
66
.

Baumol
W.J.
,
Oates
W.E.
(
1988
).
The Theory of Environmental Policy
,
Cambridge
:
Cambridge University Press
.

Bénabou
R.
,
Falk
A.
,
Tirole
J.
(
2018
).
‘Narratives, imperatives, and moral reasoning’
,
Working Paper 24798, National Bureau of Economic Research
.

Bénabou
R.
,
Tirole
J.
(
2006
).
‘Incentives and prosocial behavior’
,
American Economic Review
, vol.
96
(
5
), pp.
1652
78
.

Carattini
S.
,
Carvalho
M.
,
Fankhauser
S.
(
2018
).
‘Overcoming public resistance to carbon taxes’
,
Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews. Climate Change
, vol.
9
(
5
),
e531
.

Carattini
S.
,
Kallbekken
S.
,
Orlov
A.
(
2019
).
‘How to win public support for a global carbon tax’
,
Nature
, vol.
565
(
7739
), pp.
289
91
.

Chaudhuri
A.
(
2011
).
‘Sustaining cooperation in laboratory public goods experiments: A selective survey of the literature’
,
Experimental Economics
, vol.
14
(
1
), pp.
47
83
.

Cialdini
R.B.
,
Reno
R.R.
,
Kallgren
C.A.
(
1990
).
‘A focus theory of normative conduct: Recycling the concept of norms to reduce littering in public places’
,
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
, vol.
58
(
6
), pp.
1015
26
.

Coase
R.
(
1960
).
‘The problem of social cost’
,
Journal of Law and Economics
, vol.
3
(
1
), pp.
1
44
.

Dewatripont
M.
,
Tirole
J.
(
2022
).
‘The morality of markets’
,
Working Paper, Toulouse School of Economics
.

Eichner
T.
,
Pethig
R.
(
2020
).
‘Kantians defy the economists’ mantra of uniform Pigovian emissions taxes’
,
Working Paper 8749, CESifo
.

Fankhauser
S.
,
Hepburn
C.
,
Park
J.
(
2010
).
‘Combining multiple climate policy instruments: How not to do it’
,
Climate Change Economics
, vol.
1
(
3
), pp.
209
25
.

Goulder
L.H.
(
2013
).
‘Markets for pollution allowances: What are the (new) lessons?’
,
Journal of Economic Perspectives
, vol.
27
(
1
), pp.
87
102
.

Goulder
L.H.
,
Jacobsen
M.R.
,
van Benthem
A.A.
(
2012
).
‘Unintended consequences from nested state and federal regulations: The case of the Pavley greenhouse-gas-per-mile limits’
,
Journal of Environmental Economics and Management
, vol.
63
(
2
), pp.
187
207
.

Goulder
L.H.
,
Schein
A.R.
(
2013
).
‘Carbon taxes versus cap and trade: A critical review’
,
Climate Change Economics
, vol.
4
(
3
),
1350010
.

Grafton
R.Q.
,
Kompas
T.
,
Van Long
N.
(
2017
).
‘A brave new world? Kantian–Nashian interaction and the dynamics of global climate change mitigation’
,
European Economic Review
, vol.
99
, pp.
31
42
.

Helm
D.
(
2005
).
‘Economic instruments and environmental policy’
,
Economic and Social Review
, vol.
36
(
3
), pp.
205
28
.

Hepburn
C.
(
2006
).
‘Regulation by prices, quantities, or both: A review of instrument choice’
,
Oxford Review of Economic Policy
, vol.
22
(
2
), pp.
226
47
.

Hoel
M.
,
Karp
L.
(
2002
).
‘Taxes versus quotas for a stock pollutant’
,
Resource and Energy Economics
, vol.
24
(
4
), pp.
367
84
.

IPCC
. (
2022
).
Climate Change 2022: Mitigation of Climate Change
,
Working Group III report
, Technical Summary,
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change
.

Jakob
M.
,
Kübler
D.
,
Steckel
J.C.
,
van Veldhuizen
R.
(
2017
).
‘Clean up your own mess: An experimental study of moral responsibility and efficiency’
,
Journal of Public Economics
, vol.
155
, pp.
138
46
.

Krupka
E.L.
,
Weber
R.A.
(
2013
).
‘Identifying social norms using coordination games: Why does dictator game sharing vary?’
,
Journal of the European Economic Association
, vol.
11
(
3
), pp.
495
524
.

Ledyard
J.O.
(
1995
).
‘Public goods: A survey of experimental research’
, in (
Kagel
J.H.
,
Roth
A.E.
, eds.),
The Handbook of Experimental Economics
, pp.
111
94
.,
Princeton, NJ
:
Princeton University Press
.

Mandell
S.
(
2008
).
‘Optimal mix of emissions taxes and cap-and-trade’
,
Journal of Environmental Economics and Management
, vol.
56
(
2
), pp.
131
40
.

Montgomery
W.
(
1972
).
‘Markets in licenses and efficient pollution control programs’
,
Journal of Economic Theory
, vol.
5
(
3
), pp.
395
418
.

Narassimhan
E.
,
Gallagher
K.S.
,
Koester
S.
,
Alejo
J.R.
(
2018
).
‘Carbon pricing in practice: A review of existing emissions trading systems’
,
Climate Policy
, vol.
18
(
8
), pp.
967
91
.

Nyborg
K.
,
Howarth
R.B.
,
Brekke
K.A.
(
2006
).
‘Green consumers and public policy: On socially contingent moral motivation’
,
Resource and Energy Economics
, vol.
28
(
4
), pp.
351
66
.

Ockenfels
A.
,
Werner
P.
,
Edenhofer
O.
(
2019
).
‘Direct pricing accommodates moral behavior’
,
Working Paper, University of Colgone
.

Perino
G.
(
2015
).
‘Climate campaigns, cap and trade, and carbon leakage: Why trying to reduce your carbon footprint can harm the climate’
,
Journal of the Association of Environmental and Resource Economists
, vol.
2
(
3
), pp.
469
95
.

Pigou
A.C.
(
1920
).
The Economics of Welfare
,
London
:
MacMillan and Co
.

Pizer
W.A.
(
2002
).
‘Combining price and quantity controls to mitigate global climate change’
,
Journal of Public Economics
, vol.
85
(
3
), pp.
409
34
.

Requate
T.
(
2005
).
‘Dynamic incentives by environmental policy instruments—a survey’
,
Ecological Economics
, vol.
54
(
2–3
), pp.
175
95
.

Roberts
M.J.
,
Spence
M.
(
1976
).
‘Effluent charges and licenses under uncertainty’
,
Journal of Public Economics
, vol.
5
(
3–4
), pp.
193
208
.

Roemer
J.E.
(
2010
).
‘Kantian equilibrium’
,
Scandinavian Journal of Economics
, vol.
112
(
1
), pp.
1
24
.

Roemer
J.E.
(
2015
).
‘Kantian optimization: A microfoundation for cooperation’
,
Journal of Public Economics
, vol.
127
, pp.
45
57
.

Sandel
M.J.
(
2012
).
What Money Can’t Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets
,
1st edn.
,
New York
:
Farrar Straus and Giroux
.

Schmalensee
R.
,
Stavins
R.N.
(
2017
).
‘The design of environmental markets: What have we learned from experience with cap and trade?’
,
Oxford Review of Economic Policy
, vol.
33
(
4
), pp.
572
88
.

Schwirplies
C.
,
Ziegler
A.
(
2016
).
‘Offset carbon emissions or pay a price premium for avoiding them? A cross-country analysis of motives for climate protection activities’
,
Applied Economics
, vol.
48
(
9
), pp.
746
58
.

Sutter
M.
,
Huber
J.
,
Kirchler
M.
,
Stefan
M.
,
Walzl
M.
(
2020
).
‘Where to look for the morals in markets?’
,
Experimental Economics
, vol.
23
(
1
), pp.
30
52
.

Tiefensee
C.
(
2019
).
‘Why making no difference makes no moral difference’
, in (
Marker
K.
,
Schmitt
A.
,
Sirsch
J.
, eds.),
Demokratie und Entscheidung. Beiträge zur Analytischen Politischen Theorie
, pp.
231
44
.,
Wiesbaden
:
Springer VS
.

Vives
X.
(
1999
).
Oligopoly Pricing: Old Ideas and New Tools
,
Cambridge, MA
:
MIT Press
.

Weitzman
M.L.
(
1974
).
‘Prices vs. quantities’
,
The Review of Economic Studies
, vol.
41
(
4
), pp.
477
91
.

This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted reuse, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.