Abstract

Non-invasive functional brain imaging is used more than ever to investigate pain in health and disease, with the prospect of finding new means to alleviate pain and improve patient wellbeing. The observation that several brain areas are activated by transient painful stimuli, and that the magnitude of this activity is often graded with pain intensity, has prompted researchers to extract features of brain activity that could serve as biomarkers to measure pain objectively. However, most of the brain responses observed when pain is present can also be observed when pain is absent. For example, similar brain responses can be elicited by salient but non-painful auditory, tactile and visual stimuli, and such responses can even be recorded in patients with congenital analgesia. Thus, as argued in this review, there is still disagreement on the degree to which current measures of brain activity exactly relate to pain. Furthermore, whether more recent analysis techniques can be used to identify distributed patterns of brain activity specific for pain can be only warranted using carefully designed control conditions. On a more general level, the clinical utility of current pain biomarkers derived from human functional neuroimaging appears to be overstated, and evidence for their efficacy in real-life clinical conditions is scarce. Rather than searching for biomarkers of pain perception, several researchers are developing biomarkers to achieve mechanism-based stratification of pain conditions, predict response to medication and offer personalized treatments. Initial results with promising clinical perspectives need to be further tested for replicability and generalizability.

Introduction

Physical pain is intrinsically unpleasant and aversive. This is the very reason why it is advantageous for survival: it drives behaviours that avoid bodily injury when interacting with the environment. Yet, especially in modern societies, acute pain is often devoid of behavioural advantage. Think, for example, of the pain experienced during medical interventions. Furthermore, an increasing number of individuals suffer from pain that lasts for months or years (Breivik et al., 2006). This chronic pain is not only lacking any obvious behavioural benefit (Hodges and Tucker, 2011), but also heavily impairs quality of life. The fact that pain has a major negative impact on human wellbeing is often used as a persuasive argument to justify the funding of pain research. The prospect, which has shaped the way many pain neuroscientists conceive, design and interpret their work, is that beyond improving basic knowledge of the neural mechanisms of sensory perception, research in the field of pain will also lead to the development of more effective means to treat pain and reduce suffering.

Three arguments are usually set forth to uphold this prospect in the field of pain neuroimaging (Kupers and Kehlet, 2006; Borsook et al., 2007, 2010; de Vries et al., 2013; Lee and Tracey, 2013; Morton et al., 2016; Grosen et al., 2017; Tracey, 2017). First, it is often claimed that functional neuroimaging could be used to derive brain biomarkers that measure pain ‘objectively’. This would provide a solution to the hurdle of assessing pain using verbal reports, which are considered to be inherently prone to response biases (Wager et al., 2013; Kumbhare et al., 2017). Such biomarkers for pain would make it possible to quantify pain severity and the effects of treatments in an objective and undisputable ‘evidence-based’ fashion. Second, it is postulated that a mechanism-based diagnosis of clinical pain conditions is essential for adequate pain management (Woolf and Max, 2001; Woolf, 2008; Borsook et al., 2010, 2011; Lee and Tracey, 2013). By disclosing the neural mechanisms underlying pain in individual patients, neuroimaging could thus improve clinical diagnosis and care, for example, by predicting individual response to treatment (Wartolowska and Tracey, 2009; Denk et al., 2014; Tetreault et al., 2016; Davis and Seminowicz, 2017; Kumbhare et al., 2017). Third, it has been proposed that functional neuroimaging and electrophysiology could be used to quickly identify new pain-relieving drugs by characterizing their effects on CNS pain ‘circuits’ (Woolf and Max, 2001; Martucci et al., 2014), an approach sometimes referred to as ‘pharmaco-fMRI’ or ‘pharmaco-EEG’ (Schweinhardt et al., 2006; Wise and Tracey, 2006; Woolf, 2008; Gram et al., 2013).

One important question challenges the use of functional neuroimaging to derive ‘biomarkers’ of pain perception: does the brain activity sampled by these techniques when an individual experiences pain correspond to the neuronal activity causing the emergence of the painful percept? As summarized in a review paper that we published a few years ago (Iannetti and Mouraux, 2010), we and others (Carmon et al., 1976; Chapman et al., 1981; Melzack, 1999; Downar et al., 2003) have expressed concern regarding the specificity for pain of the brain responses classically observed when experiencing transient pain, i.e. the so-called ‘pain matrix’, a label covertly implying some specificity for pain. The concern is based on the observation that largely the same functional neuroimaging responses can be elicited by non-painful stimuli, provided that they are salient enough (Chapman et al., 1981; Downar et al., 2003; Mouraux and Iannetti, 2009; Mouraux et al., 2011) (Fig. 1). More recently it was also shown that a virtually identical ‘pain matrix’ response can be observed in patients with congenital insensitivity to pain (Salomons et al., 2016), thus providing further evidence that these brain responses are largely non-specific for pain. (This statement does not imply that neural activities specific for pain do not exist. Instead, it implies that the neural activities captured by current EEG or functional MRI techniques, which reflect synchronous activity within large populations of neurons, are—at the very least—largely unspecific for pain.) To escape from these controversies, many researchers now refrain from using the term ‘pain matrix’, and opt instead for terms like ‘pain network’, ‘pain signature’ or ‘neural circuits’ (Tracey and Mantyh, 2007; Seifert and Maihofner, 2011; Lelic et al., 2012; Longo et al., 2012; De Simone et al., 2013; Wager et al., 2013). Such labels are equally suggestive of the idea that the brain responses that are being measured reflect neural activity somehow unique for pain. To elaborate on only one of these examples, the term ‘signature’ denotes a distinctive pattern, product or characteristic by which something can be unequivocally identified. As detailed below, we argue that the attempts to falsify the hypothesis that the brain responses being measured are specific for pain using appropriate control stimuli have been insufficient, and the liberal use of terms implying specificity has biased the interpretation of several pain neuroimaging results.

Transient nociceptive stimuli causing pain. In this example heat laser pulses delivered to the right hand (scalp EEG and intracerebral LFP) or foot (functional MRI) elicit large-scale brain responses. In scalp EEG, the response is dominated by a large negative-positive wave maximal at the scalp vertex (electrode Cz), probably originating from bilateral operculo-insular regions, the cingulate cortex and, possibly, the contralateral primary somatosensory cortex. Responses in similar regions are also detected using functional MRI. Importantly, equally salient but non-painful and non-nociceptive tactile or auditory stimuli elicit very similar EEG and functional MRI responses, indicating that most of this activity is unspecific for pain or nociception and, instead, multimodal (Mouraux and Iannetti, 2009; Mouraux et al., 2011). Similarly, although the insula has been proposed to be strongly involved in pain perception, equally salient nociceptive and non-nociceptive stimuli trigger similar local field potentials (LFPs) recorded directly within the insula (Liberati et al., 2016). Nevertheless, other less prominent features of the sampled activity might be more selective for pain or nociception, as reflected by the selective increase of gamma-band oscillations (GBOs) when painful heat stimuli are presented (Liberati et al., 2018). BOLD = blood-oxygen level-dependent; ER% = event-related change in oscillation amplitude; ERP = event-related potential.
Figure 1

Transient nociceptive stimuli causing pain. In this example heat laser pulses delivered to the right hand (scalp EEG and intracerebral LFP) or foot (functional MRI) elicit large-scale brain responses. In scalp EEG, the response is dominated by a large negative-positive wave maximal at the scalp vertex (electrode Cz), probably originating from bilateral operculo-insular regions, the cingulate cortex and, possibly, the contralateral primary somatosensory cortex. Responses in similar regions are also detected using functional MRI. Importantly, equally salient but non-painful and non-nociceptive tactile or auditory stimuli elicit very similar EEG and functional MRI responses, indicating that most of this activity is unspecific for pain or nociception and, instead, multimodal (Mouraux and Iannetti, 2009; Mouraux et al., 2011). Similarly, although the insula has been proposed to be strongly involved in pain perception, equally salient nociceptive and non-nociceptive stimuli trigger similar local field potentials (LFPs) recorded directly within the insula (Liberati et al., 2016). Nevertheless, other less prominent features of the sampled activity might be more selective for pain or nociception, as reflected by the selective increase of gamma-band oscillations (GBOs) when painful heat stimuli are presented (Liberati et al., 2018). BOLD = blood-oxygen level-dependent; ER% = event-related change in oscillation amplitude; ERP = event-related potential.

The danger of assuming that brain responses sampled when experiencing pain are specific for pain is well illustrated by the way several pain neuroimaging results have been communicated by the general media. For example, a press release reporting a neuroimaging study on pain in infants conducted by Goksan et al. (2015) stated that because the ‘brains of babies light up in a very similar way to adults when exposed to a painful stimulus, new-borns experience pain in the same way as adults’ (http://www.ox.ac.uk/news/2015-04-21-babies-feel-pain-‘-adults’). Evidently, this conclusion, based on reverse inference, is valid if and only if the observed brain activity is specific for pain, as detailed in the ‘Pain-specific and pain-selective brain activity’ section below.

In the following sections, we first examine whether an established assumption—that there is a real clinical need for an ‘objective’ laboratory measure for the subjective perception of pain—is truly justified. Second, we examine the issue of pain specificity of the brain activity sampled using functional neuroimaging and electrophysiological techniques. This is necessary and timely, given the increasing use of new methods to analyse brain activity such as multivariate pattern analysis of functional MRI data to reveal ‘pain signatures’ (Wager et al., 2013), as well as the proposal of new theoretical concepts such as the ‘pain connectome’ (Kucyi and Davis, 2015, 2017), in which pain would emerge from widespread brain network activity. Third, we assess pragmatically whether current biomarkers derived from neuroimaging have the ability to measure pain ‘objectively’. Finally, we evaluate the strength of the evidence supporting the use of functional neuroimaging to perform mechanism-based stratification of patients with chronic pain, predict response to treatment, and assist the pharmacological development of novel treatments for pain.

Are neuroimaging biomarkers for pain really useful?

One of the enticing prospects of functional neuroimaging is that the sampled brain activity can be related to certain perceptual states. A spectacular example of what advanced algorithms to analyse brain activity can achieve is the decoding of the content of visual perception in wakefulness and sleep using brain activity sampled in visual areas (Horikawa et al., 2013). This gives strong theoretical and technological hope for the ability to use functional neuroimaging to decode the occurrence of a wide range of perceptions, including pain.

A crucial point to consider when one aims to use neuroimaging to ‘measure’ pain is the fact that, such as any other percept, pain is an intrinsically subjective experience. Therefore, even though measures of brain activity can be objective from a physiological standpoint (e.g. an objective measure of cerebral blood flow or scalp potential), biomarkers derived from these measures will be truthful correlates of perceived pain if and only if they account for the subjectivity of the pain experience (Robinson et al., 2013; Sullivan et al., 2013).

Healthcare providers often question the clinical utility of using complex and expensive neuroimaging techniques as means to measure pain because just interrogating patients about their pain is much simpler and more straightforward (Robinson et al., 2013). In the vast majority of circumstances, it is hard to argue that they are not right. One advantage of using a measure of brain activity to assess pain could be to bypass verbal reports, as these could be influenced by factors other than the experienced pain, and not only in the context of malingering. For example, patients may consciously or unconsciously exaggerate their report of pain to attract the attention of the caregiver or make sure that their complaint is taken into consideration. Other reasons may lead patients to understate their pain experience, such as not wanting to seem weak or be a nuisance, or satisfy the caregiver following a treatment. Finally, physicians can also be subject to biases, for example in relation to culture and ethnicity (Hoffman et al., 2016). Therefore, contextual factors are not only important determinants of the subjective pain experience, but might also modulate how the pain experience is reported and evaluated, and this is probably why some scientists and physicians have been seeking more ‘objective’ ways to measure pain. However, although verbal reports collected in large samples and controlled experimental settings may be more reliable than individual reports in clinical settings, the only way to test the sensitivity and specificity of alternative measures of pain perception is to compare them to verbal reports.

In few specific instances, means to assess the presence or intensity of pain that do not rely on verbal reports would be undeniably useful. First, to demonstrate pain in patients seeking compensation in a medico-legal context (Reardon, 2015; Salmanowitz, 2015; Davis et al., 2017), because the financial incentive for appearing disabled by pain leads indemnitors to question the sincerity of verbal reports. Second, to assess pain or nociception in individuals that are unable to communicate, such as infants (Goksan et al., 2015; Hartley et al., 2017), adults with consciousness disorders (Boly et al., 2008), cognitive impairment (Defrin et al., 2015), and patients under general anaesthesia (Cowen et al., 2015). However, it should be stressed that the physiological properties of the brain of such patients (properties that determine the signal measured using functional neuroimaging and electrophysiology) can be different from those of the normal adult brain (Iannetti and Wise, 2007; Marshall et al., 2014). Hence, pain biomarkers derived from healthy adult volunteers are not necessarily valid to assess pain in these clinical conditions. Furthermore, the utility of neuroimaging-based pain biomarkers should be compared with that of biomarkers using pain-related behaviours or physiological responses that may be easier to measure and implement in a clinical setting, such as changes in facial expression, heart rate, pupil diameter or skin conductance (Cowen et al., 2015) (Fig. 2).

Several physiological measures can, in some circumstances, correlate reliably with the reported intensity of perceived pain. As shown in the left plots, these measures can be obtained at different levels of the neuraxis: peripheral nociceptor activity recorded using microneurography [firing rate of a peripheral C-fibre nociceptor and intensity of perception as a function of stimulation temperature; adapted from Torebjork et al. (1984)], spinal cord activity assessed using dorsal horn electrophysiology in animals [firing rate of WDR and nociceptive specific dorsal horn neuron as a function of stimulation temperature; adapted from Khasabov et al. (2001)] or the recording of nociceptive RIII reflex activity using EMG in humans [amplitude of the RIII nociceptive withdrawal reflex in the tibialis anterior and intensity of perception as a function of the intensity of electric stimulation of the sural nerve; adapted from Willer et al. (1984)], cortical activity sampled using non-invasive functional neuroimaging techniques such as EEG [event-related brain potentials elicited by laser heat stimulation of the hand dorsum as a function of intensity of perception; adapted from Iannetti et al. (2008)], magnetoencephalography (MEG), functional MRI [fMRI-BOLD response elicited by thermal stimulation at different target temperatures; adapted from Bornhovd et al. (2002)] or PET, but also autonomic responses such as pupil dilation [magnitude of pupil dilation and intensity of perception as a function of stimulation intensity; adapted from Chapman et al. (1999)].
Figure 2

Several physiological measures can, in some circumstances, correlate reliably with the reported intensity of perceived pain. As shown in the left plots, these measures can be obtained at different levels of the neuraxis: peripheral nociceptor activity recorded using microneurography [firing rate of a peripheral C-fibre nociceptor and intensity of perception as a function of stimulation temperature; adapted from Torebjork et al. (1984)], spinal cord activity assessed using dorsal horn electrophysiology in animals [firing rate of WDR and nociceptive specific dorsal horn neuron as a function of stimulation temperature; adapted from Khasabov et al. (2001)] or the recording of nociceptive RIII reflex activity using EMG in humans [amplitude of the RIII nociceptive withdrawal reflex in the tibialis anterior and intensity of perception as a function of the intensity of electric stimulation of the sural nerve; adapted from Willer et al. (1984)], cortical activity sampled using non-invasive functional neuroimaging techniques such as EEG [event-related brain potentials elicited by laser heat stimulation of the hand dorsum as a function of intensity of perception; adapted from Iannetti et al. (2008)], magnetoencephalography (MEG), functional MRI [fMRI-BOLD response elicited by thermal stimulation at different target temperatures; adapted from Bornhovd et al. (2002)] or PET, but also autonomic responses such as pupil dilation [magnitude of pupil dilation and intensity of perception as a function of stimulation intensity; adapted from Chapman et al. (1999)].

Pain-specific and pain-selective brain activity

A great number of studies have shown that noxious experimental stimuli perceived as painful elicit activity within a wide array of brain regions including the primary (S1) and secondary (S2) somatosensory cortices, the insula and the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) (Peyron et al., 2000; Garcia-Larrea et al., 2003; Apkarian et al., 2005; Bushnell and Apkarian, 2005; Tracey and Mantyh, 2007). Because these responses (i) are consistently observed when subjects are experiencing acute pain; and (ii) often correlate with the amount of pain experienced by the subject, several studies have claimed that they reflect, just to cite a few examples, ‘the neural substrates of pain’ (Ploghaus et al., 1999), the functioning of ‘cortical areas devoted to pain elaboration’ (de Tommaso et al., 2005), or even ‘different aspects of pain elaboration’ (Di Clemente et al., 2013). As discussed below, these conclusions do not consider the exclusivity of the relationship between these responses and the state of experiencing pain (Poldrack, 2006; Iannetti and Mouraux, 2010).

A first question that arises is what is meant by ‘pain-selective’ and ‘pain-specific’. When these terms are used to qualify the functional significance of neural activity, they are often used interchangeably. Looking at how they are used in other domains is informative, because it indicates that the two terms in fact convey different meanings. In pharmacology, compound A is qualified as more selective than compound B, if A has a greater effect than B on the target population of cells or receptors, and a smaller effect than B on the non-target populations of cells or receptors. Similarly, in analytical chemistry, a method is qualified as more selective if it can quantify an analyte with less interference from other components (Vessman, 1996). A parallel can also be made between the concept of selectivity in pharmacology and the concept of response preference in single unit electrophysiology, which indicates neurons that respond preferentially to a given stimulus, although they also respond to other types of stimuli. Therefore, a neuron selective for pain would exhibit a response preference for pain, i.e. it would fire more strongly when pain is present as compared to when pain is absent. It follows that selectivity is not an all-or-nothing property and, instead, can be graded or quantified.

In contrast, the term specificity implies an all-or-nothing characteristic. In pharmacology, a molecule specific for a given target would have an exclusive effect on that target and no effect at all on any other target. In analytical chemistry, a specific assay would be one that quantifies an analyte without any interference from other components (Vessman, 1996). It follows that a ‘pain specific’ neuron would be a neuron that increases its firing rate when pain is present, and never does when pain is absent, i.e. it would exhibit the highest degree of selectivity. Strictly speaking, demonstrating that a neural response is specific for pain is practically impossible: it would require testing the entire spectrum of stimuli and conditions that could produce a response, to show that the response is observed only in the particular cases where pain is experienced. For this reason, we argue that the terms pain-specific or nociceptive-specific should be avoided not only because it is practically impossible to demonstrate specificity, but also because it is more informative to approach the problem in probabilistic terms and try to assess the likelihood that a given response is preferential for pain, i.e. its selectivity. This requires determining the probability of pain being present when the neural response is observed. Crucially, this is not the same as determining the probability of observing the neural response when pain is present, as it will also depend on the probability of the neural response being observed when there is no pain (Senn, 2013).

A parallel can be made between the definition of specificity and the validity of conclusions based on reverse inference of functional neuroimaging data (Poldrack, 2006). Stating that a given brain response is a specific ‘signature’ for a given mental state or sensation requires demonstrating that this brain response is not only always observed when that mental state is present, but also that it is never observed in any conditions where that mental state is absent. Because it is not possible to test the infinite number of conditions where a mental state is absent, one can judge the likelihood of the statement being true to be high if the exclusivity of the relationship is demonstrated in many conditions (Iannetti et al., 2013).

When reflecting on the criteria necessary to consider a neural response as selective or specific for pain, it is also important to consider the perceptual qualities that are coupled with pain, as defined by the International Association for the Study of Pain (IASP): ‘an unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with actual or potential tissue damage, or described in terms of such damage’ (Merskey and Bogduk, 1994). Thus, pain is not defined by a unique attribute, but by the conjunction of several attributes, such as the intrinsic unpleasantness of the experience and its threatening association with bodily damage. In addition, in a large number of circumstances, pain is also highly salient and, thus, attracts attention. Because pain signals a threat for the body, it also has strong behavioural relevance. However, sensations that are unpleasant, salient and behaviourally-relevant are not necessarily painful (e.g. the hideous sound produced when fingernails scrape a blackboard). Therefore, when assessing the selectivity or specificity for pain of a given brain response, it is crucial to use non-painful control stimuli that elicit sensations matched with respect to unpleasantness, salience and relevance. These different aspects are strongly associated with pain but they do not capture what truly distinguishes physical pain from other sensations, i.e. the experience of actual or potential tissue damage (Merskey and Bogduk, 1994). If the responses to painful stimuli are not compared to non-painful control stimuli that elicit sensations matched with respect to unpleasantness, salience and relevance, it follows that it is impossible to determine whether the differences observed between the brain responses elicited by painful and non-painful stimuli reflect neural activities that are selective for pain, or neural activities that are selective for these other features.

Does the brain contain neurons specific or selective for pain? At present, there is no clear answer to this question. Using anterograde trans-synaptic tracing from the spinal cord via the thalamus to the cerebral cortex in monkeys, Dum et al. (2009) confirmed the existence of direct di-synaptic spino-thalamo-cortical projections to S1, S2, the insula and the ACC. However, the projections to S1 were very sparse (<5%) as compared to projections to the posterior insula (40%), S2 (30%) and the mid-region of the cingulate cortex (24%), which thus appear to constitute the three main cortical targets of nociceptive input. Single-unit recordings performed in anaesthetized and/or awake animals have identified neurons responding to nociceptive stimuli in all these areas (Robinson and Burton, 1980; Kenshalo and Isensee, 1983; Dong et al., 1989; Sikes and Vogt, 1992; Yamamura et al., 1996; Treede et al., 1999; Dum et al., 2009). However, a large proportion of these neurons show only a moderate selectivity for nociceptive stimuli, as they respond more strongly to nociceptive stimuli as compared to non-nociceptive somatic stimuli, but nevertheless respond clearly to both types of stimuli. These neurons are often referred to as ‘wide dynamic range neurons’ (WDR). Other neurons appear to have higher mechanical or thermal activation thresholds and, therefore, appear to exhibit a stronger selectivity for nociception. These are often labelled as ‘high threshold’ or ‘nociceptive specific’ neurons. Supporting the view that S1 is not a major target of spinothalamic input, neurons responding to nociceptive input in S1 are strikingly sparse (Kenshalo and Isensee, 1983; Kenshalo et al., 2000). However, researchers have argued that this could be dependent on (i) whether the recordings are performed in anaesthetized versus awake animals; (ii) which subregions of S1 were sampled; and (iii) the type of nociceptive stimuli that are used to elicit responses (Mancini et al., 2012; Vierck et al., 2013; Jin et al., 2018). Considering that tracing studies indicate S2 and the insula as main targets of spinothalamic input (Dum et al., 2009), it is surprising that electrophysiological recordings identified only a very small number of neurons responding to nociceptive input in these regions. For example, Robinson and Burton (1980) reported, in awake monkeys, that most neurons in S2 and the insula respond to a variety of somatic stimuli, but almost never respond to noxious stimuli. An explanation for this discrepancy could be a searching bias: noci-responsive neurons might be confined to specific subregions of S2 and the insula, which were not explored by electrophysiological recordings. Supporting this interpretation, Dong et al. (1989) identified a cluster or noci-responsive neurons in the lateral sulcus on the upper bank of the parietal operculum, at the border between S2 and area 7b. Of 123 neurons responding to somatic stimuli, 118 responded to innocuous mechanical stimuli and only five responded exclusively to noxious mechanical stimulation. The authors were careful in their interpretation, stating that ‘additional testing is needed to support the tentative conclusion that an exclusive nociceptive-specific population exists’ in this region. In a subsequent study, Dong et al. (1994) attempted to further characterize the function of these noci-responsive neurons. In that study, 21 of 244 neurons responding to somatosensory stimulation responded to noxious heat stimuli, but only one neuron responded exclusively to noxious heat and mechanical stimuli. Importantly, approximately one-third of the neurons responding to noxious heat were at least bimodal: they also responded to spatially-aligned threatening or novel visual stimuli moving towards their cutaneous receptive fields. This finding indicates that the selectivity of these neurons does not relate to nociception but, instead, to threat, saliency, and/or behavioural relevance (Fig. 3).

Assessing the selectivity for pain of a given brain response requires not only to demonstrate that the response is present when pain is experienced, but also to demonstrate that it is not present when pain is not experienced. (A) Dong et al. (1994) recorded the activity of a single neuron located in area 7b, close to the secondary somatosensory cortex. When tested with a variety of thermal and mechanical somatic stimuli, the neuron responds to noxious heat stimuli applied to the face in a graded fashion, whereas it does not respond to a variety of mechanical stimuli. Based on these observations one might be tempted to conclude that the neuron is specific for burning pain. However, the same neuron also responds vigorously to visual stimuli approaching its receptive field (A–E), and the response was most prominent when the approaching object was novel or threatening. Therefore, in classical pain studies testing the response properties with noxious and innocuous somatosensory stimuli, this neuron would be labelled as nociceptive-specific (NS). However, this labelling would be incorrect, at least until the lack of responses to a wide range of equally salient, unpleasant and behaviourally-relevant stimuli has been comprehensively demonstrated. (B) Similarly, Hutchison et al. (1999) performed single unit recordings in the human anterior cingulate cortex, and found many neurons responding to noxious heat stimuli, and not to slow-rising innocuous mechanical stimuli. However, some of these neurons also responded to watching noxious stimuli being delivered to the experimenter, suggesting that they may serve a supramodal function related or consequent to stimulus saliency or threat detection. CS = central sulcus; IPS = intraparietal sulcus; LS = lateral sulcus. Adapted with permission from Fig. 7 in Dong et al. (1994) and Fig. 1 in Hutchison et al. (1999).
Figure 3

Assessing the selectivity for pain of a given brain response requires not only to demonstrate that the response is present when pain is experienced, but also to demonstrate that it is not present when pain is not experienced. (A) Dong et al. (1994) recorded the activity of a single neuron located in area 7b, close to the secondary somatosensory cortex. When tested with a variety of thermal and mechanical somatic stimuli, the neuron responds to noxious heat stimuli applied to the face in a graded fashion, whereas it does not respond to a variety of mechanical stimuli. Based on these observations one might be tempted to conclude that the neuron is specific for burning pain. However, the same neuron also responds vigorously to visual stimuli approaching its receptive field (A–E), and the response was most prominent when the approaching object was novel or threatening. Therefore, in classical pain studies testing the response properties with noxious and innocuous somatosensory stimuli, this neuron would be labelled as nociceptive-specific (NS). However, this labelling would be incorrect, at least until the lack of responses to a wide range of equally salient, unpleasant and behaviourally-relevant stimuli has been comprehensively demonstrated. (B) Similarly, Hutchison et al. (1999) performed single unit recordings in the human anterior cingulate cortex, and found many neurons responding to noxious heat stimuli, and not to slow-rising innocuous mechanical stimuli. However, some of these neurons also responded to watching noxious stimuli being delivered to the experimenter, suggesting that they may serve a supramodal function related or consequent to stimulus saliency or threat detection. CS = central sulcus; IPS = intraparietal sulcus; LS = lateral sulcus. Adapted with permission from Fig. 7 in Dong et al. (1994) and Fig. 1 in Hutchison et al. (1999).

As compared to S1 and the operculo-insular cortex, a greater number of neurons responding to nociceptive stimuli have been identified in the cingulate cortex (Sikes and Vogt, 1992; Yamamura et al., 1996; Hutchison et al., 1999), including a study conducted in humans (Hutchison et al., 1999). However, a good amount of these noci-responsive neurons in the cingulate may, in fact, be supramodal. For example, Sikes and Vogt (1992) found that out of 542 units recorded in area 24 of the cingulate cortex of rabbits, 150 units responded to noxious electrical stimulation of the skin. Of 221 units tested with noxious mechanical stimuli, only 91 responded, and of 47 units tested for noxious heat stimulation only nine responded. Approximately 25% of the units that responded to noxious mechanical stimulation also responded to noxious heat stimulation. These noci-responsive neurons did not respond to slow-rising innocuous mechanical stimuli, such as light stroking, brushing or pressure, an observation suggesting selectivity or specificity for nociception. However, more than half of these units did respond to fast-rising innocuous mechanical stimuli, such as tapping of the skin (11/19 tested units), suggesting that these ‘noci-responsive’ neurons in the ACC might in fact be more sensitive to the suddenness or salience of the stimulus. Similarly, Hutchison et al. (1999) performed single-unit recordings of the ACC in 11 human patients. In four patients, 11 ACC neurons responded to contralateral noxious thermal and/or noxious mechanical stimuli. None of these neurons responded to innocuous tactile stimuli. However, three of these 11 neurons also responded to anticipation or observation of potentially painful stimuli. Furthermore, the electrical stimulation of the ACC failed to elicit painful sensations, even at sites where noci-responsive neurons had been identified. Again, this suggests that at least a fraction of neurons responding to nociceptive stimuli may serve supramodal functions related or consequent to the detection of stimulus saliency, threat detection and/or behavioural relevance (Hutchison et al., 1999).

Taken together, studies conducted so far suggest that if truly nociceptive-specific neurons or even neurons highly selective for nociception exist in the brain, they are very scarce (Wall, 1995). Furthermore, because these studies were almost exclusively conducted in animals that cannot report whether they are experiencing pain, how the activity of these neurons relates to the perception of pain is largely unknown. Finally, as we will argue below, the ability to perceive and discriminate pain from other somatic sensations does not necessarily require the activity of individual neurons with high selectivity for pain, because distinct percepts could emerge from distinct patterns of activity in neuronal populations having, individually, a low response selectivity.

Does the brain contain areas that are specific or selective for pain? This question asks whether the brain contains areas in which pain-selective or pain-specific neurons may be spatially segregated, in the same way as, for example, neurons whose primary function is to process visual input are clustered in the primary visual cortex, or neurons whose primary function is to generate somatic motor output are clustered in the primary motor cortex. The main distinction between this question and the previous question is that it addresses cortical specialization at population level, using techniques sampling the summated activity of large populations of neurons, such as functional MRI or EEG. As mentioned above and shown in Fig. 1, using such brain imaging techniques, there is an important overlap between the brain responses to acute pain and the brain responses that can be elicited by non-painful salient tactile, auditory or visual stimuli. There are at least two possible explanations for this overlap. First, it could be consequent to the difficulty in detecting fine-grained spatial differences in cortical activity using univariate group-level analyses of spatially-smoothed functional MRI data, or using low spatial resolution scalp EEG and MEG data. Second, it could be due to the fact that transient stimuli elicit widespread large amplitude saliency-related responses, which could conceal smaller amplitude activity specific for pain.

As detailed above, tracing studies performed in monkeys have shown that the main projection sites of spinothalamic input are the insula, S2 and the cingulate cortex (Dum et al., 2009), suggesting that these areas play a primary role in the cortical processing of ascending nociceptive input. Whether these areas are selective for pain is a timely question, given recent claims that ‘the dorsal posterior insula subserves a fundamental role in human pain’ (Segerdahl et al., 2015), or that the dorsal anterior cingulate cortex is ‘selectively involved in pain-related processes’ (Lieberman and Eisenberger, 2015).

Segerdahl et al. (2015) used functional MRI based on arterial spin labelling to identify sustained variations in brain activity whose time courses follow equally sustained changes in pain perception generated by the combination of topical capsaicin and heat. The originality of this tonic stimulation approach, which has been also used in a small number of other studies (Schulz et al., 2015), is the attempt to move away from sampling responses triggered by the onset of transient noxious stimuli. The authors postulated that slow variations in brain activity that correlate with slow variations of pain intensity could isolate brain activity more directly related to the perception of pain. The strongest correlation was observed in the dorsal posterior part of the insula. This led the authors to conclude ‘a specific role for the dorsal posterior insula in pain’. The propensity for sensationalism of the general media led to a press report stating that the ‘ouch zone of the human brain had been identified’ (http://www.ox.ac.uk/news/2015-03-09-‘ouch-zone’-brain-identified-0). However, we and others argued that the experiment did not include appropriate control stimuli to substantiate the claim for ‘specificity’, or even ‘selectivity’. Indeed, presence versus absence of pain was by no means the only difference between their sustained pain condition and their control sustained touch condition (Davis et al., 2015) (see http://f1000research.com/articles/4-362 for reviewer and reader comments). Another crucial difference was that the nociceptive stimulation was much more salient and unpleasant than the tactile stimulation, which in fact failed to elicit activity in S1. There is now strong experimental evidence indicating that the differences between the insular responses elicited by nociceptive and tactile stimulation observed by Segerdahl et al. (2015) could have been driven entirely by factors other than pain. For example, invasive intracerebral EEG recordings from the human insula showed that transient painful stimuli and non-painful tactile, auditory and visual stimuli elicit largely similar responses in all subregions of the human insula including the dorsal posterior insula, provided that they are similarly salient (Liberati et al., 2016). Furthermore, there is a case report of a patient with bilateral extensive damage to the insula with intact abilities to experience and express pain (Salomons et al., 2016). Similarly, although some studies suggested that lesions of the insula may impair the ability to perceive pain (Garcia-Larrea et al., 2010), a later review of 24 patients with acute unilateral stroke lesions primarily affecting the insular cortex reported no changes in cold pain, heat pain or mechanical pain thresholds (Baier et al., 2014). Nevertheless, some studies have suggested that lesions of the insula impair the ability to perceive pain and that direct cortical stimulation of the insula or epileptic activity in the insula can generate pain, although only in rare cases (Isnard et al., 2011; Mazzola et al., 2012). Furthermore, intracerebral recordings of local field potentials in the human insula have shown that painful heat stimuli elicit gamma-band oscillations that are not observed in response to similarly salient tactile, auditory or visual stimuli (Liberati et al., 2018) (Fig. 1). Clearly, in the current state of affairs, whether or not the insula plays a causal role in the generation of pain remains a largely open question.

Another study recently claimed that the dorsal anterior cingulate is ‘selective for pain’ (Lieberman and Eisenberger, 2015). The claim stems from a meta-analysis conducted using Neurosynth, a tool to analyse a database of published functional neuroimaging data based on the frequency of terms used in the manuscripts reporting that data. The authors found (i) that activation of the dorsal anterior cingulate is more consistently reported in publications using pain-related terms (‘pain’, ‘painful’, ‘noxious’) as compared to publications not using these terms; and (ii) that this is not the case for studies that frequently used terms related to executive control (‘executive’, ‘working memory’, ‘effort’, ‘cognitive control’, ‘cognitive’, ‘control’), conflict processing (‘conflict’, ‘error’, ‘inhibition’, ‘stop signal’, ‘Stroop’, ‘motor’), or salience (‘salience’, ‘detection’, ‘task relevant’, ‘auditory’, ‘tactile’, ‘visual’). The validity of this comparison has been extensively critiqued elsewhere (Wager et al., 2016; Yarkoni, 2018). Most importantly, using the same database but manually identifying the topics of the studies based on the title and abstract, Wager et al. (2016) showed that activation of the dorsal anterior cingulate was associated with a 12% probability of that study involving pain, on par with language (8%), emotion (12%), attention (19%) and memory (12%); indicating that the functional MRI response in the dorsal anterior cingulate is largely unselective for pain (see also Shackman et al., 2011).

In summary, even though the operculo-insular and cingulate cortex appear to be the main cortical targets of inputs ascending the spinothalamic tracts (Dum et al., 2009), the actual involvement of these two brain structures in generating painful percepts remains to be warranted and clarified.

Does the brain generate patterns of activity that are specific or selective for pain? Faced with the increasing evidence that pain does not appear to emerge from the activation of ‘pain-specific’ neurons or brain areas, several researchers have proposed that the experience of pain could emerge from the interactions between a population of interconnected neurons (Norrsell et al., 1999; Melzack, 2005; Kucyi and Davis, 2015). In this view, which is also increasingly considered in other fields of neuroscience (Sporns, 2013), specificity or selectivity of single neurons or of single brain areas would not be required to generate qualitatively unique experiences, like pain. The opposing ‘labelled lines’ and ‘pattern’ theories of neural coding have nourished scientific debate for decades (Doetsch, 2000). The pattern coding theory was first proposed in the beginning of the 19th century as a solution to the problem that photoreceptors only sensitive to three colours of light can convey information about the entire spectrum of light colours. This idea was later extended to all sensory, motor and cognitive brain functions (Erickson, 1963). In pain research, supporters of the ‘specificity theory of pain’ have advocated that pain is a specific modality with its own receptors and pathways, i.e. pain-specific labelled lines; whereas defenders of the ‘pattern theory of pain’ proposed that pain results from the pattern of activation generated in receptors and pathways that can also generate non-painful percepts and, therefore, are unspecific for pain (Erickson, 1973; Norrsell et al., 1999; Prescott et al., 2014).

This view that pain could emerge from a specific distributed pattern of neural activity constitutes one of the rationales for using multivariate approaches to explore functional neuroimaging data obtained when subjects are experiencing pain. In contrast to univariate approaches, multivariate pattern analysis (MVPA) attempts to link a particular mental state, such as experiencing pain, with a specific spatial pattern of brain activity sampled with functional MRI or EEG (Schulz et al., 2012; Wager et al., 2013; Corradi-Dell‘Acqua et al., 2016; Lindquist et al., 2017; Woo et al., 2017). However, it is crucial to emphasize that testing whether a given spatial pattern of brain activity constitutes a ‘pain signature’ requires exactly the same evidence that is needed to demonstrate the existence of ‘pain-specific’ neurons or brain areas. In addition to showing that the identified spatial pattern is always present when one experiences pain, one must also show that the spatial pattern of activity is never present in the absence of pain. Wager et al. (2013) found that the same spatial pattern of brain activity can be observed in a variety of conditions where subjects are experiencing physical pain, and labelled this pattern ‘neurological pain signature’ (Wager et al., 2013). The authors also assessed the selectivity of this response by showing that it is not observed in a number of control conditions. However, they restricted their testing to control conditions that differed from the painful conditions in many ways other than the presence versus absence of pain. Specifically, their control conditions were either less salient, less behaviourally relevant, and/or not somatic; for example, a low-salience mild warm stimulus versus a high-salience burning heat stimulus, or a non-somatic ‘social pain’ stimulus versus a somatic painful stimulus. For this reason, it could well be that the spatial pattern of brain activity that they referred to as a ‘neurological pain signature’ was, in fact, a spatial pattern of brain activity that is selective for the occurrence of a salient somatic stimulus, regardless of whether it elicits pain. Significantly, in a later study, the same authors observed that the neurological pain signature fails to predict variations in pain induced by cognitive ‘self regulation’, i.e. by imagining that nociceptive stimuli are more painful or less painful than they are, thereby demonstrating that the neurological pain signature does not necessarily track the subjective pain experience (Woo et al., 2015).

Within the framework that specific sensations could emerge from the interactions within a network of interconnected neurons, the interesting notion of a ‘dynamic pain connectome’ has been recently proposed (Kucyi and Davis, 2015, 2017). In this theoretical model, pain would be encoded in ‘the spatiotemporal signature of brain network communication that represents the integration of all cognitive, affective, and sensorimotor aspects of pain’ (Kucyi and Davis, 2015). At first glance, this view is highly similar to the one proposed by Melzack (1999, 2005) in the ‘neuromatrix theory of pain’, in which pain would be ‘a multidimensional experience produced by characteristic neurosignature patterns of nerve impulses generated by a widely distributed neural network in the brain’. The difference between the two theories is that the ‘connectome’ of Kucyi and Davis (2015) emphasizes that the specificity of the patterns is not only defined by which elements are part of the network, but also by the temporal characteristics of the activity generated within the different elements. The fact that there must be specific features of brain activity that underlie pain sensations is unquestionable, unless one takes a dualistic stance on the mind-body relationship. However, this is not sufficient to demonstrate that there is a ‘pain connectome’. Future work is needed to translate this general concept into a set of falsifiable hypotheses. Importantly, one must bear in mind that current functional neuroimaging techniques may not have the spatial and/or temporal resolution required to discriminate the potentially subtle spatio-temporal features of brain activity that underlie pain sensations.

What can we conclude from the ability of neuroimaging biomarkers to measure pain?

When neuroimaging is used as a clinical tool to predict the intensity of pain perceived by a human subject, whether the brain activity used to ‘decode’ pain intensity reflects neural processes that are specific or selective for pain is not an issue (Hu and Iannetti, 2016). Indeed, to achieve this very pragmatic objective, the only requirement is that the index derived from the measured brain activity must vary systematically with pain intensity. Furthermore, the relationship between this index and pain intensity should not be influenced by factors not affecting pain perception, at least in the situations for which the ‘pain biomarker’ is intended to be used.

Reflecting on the use of functional neuroimaging to guess whether a subject is experiencing pain brings us to the meaning and definition of the term ‘specificity’ in the context of a clinical diagnostic test, which is radically different from when the term specificity is used to qualify the function of neuronal activity (see ‘Pain-specific and pain-selective brain activity’ section). When referring to a diagnostic test, specificity indicates the proportion of patients not affected by a given condition that are correctly identified as such (i.e. the rate of ‘true negatives’). Conversely, the term sensitivity refers to the proportion of patients affected by a given condition that are correctly identified as positive (i.e. the rate of ‘true positives’). Thus, when applied to a neuroimaging biomarker for pain, the terms specificity and sensitivity refer to the ability of that biomarker to correctly identify the absence of pain in patients without pain and to correctly identify the presence of pain in patients with pain, respectively. Demonstrating that a given pain biomarker has a high sensitivity and specificity does not necessarily imply that the neural activity from which that pain biomarker is derived corresponds to the neural activity specific for pain, i.e. neural activity causing pain. Thus, if a given neuroimaging index has a good specificity with respect to its ability to measure pain, it is incorrect to automatically assume that the neural activity from which the index is derived corresponds to the neural activity generating pain. In other words, a pain biomarker can have utility (if it has enough selectivity and sensitivity in a clinical setting, or it is useful as a dependent measure in an experimental setting), but this utility does not necessarily mean that the biomarker is of any theoretical interest or that we are any closer to understanding the biological conditions that are necessary and sufficient for the subjective experience of pain.

It is instructive to consider the large number of biological measures that can be used to measure pain, without having any causal role in generating pain (Fig. 2). For example, noxious stimuli cause phasic dilation of the pupil (Chapman et al., 1999; Eisenach et al., 2017). Even though the magnitude of pupil dilation often correlates with pain reports (and pupil dilation has indeed been proposed as an objective measure of pain; Cowen et al., 2015), this would not lead anyone to conclude that pain is caused by the pupil dilation itself. Another example more directly related to the brain is the following. If one could properly sample the activity of all retinal ganglion cells or primary visual cortex neurons, it would be possible to reconstruct fairly accurately what an individual is seeing. However, this does not mean that the sampled activity is what creates the visual percept. It only means that the sampled activity contains information related to what is being seen. In other words, one could have an effective pain biomarker using neural activity that does not actually generate the painful percept, such as the activity of primary nociceptive afferents or dorsal horn neurons, or the activity of neurons related to processes that are consequential to the percept (Fig. 2).

As a matter of fact, this same issue has led to heated debates among researchers searching for the neural correlates of consciousness. Identifying these neural correlates often relies on comparing conditions in which consciousness is present to conditions in which consciousness is absent (e.g. the presentation of a supraliminal versus subliminal sensory stimulus). As emphasized by Aru et al. (2012), differences in brain activity observed across the two conditions do not necessarily highlight the neural activity giving rise to conscious percepts, because at least part of the observed differences could reflect a number of prerequisites and/or consequences of conscious processing (Aru et al., 2012).

Another important concept relevant to the discussion about pain biomarkers is generalizability (Davis et al., 2017). First, it is important to demonstrate that the biomarker generalizes beyond the dataset used to generate the biomarker. This requires that the dataset used to test the predictive power of the biomarker is not the same dataset used to generate the biomarker. Second, a given biomarker might have high sensitivity and specificity within the context in which it is developed, tested and used (e.g. presence versus absence of acute experimental pain) but a low sensitivity and specificity in other contexts (e.g. presence versus absence of sustained clinical pain), i.e. it might not generalize to all conditions where physical pain is experienced. For example, Huang et al. (2013) identified a biomarker derived from EEG activity that successfully allows predicting subjective pain reports to brief nociceptive heat stimuli, both within subjects and across subjects. This biomarker was based on the amplitude and latency of the negative and positive vertex waves typically evoked by fast-rising nociceptive thermal stimuli in the ongoing EEG. However, an important caveat—which Huang et al. (2013) clearly acknowledge—is that the relationship between the biomarker and subjective pain is not obligatory. We give three examples of a clear disruption of this relationship. First, simply repeating the fast-rising painful stimulus three times at a fixed 1-s interval has no effect on the intensity of the pain elicited by each of the three stimuli, but has a very strong effect on the magnitude of the stimulus-evoked brain potentials: compared to the EEG response to the first stimulus, the EEG responses to the second and third stimuli are markedly reduced (Iannetti et al., 2008). In this situation, the biomarker described by Huang et al. would make the erroneous prediction that the second and third stimuli elicit less or no pain, thus producing a false negative. Second, compared to fast-rising nociceptive stimuli, slow-rising nociceptive stimuli can produce the same intensity of pain, but fail to produce a similarly large brain response, simply because the magnitude of these phase-locked EEG responses is strongly dependent on the phasic nature of the stimulus onset (Iannetti et al., 2004; Baumgartner et al., 2005). In this case, the biomarker proposed by Huang et al. (2013) would again underestimate the perceived pain and produce a false negative. Third, as we detailed above, several studies have shown that the brain responses elicited when experiencing acute pain are largely indistinguishable from the brain responses elicited by non-painful but saliency-matched tactile stimuli (Fig. 1) (Mouraux and Iannetti, 2009; Liberati et al., 2016). In this case, the abovementioned pain biomarker would predict that individuals are experiencing pain when they are exposed to salient stimuli that are not painful.

Another issue is whether pain biomarkers derived from brain activity sampled in healthy participants experiencing acute pain can be used to assess pain in clinical conditions. Using functional MRI, Baliki et al. (2006) found that regions showing increased cerebral blood flow when human subjects experience acute pain are very different from the brain regions whose activity correlates with the spontaneous fluctuations of pain in patients with non-acute low back pain (Fig. 4). From this observation, it follows that a pain biomarker derived from the brain activity commonly observed when experiencing acute pain might have a good sensitivity and specificity to identify acute pain, but a very low sensitivity and specificity to identify the sustained pain frequently observed in clinical conditions. Obviously, this issue can be addressed by developing pain biomarkers derived from brain activity measured in patients experiencing clinical pain. In addition to Baliki et al. (2006), several other promising attempts have already been made in this direction. For example, Howard et al. (2011) and Hodkinson et al. (2013) used MRI arterial spin labelling to compare sustained measures of cerebral blood flow before versus after surgical tooth extraction, and found increased activity in the posterior and anterior insula, S2 and the anterior cingulate, i.e. a pattern of brain activity similar to the pattern of brain activity observed during acute pain. Using the same imaging technique, Wasan et al. (2011) compared patients with chronic low back pain in three conditions: a rest condition, a condition during which clinical manoeuvres were used to increase the intensity of back pain, and a third condition during which noxious heat was applied to the affected dermatome. They found that increasing the pathological back pain was associated with increased blood flow in somatosensory, prefrontal and insular cortices, and the superior parietal lobule. This pattern of brain activity differed from that observed during acute noxious heat pain, which showed no increase of activity in the superior parietal lobule. However, it also differed from the pattern of brain activity reported by Baliki et al. (2006). The differences could be due to the methodologies used to measure brain activity (blood-oxygen level-dependent signals versus arterial spin labelling), to create contrasts in clinical pain intensity (spontaneous fluctuations of clinical pain versus exacerbation of clinical pain using clinical manoeuvres), or to differences between the studied populations.

Brain activity related to the perception of acute experimental pain and sustained clinical pain.Top row shows the results of a meta-analysis of functional neuroimaging publications that frequently use the term ‘pain’ in the full text (Neurosynth-generated ‘reverse inference map’ using the term ‘pain’). The mask highlights the brain regions that are frequently often observed in ‘pain’ studies as compared to studies that do not frequently mention the term ‘pain’. The second row shows the overlap between this Neurosynth mask and the brain areas showing a significant BOLD response when transient painful stimuli are delivered to the right foot of healthy volunteers [data from Mouraux et al. (2011)]. Note the strong overlap, in yellow. The third row shows the BOLD response elicited by a transient painful stimulus in a group of patients with low back pain, generally similar to the BOLD response observed in healthy participants [data from Baliki et al. (2006)]. The bottom row shows, in the same patients, the regions where the BOLD signal correlates significantly with spontaneous fluctuations of low back pain. Note the lack of overlap between these areas and the Neurosynth-generated mask, indicating that a brain biomarker derived from brain activity triggered by acute painful stimuli is likely to be unable to assess pain in clinical conditions. LBP = low back pain.
Figure 4

Brain activity related to the perception of acute experimental pain and sustained clinical pain.Top row shows the results of a meta-analysis of functional neuroimaging publications that frequently use the term ‘pain’ in the full text (Neurosynth-generated ‘reverse inference map’ using the term ‘pain’). The mask highlights the brain regions that are frequently often observed in ‘pain’ studies as compared to studies that do not frequently mention the term ‘pain’. The second row shows the overlap between this Neurosynth mask and the brain areas showing a significant BOLD response when transient painful stimuli are delivered to the right foot of healthy volunteers [data from Mouraux et al. (2011)]. Note the strong overlap, in yellow. The third row shows the BOLD response elicited by a transient painful stimulus in a group of patients with low back pain, generally similar to the BOLD response observed in healthy participants [data from Baliki et al. (2006)]. The bottom row shows, in the same patients, the regions where the BOLD signal correlates significantly with spontaneous fluctuations of low back pain. Note the lack of overlap between these areas and the Neurosynth-generated mask, indicating that a brain biomarker derived from brain activity triggered by acute painful stimuli is likely to be unable to assess pain in clinical conditions. LBP = low back pain.

Neuroimaging for mechanism-based diagnosis and stratification of patients with chronic pain

Researchers have suggested that it might be possible to use neuroimaging to identify different ‘constituent components’ or ‘networks’ underlying pain and its modulation (Di Clemente et al., 2013; Denk et al., 2014), such as the neural activities underlying central sensitization (Lee et al., 2008), descending pain modulation (Bingel and Tracey, 2008), modulation of pain by emotions, attention or cognitive control (Peyron et al., 2000; Kragel et al., 2018), pain relief following a specific treatment (Iannetti et al., 2005) or placebo analgesia (Bingel et al., 2006; Schafer et al., 2018). Thus, by identifying in individual patients suffering from chronic pain the engagement of different ‘constituent components’ contributing to the pain experience and its modulation, neuroimaging could make it possible to stratify patients in functionally distinct groups, with the exciting prospect of identifying which treatment is most likely to provide relief in individual patients and, hence, propose optimal first-line treatments (Fig. 5).

Use of functional neuroimaging to predict treatment response and stratify patients. Non-personalized treatment (top). When a population of patients is exposed to treatment X, some individuals respond to the treatment (e.g. 40%) and others do not (e.g. 60%). Brain biomarker of treatment response (middle). Functional brain imaging before any treatment is delivered to a group of patients to obtain predictive information about whether the patients are responders or non-responders. Personalized treatment using brain biomarker (bottom). The features of brain activity that distinguished responders from non-responders can be looked for in a new population of patients who have not yet been treated, to predict individual patient’s response, and thereby provide the first-line treatment that is most likely to be effective for that individual patient.
Figure 5

Use of functional neuroimaging to predict treatment response and stratify patients. Non-personalized treatment (top). When a population of patients is exposed to treatment X, some individuals respond to the treatment (e.g. 40%) and others do not (e.g. 60%). Brain biomarker of treatment response (middle). Functional brain imaging before any treatment is delivered to a group of patients to obtain predictive information about whether the patients are responders or non-responders. Personalized treatment using brain biomarker (bottom). The features of brain activity that distinguished responders from non-responders can be looked for in a new population of patients who have not yet been treated, to predict individual patient’s response, and thereby provide the first-line treatment that is most likely to be effective for that individual patient.

The idea that different measures of pain-related brain activity can be separated in functionally distinct components was probably first put forward by Albe-Fessard et al. (1985), when they proposed that pain processing can be separated into anatomically and functionally distinct ‘lateral’ and ‘medial’ pain systems, on the basis that ascending nociceptive inputs project onto lateral and medial thalamic nuclei, each having distinct cortical projections (Albe-Fessard et al., 1985; Ingvar, 1999). In this model, the lateral pain system, comprising S1 and S2, would subserve the sensori-discriminative dimension of pain; whereas the medial pain system, comprising various brain structures including the cingulate cortex, would subserve the affective and cognitive dimensions of pain. However, although most researchers agree that this functional dichotomy between lateral and medial systems is an oversimplification (Brooks and Tracey, 2005; Iannetti and Mouraux, 2010), it is still used today as a framework to interpret experimental or clinical observations. For example, the finding that pain-evoked brain responses thought to originate from S2 are modulated by topiramate, a drug used as a pre-emptive treatment for migraine, led authors to conclude that the drug acts ‘specifically on the sensory-discriminative component of pain elaboration’ (Di Clemente et al., 2013). Similarly, numerous studies on empathy and social exclusion have dichotomized pain-related brain activity as belonging either to ‘the affective part’ or the ‘sensori-discriminative part’, depending on whether they originate from brain structures belonging to the medial or lateral pain systems (Kross et al., 2011, Novembre et al., 2015). It should be noted that the empirical evidence supporting the functional distinction between ‘medial’ and ‘lateral’ pain systems is, to say the least, scarce. First, it relies on two experiments conducted by the same group, showing that the hypnotic modulation of pain unpleasantness is paralleled by a modulation of pain-evoked activity in the ACC, interpreted as a modulation of the ‘medial’ pain system (Rainville et al., 1997), whereas hypnotic modulation of pain intensity is paralleled by a modulation of pain-evoked activity in S1, interpreted as a modulation of the ‘lateral’ pain system (Hofbauer et al., 2001). Second, it relies on evidence from the single report of a patient with reduced ability to detect and discriminate pain, but preserved ability to experience its unpleasantness following a post-central lesion (Ploner et al., 1999), and qualitative reports that chronic pain patients treated with anterior cingulotomy continue to feel pain, but are less emotionally affected by it (Foltz and White, 1962, 1968).

More recently, rather than focusing on the brain activity related to the perception of pain, a number of functional neuroimaging studies have investigated the brain activity thought to be involved in mechanisms modulating pain, such as the top-down influence of nociceptive transmission at the level of the spinal cord (Bingel et al., 2006; Tinnermann et al., 2017), the changes in brain activity thought to be involved in central sensitization or placebo analgesia (Petrovic et al., 2002; Wager et al., 2004, 2007; Zambreanu et al., 2005; Zubieta et al., 2005; Lee et al., 2008), the modulation of pain by cognitive control, emotions and attention (Brascher et al., 2016). If successful, these approaches hold strong promise. Indeed, considering that pain-modulatory mechanisms might vary across individuals, being able to characterize their contribution at an individual level opens the prospect of being able stratify patients into functionally meaningful categories, to better understand the functional mechanisms contributing to the development and maintenance of chronic pain, and to potentially orient towards more personalized and effective treatment strategies taking into consideration individual ‘pain endophenotypes’ (Tracey, 2011). For example, functional neuroimaging could be used to assess the ability of an individual patient to engage descending inhibitory control mechanisms, or his susceptibility to sensitize when exposed to intense nociceptive stimulation. Such results would have immediate practical implications, as they might allow prediction of whether that patient will respond well to a specific treatment, or how likely it is that he will develop chronic pain after surgery. However, as recently emphasized by Denk et al. (2014), data currently supporting this view are still sparse and, most critically, do not allow one to infer causal relationships. Indeed, the use of proper controls is necessary to relate changes in brain activity to specific pain modulatory mechanisms. If brain structure A has a level of activity that relates positively to the amount of reduction in pain perception caused by a given treatment or experimental manipulation, this does not automatically mean that brain structure A is involved in generating the pain relief caused by the treatment. For example, if distraction from the painful stimulus is induced by performing a counting Stroop task (as in Bantick et al., 2002), the increased neural activity observed in brain structure A during distraction could reflect brain processes engaged by the execution of the task, but independent of the processes responsible for the effect of the task on pain perception. Hence, observing that distraction from pain is associated with increased activity in brain structure A does not allow conclusion that this activity is ‘orchestrating the modulation of pain by attention’ (Bantick et al., 2002). Finally, to be clinically useful, such neuroimaging measures must have predictive value at individual level. In this respect, the use of longitudinal designs is imperative to determine whether brain imaging can be useful to assess individual vulnerability to develop chronic pain. Although difficult to implement, a few studies have followed this line and generated encouraging results. For example, Baliki et al. (2012) recently showed that the state of cortico-striatal ‘reward-motivation circuits’ measured using functional MRI can predict the transition to chronic pain in patients with subacute low-back pain.

Along the same lines, a recent study from the same group compared the effects of placebo and duloxetine in patients with chronic pain, yielding striking results. Specific patterns of brain connectivity before receiving the treatment could predict which patients would be placebo responders, as well as the degree of analgesia that would be induced by both the placebo and the active agent (Tetreault et al., 2016). Given their wide clinical implications in terms of patient stratification and drug development, these results demand replication. Still, they already hint towards the practical use of neuroimaging to predict response to treatment in chronic pain conditions.

In conclusion, it is important that further studies on brain biomarkers of pain and its modulation are conducted to test the biomarkers' generalizability, assess their performance at an individual level, and understand the reasons why they may correlate with pain or its modulation using longitudinal design studies and carefully designed control conditions. In any case, it is imperative to draw a clear line to distinguish between the clinical or experimental utility of a biomarker and its usefulness in achieving mechanistic insight. A biomarker can demonstrate good utility because it is able to identify clinically meaningful groups of patients with a high sensitivity and specificity (e.g. patients who will respond in a certain way to a specific treatment). However, this does not necessarily imply that the biomarker reflects directly the mechanisms that give rise to a given clinical pain condition, as the patterns of neural activation that allow discrimination between conditions might be entirely epiphenomenal.

Acknowledgements

A.M. and G.D. are grateful to their lab members and colleagues for excellent comments on earlier versions of this manuscript.

Funding

A.M. is supported by the ERC Starting Grant PROBING-PAIN. G.D.I. is supported by the Wellcome Trust and by the ERC Consolidator Grant PAINSTRAT.

Competing interests

The authors report no competing interests.

References

Albe-Fessard
D
,
Berkley
KJ
,
Kruger
L
,
Ralston
HJ
,
3rd
,
Willis
WD
Jr
.
Diencephalic mechanisms of pain sensation
.
Brain Res
1985
;
356
:
217
96
.

Apkarian
AV
,
Bushnell
MC
,
Treede
RD
,
Zubieta
JK
.
Human brain mechanisms of pain perception and regulation in health and disease
.
Eur J Pain
2005
;
9
:
463
84
.

Aru
J
,
Bachmann
T
,
Singer
W
,
Melloni
L
.
Distilling the neural correlates of consciousness
.
Neurosci Biobehav Rev
2012
;
36
:
737
46
.

Baier
B
,
Eulenburg
PZ
,
Geber
C
,
Rohde
F
,
Rolke
R
,
Maihöfner
C
et al. .
Insula and sensory insular cortex and somatosensory control in patients with insular stroke
.
Eur J Pain
2014
;
18
:
1385
93
.

Baliki
MN
,
Chialvo
DR
,
Geha
PY
,
Levy
RM
,
Harden
RN
,
Parrish
TB
et al. .
Chronic pain and the emotional brain: specific brain activity associated with spontaneous fluctuations of intensity of chronic back pain
.
J Neurosci
2006
;
26
:
12165
73
.

Baliki
MN
,
Petre
B
,
Torbey
S
,
Herrmann
KM
,
Huang
L
,
Schnitzer
TJ
et al. .
Corticostriatal functional connectivity predicts transition to chronic back pain
.
Nat Neurosci
2012
;
15
:
1117
19
.

Bantick
SJ
,
Wise
RG
,
Ploghaus
A
,
Clare
S
,
Smith
SM
,
Tracey
I
.
Imaging how attention modulates pain in humans using functional MRI
.
Brain
2002
;
125
(
Pt 2
):
310
19
.

Baumgartner
U
,
Cruccu
G
,
Iannetti
GD
,
Treede
RD
.
Laser guns and hot plates
.
Pain
2005
;
116
:
1
3
.

Bingel
U
,
Lorenz
J
,
Schoell
E
,
Weiller
C
,
Buchel
C
.
Mechanisms of placebo analgesia: rACC recruitment of a subcortical antinociceptive network
.
Pain
2006
;
120
:
8
15
.

Bingel
U
,
Tracey
I
.
Imaging CNS modulation of pain in humans
.
Physiology
2008
;
23
:
371
80
.

Boly
M
,
Faymonville
ME
,
Schnakers
C
,
Peigneux
P
,
Lambermont
B
,
Phillips
C
et al. .
Perception of pain in the minimally conscious state with PET activation: an observational study
.
Lancet Neurol
2008
;
7
:
1013
20
.

Bornhovd
K
,
Quante
M
,
Glauche
V
,
Bromm
B
,
Weiller
C
,
Buchel
C
.
Painful stimuli evoke different stimulus-response functions in the amygdala, prefrontal, insula and somatosensory cortex: a single-trial fMRI study
.
Brain
2002
;
125
(
Pt 6
):
1326
36
.

Borsook
D
,
Becerra
L
,
Hargreaves
R
.
Biomarkers for chronic pain and analgesia. Part 1: the need, reality, challenges, and solutions
.
Discov Med
2011
;
11
:
197
207
.

Borsook
D
,
Moulton
EA
,
Schmidt
KF
,
Becerra
LR
.
Neuroimaging revolutionizes therapeutic approaches to chronic pain
.
Mol Pain
2007
;
3
:
25
.

Borsook
D
,
Sava
S
,
Becerra
L
.
The pain imaging revolution: advancing pain into the 21st century
.
Neuroscientist
2010
;
16
:
171
85
.

Brascher
AK
,
Becker
S
,
Hoeppli
ME
,
Schweinhardt
P
.
Different brain circuitries mediating controllable and uncontrollable pain
.
J Neurosci
2016
;
36
:
5013
25
.

Breivik
H
,
Collett
B
,
Ventafridda
V
,
Cohen
R
,
Gallacher
D
.
Survey of chronic pain in Europe: prevalence, impact on daily life, and treatment
.
Eur J Pain
2006
;
10
:
287
333
.

Brooks
J
,
Tracey
I
.
From nociception to pain perception: imaging the spinal and supraspinal pathways
.
J Anat
2005
;
207
:
19
33
.

Bushnell
MC
,
Apkarian
AV
.
Representation of pain in the brain
. In:
McMahon
S
,
Koltzenburg
M
, editors.
Textbook of pain
. 5th edn.
London
:
Churchill Livingstone
;
2005
. p.
267
89
.

Carmon
A
,
Mor
J
,
Goldberg
J
.
Evoked cerebral responses to noxious thermal stimuli in humans
.
Exp Brain Res
1976
;
25
:
103
7
.

Chapman
CR
,
Colpitts
YH
,
Mayeno
JK
,
Gagliardi
GJ
.
Rate of stimulus repetition changes evoked potential amplitude: dental and auditory modalities compared
.
Exp Brain Res
1981
;
43
:
246
52
.

Chapman
CR
,
Oka
S
,
Bradshaw
DH
,
Jacobson
RC
,
Donaldson
GW
.
Phasic pupil dilation response to noxious stimulation in normal volunteers: relationship to brain evoked potentials and pain report
.
Psychophysiology
1999
;
36
:
44
52
.

Corradi-Dell‘Acqua
C
,
Tusche
A
,
Vuilleumier
P
,
Singer
T
.
Cross-modal representations of first-hand and vicarious pain, disgust and fairness in insular and cingulate cortex
.
Nat Commun
2016
;
7
:
10904
.

Cowen
R
,
Stasiowska
MK
,
Laycock
H
,
Bantel
C
.
Assessing pain objectively: the use of physiological markers
.
Anaesthesia
2015
;
70
:
828
47
.

Davis
KD
,
Bushnell
MC
,
Iannetti
GD
,
St Lawrence
K
,
Coghill
R
.
Evidence against pain specificity in the dorsal posterior insula
.
F1000Res
2015
;
4
:
362
.

Davis
KD
,
Flor
H
,
Greely
HT
,
Iannetti
GD
,
Mackey
S
,
Ploner
M
et al. .
Brain imaging tests for chronic pain: medical, legal and ethical issues and recommendations
.
Nat Rev Neurol
2017
;
13
:
624
38
.

Davis
KD
,
Seminowicz
DA
.
Insights for clinicians from brain imaging studies of pain
.
Clin J Pain
2017
;
33
:
291
4
.

De Simone
R
,
Ranieri
A
,
Montella
S
,
Bonavita
V
.
Cortical spreading depression and central pain networks in trigeminal nuclei modulation: time for an integrated migraine pathogenesis perspective
.
Neurol Sci
2013
;
34
(Suppl 1):
S51
5
.

de Tommaso
M
,
Losito
L
,
Difruscolo
O
,
Libro
G
,
Guido
M
,
Livrea
P
.
Changes in cortical processing of pain in chronic migraine
.
Headache
2005
;
45
:
1208
18
.

de Vries
M
,
Wilder-Smith
OH
,
Jongsma
ML
,
van den Broeke
EN
,
Arns
M
,
van Goor
H
et al. .
Altered resting state EEG in chronic pancreatitis patients: toward a marker for chronic pain
.
J Pain Res
2013
;
6
:
815
24
.

Defrin
R
,
Amanzio
M
,
de Tommaso
M
,
Dimova
V
,
Filipovic
S
,
Finn
DP
et al. .
Experimental pain processing in individuals with cognitive impairment: current state of the science
.
Pain
2015
;
156
:
1396
408
.

Denk
F
,
McMahon
SB
,
Tracey
I
.
Pain vulnerability: a neurobiological perspective
.
Nat Neurosci
2014
;
17
:
192
200
.

Di Clemente
L
,
Puledda
F
,
Biasiotta
A
,
Vigano
A
,
Vicenzini
E
,
Truini
A
et al. .
Topiramate modulates habituation in migraine: evidences from nociceptive responses elicited by laser evoked potentials
.
J Headache Pain
2013
;
14
:
25
.

Doetsch
GS
.
Patterns in the brain. Neuronal population coding in the somatosensory system
.
Physiol Behav
2000
;
69
:
187
201
.

Dong
WK
,
Chudler
EH
,
Sugiyama
K
,
Roberts
VJ
,
Hayashi
T
.
Somatosensory, multisensory, and task-related neurons in cortical area 7b (PF) of unanesthetized monkeys
.
J Neurophysiol
1994
;
72
:
542
64
.

Dong
WK
,
Salonen
LD
,
Kawakami
Y
,
Shiwaku
T
,
Kaukoranta
EM
,
Martin
RF
.
Nociceptive responses of trigeminal neurons in SII-7b cortex of awake monkeys
.
Brain Res
1989
;
484
:
314
24
.

Downar
J
,
Mikulis
DJ
,
Davis
KD
.
Neural correlates of the prolonged salience of painful stimulation
.
Neuroimage
2003
;
20
:
1540
51
.

Dum
RP
,
Levinthal
DJ
,
Strick
PL
.
The spinothalamic system targets motor and sensory areas in the cerebral cortex of monkeys
.
J Neurosci
2009
;
29
:
14223
35
.

Eisenach
JC
,
Curry
R
,
Aschenbrenner
CA
,
Coghill
RC
,
Houle
TT
.
Pupil responses and pain ratings to heat stimuli: reliability and effects of expectations and a conditioning pain stimulus
.
J Neurosci Methods
2017
;
279
:
52
9
.

Erickson
R
.
Sensory neural patterns and gustation
. In:
Zotterman
Y
, editor.
Proceedings of the first international symposium on olfaction and taste
.
New York
:
Pergamon Press
;
1963
. p.
205
13
.

Erickson
RP
.
On the intensive aspect of the temperature sense
.
Brain Res
1973
;
61
:
113
18
.

Foltz
EL
,
White
LE
.
The role of rostral cingulumotomy in ‘pain’ relief
.
Int J Neurol
1968
;
6
:
353
73
.

Foltz
EL
,
White
LE
Jr
.
Pain ‘relief’ by frontal cingulumotomy
.
J Neurosurg
1962
;
19
:
89
100
.

Garcia-Larrea
L
,
Frot
M
,
Valeriani
M
.
Brain generators of laser-evoked potentials: from dipoles to functional significance
.
Neurophysiol Clin
2003
;
33
:
279
92
.

Garcia-Larrea
L
,
Perchet
C
,
Creac‘h
C
,
Convers
P
,
Peyron
R
,
Laurent
B
et al. .
Operculo-insular pain (parasylvian pain): a distinct central pain syndrome
.
Brain
2010
;
133
:
2528
39
.

Goksan
S
,
Hartley
C
,
Emery
F
,
Cockrill
N
,
Poorun
R
,
Moultrie
F
et al. .
fMRI reveals neural activity overlap between adult and infant pain
.
Elife
2015
;
4
:
e06356
.

Gram
M
,
Graversen
C
,
Nielsen
AK
,
Arendt-Nielsen
T
,
Morch
CD
,
Andresen
T
et al. .
A novel approach to pharmaco-EEG for investigating analgesics: assessment of spectral indices in single-sweep evoked brain potentials
.
Br J Clin Pharmacol
2013
;
76
:
951
63
.

Grosen
K
,
Olesen
AE
,
Gram
M
,
Jonsson
T
,
Kamp-Jensen
M
,
Andresen
T
et al. .
Predictors of opioid efficacy in patients with chronic pain: a prospective multicenter observational cohort study
.
PLoS One
2017
;
12
:
e0171723
.

Hartley
C
,
Duff
EP
,
Green
G
,
Mellado
GS
,
Worley
A
,
Rogers
R
et al. .
Nociceptive brain activity as a measure of analgesic efficacy in infants
.
Sci Transl Med
2017
;
9
:
eaah6122
.

Hodges
PW
,
Tucker
K
.
Moving differently in pain: a new theory to explain the adaptation to pain
.
Pain
2011
;
152
(3 Suppl):
S90
8
.

Hodkinson
DJ
,
Krause
K
,
Khawaja
N
,
Renton
TF
,
Huggins
JP
,
Vennart
W
et al. .
Quantifying the test-retest reliability of cerebral blood flow measurements in a clinical model of on-going post-surgical pain: a study using pseudo-continuous arterial spin labelling
.
Neuroimage Clin
2013
;
3
:
301
10
.

Hofbauer
RK
,
Rainville
P
,
Duncan
GH
,
Bushnell
MC
.
Cortical representation of the sensory dimension of pain
.
J Neurophysiol
2001
;
86
:
402
11
.

Hoffman
KM
,
Trawalter
S
,
Axt
JR
,
Oliver
MN
.
Racial bias in pain assessment and treatment recommendations, and false beliefs about biological differences between blacks and whites
.
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA
2016
;
113
:
4296
301
.

Horikawa
T
,
Tamaki
M
,
Miyawaki
Y
,
Kamitani
Y
.
Neural decoding of visual imagery during sleep
.
Science
2013
;
340
:
639
42
.

Howard
MA
,
Krause
K
,
Khawaja
N
,
Massat
N
,
Zelaya
F
,
Schumann
G
et al. .
Beyond patient reported pain: perfusion magnetic resonance imaging demonstrates reproducible cerebral representation of ongoing post-surgical pain
.
PLoS One
2011
;
6
:
e17096
.

Hu
L
,
Iannetti
GD
.
Issues in pain prediction—beyond pain and gain
.
Trends Neurosci
2016
;
39
:
640
2
.

Huang
G
,
Xiao
P
,
Hung
YS
,
Iannetti
GD
,
Zhang
ZG
,
Hu
L
.
A novel approach to predict subjective pain perception from single-trial laser-evoked potentials
.
Neuroimage
2013
;
81
:
283
93
.

Hutchison
WD
,
Davis
KD
,
Lozano
AM
,
Tasker
RR
,
Dostrovsky
JO
.
Pain-related neurons in the human cingulate cortex
.
Nat Neurosci
1999
;
2
:
403
5
.

Iannetti
GD
,
Hughes
NP
,
Lee
MC
,
Mouraux
A
.
Determinants of laser-evoked EEG responses: pain perception or stimulus saliency?
J Neurophysiol
2008
;
100
:
815
28
.

Iannetti
GD
,
Leandri
M
,
Truini
A
,
Zambreanu
L
,
Cruccu
G
,
Tracey
I
.
Adelta nociceptor response to laser stimuli: selective effect of stimulus duration on skin temperature, brain potentials and pain perception
.
Clin Neurophysiol
2004
;
115
:
2629
37
.

Iannetti
GD
,
Mouraux
A
.
From the neuromatrix to the pain matrix (and back)
.
Exp Brain Res
2010
;
205
:
1
12
.

Iannetti
GD
,
Salomons
TV
,
Moayedi
M
,
Mouraux
A
,
Davis
KD
.
Beyond metaphor: contrasting mechanisms of social and physical pain
.
Trends Cogn Sci
2013
;
17
:
371
8
.

Iannetti
GD
,
Wise
RG
.
BOLD functional MRI in disease and pharmacological studies: room for improvement?
Magn Reson Imaging
2007
;
25
:
978
88
.

Iannetti
GD
,
Zambreanu
L
,
Wise
RG
,
Buchanan
TJ
,
Huggins
JP
,
Smart
TS
et al. .
Pharmacological modulation of pain-related brain activity during normal and central sensitization states in humans
.
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA
2005
;
102
:
18195
200
.

Ingvar
M
.
Pain and functional imaging
.
Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci
1999
;
354
:
1347
58
.

Isnard
J
,
Magnin
M
,
Jung
J
,
Mauguiere
F
,
Garcia-Larrea
L
.
Does the insula tell our brain that we are in pain?
Pain
2011
;
152
:
946
51
.

Jin
Q
,
Wu
G
,
Peng
W
,
Xia
X
,
Hu
L
,
Iannetti
G
.
Somatotopic representation of second pain in the primary somatosensory cortex of humans and rodents
.
J Neurosci
2018
;
38
:
5538
50
.

Kenshalo
DR
,
Iwata
K
,
Sholas
M
,
Thomas
DA
.
Response properties and organization of nociceptive neurons in area 1 of monkey primary somatosensory cortex
.
J Neurophysiol
2000
;
84
:
719
29
.

Kenshalo
DR
Jr,
Isensee
O
.
Responses of primate SI cortical neurons to noxious stimuli
.
J Neurophysiol
1983
;
50
:
1479
96
.

Khasabov
SG
,
Cain
DM
,
Thong
D
,
Mantyh
PW
,
Simone
DA
.
Enhanced responses of spinal dorsal horn neurons to heat and cold stimuli following mild freeze injury to the skin
.
J Neurophysiol
2001
;
86
:
986
96
.

Kragel
PA
,
Kano
M
,
Van Oudenhove
L
,
Ly
HG
,
Dupont
P
,
Rubio
A
et al. .
Generalizable representations of pain, cognitive control, and negative emotion in medial frontal cortex
.
Nat Neurosci
2018
;
21
:
283
9
.

Kross
E
,
Berman
MG
,
Mischel
W
,
Smith
EE
,
Wager
TD
.
Social rejection shares somatosensory representations with physical pain
.
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA
2011
;
108
:
6270
5
.

Kucyi
A
,
Davis
KD
.
The dynamic pain connectome
.
Trends Neurosci
2015
;
38
:
86
95
.

Kucyi
A
,
Davis
KD
.
The neural code for pain: from single-cell electrophysiology to the dynamic pain connectome
.
Neuroscientist
2017
;
23
:
397
414
.

Kumbhare
DA
,
Elzibak
AH
,
Noseworthy
MD
.
Evaluation of chronic pain using magnetic resonance (mr) neuroimaging approaches: what the clinician needs to know
.
Clin J Pain
2017
;
33
:
281
90
.

Kupers
R
,
Kehlet
H
.
Brain imaging of clinical pain states: a critical review and strategies for future studies
.
Lancet Neurol
2006
;
5
:
1033
44
.

Lee
MC
,
Tracey
I
.
Imaging pain: a potent means for investigating pain mechanisms in patients
.
Br J Anaesth
2013
;
111
:
64
72
.

Lee
MC
,
Zambreanu
L
,
Menon
DK
,
Tracey
I
.
Identifying brain activity specifically related to the maintenance and perceptual consequence of central sensitization in humans
.
J Neurosci
2008
;
28
:
11642
9
.

Lelic
D
,
Olesen
SS
,
Valeriani
M
,
Drewes
AM
.
Brain source connectivity reveals the visceral pain network
.
Neuroimage
2012
;
60
:
37
46
.

Liberati
G
,
Klocker
A
,
Algoet
M
,
Mulders
D
,
Safronova
MM
,
Ferrao Santos
S
et al. .
Gamma-band oscillations preferential for nociception can be recorded in the human insula
.
Cereb Cortex
2018
;
28
:
3650
64
.

Liberati
G
,
Klocker
A
,
Safronova
MM
,
Ferrao Santos
S
,
Ribeiro Vaz
JG
,
Raftopoulos
C
et al. .
Nociceptive local field potentials recorded from the human insula are not specific for nociception
.
PLoS Biol
2016
;
14
:
e1002345
.

Lieberman
MD
,
Eisenberger
NI
.
The dorsal anterior cingulate cortex is selective for pain: results from large-scale reverse inference
.
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA
2015
;
112
:
15250
5
.

Lindquist
MA
,
Krishnan
A
,
Lopez-Sola
M
,
Jepma
M
,
Woo
CW
,
Koban
L
et al. .
Group-regularized individual prediction: theory and application to pain
.
Neuroimage
2017
;
145
(
Pt B
):
274
87
.

Longo
MR
,
Iannetti
GD
,
Mancini
F
,
Driver
J
,
Haggard
P
.
Linking pain and the body: neural correlates of visually induced analgesia
.
J Neurosci
2012
;
32
:
2601
7
.

Mancini
F
,
Haggard
P
,
Iannetti
GD
,
Longo
MR
,
Sereno
MI
.
Fine-grained nociceptive maps in primary somatosensory cortex
.
J Neurosci
2012
;
32
:
17155
62
.

Marshall
O
,
Lu
H
,
Brisset
JC
,
Xu
F
,
Liu
P
,
Herbert
J
et al. .
Impaired cerebrovascular reactivity in multiple sclerosis
.
JAMA Neurol
2014
;
71
:
1275
81
.

Martucci
KT
,
Ng
P
,
Mackey
S
.
Neuroimaging chronic pain: what have we learned and where are we going?
Future Neurol
2014
;
9
:
615
26
.

Mazzola
L
,
Isnard
J
,
Peyron
R
,
Mauguiere
F
.
Stimulation of the human cortex and the experience of pain: Wilder Penfield‘s observations revisited
.
Brain
2012
;
135 (Pt 2)
:
631
40
.

Melzack
R
.
From the gate to the neuromatrix
.
Pain
1999
; Suppl 6:
S121
6
.

Melzack
R
.
Evolution of the neuromatrix theory of pain. The Prithvi Raj Lecture: presented at the third World Congress of World Institute of Pain, Barcelona 2004
.
Pain Pract
2005
;
5
:
85
94
.

Merskey
H
,
Bogduk
N
.
Pain terms, a current list with definitions and notes on usage. IASP task force on taxonomy
. In:
Merskey
H
,
Bogduk
N
, editors.
Classification of chronic pain
.
Seattle
:
IASP Press
;
1994
. p.
209
14
.

Morton
DL
,
Sandhu
JS
,
Jones
AK
.
Brain imaging of pain: state of the art
.
J Pain Res
2016
;
9
:
613
24
.

Mouraux
A
,
Diukova
A
,
Lee
MC
,
Wise
RG
,
Iannetti
GD
.
A multisensory investigation of the functional significance of the ‘pain matrix’
.
Neuroimage
2011
;
54
:
2237
49
.

Mouraux
A
,
Iannetti
GD
.
Nociceptive laser-evoked brain potentials do not reflect nociceptive-specific neural activity
.
J Neurophysiol
2009
;
101
:
3258
69
.

Norrsell
U
,
Finger
S
,
Lajonchere
C
.
Cutaneous sensory spots and the ‘law of specific nerve energies’: history and development of ideas
.
Brain Res Bull
1999
;
48
:
457
65
.

Novembre
G
,
Zanon
M
,
Silani
G
.
Empathy for social exclusion involves the sensory-discriminative component of pain: a within-subject fMRI study
.
Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci
2015
;
10
:
153
64
.

Petrovic
P
,
Kalso
E
,
Petersson
KM
,
Ingvar
M
.
Placebo and opioid analgesia—imaging a shared neuronal network
.
Science
2002
;
295
:
1737
40
.

Peyron
R
,
Laurent
B
,
Garcia-Larrea
L
.
Functional imaging of brain responses to pain. A review and meta-analysis (2000)
.
Neurophysiol Clin
2000
;
30
:
263
88
.

Ploghaus
A
,
Tracey
I
,
Gati
JS
,
Clare
S
,
Menon
RS
,
Matthews
PM
et al. .
Dissociating pain from its anticipation in the human brain
.
Science
1999
;
284
:
1979
81
.

Ploner
M
,
Freund
HJ
,
Schnitzler
A
.
Pain affect without pain sensation in a patient with a postcentral lesion
.
Pain
1999
;
81
:
211
14
.

Poldrack
RA
.
Can cognitive processes be inferred from neuroimaging data?
Trends Cogn Sci
2006
;
10
:
59
63
.

Prescott
SA
,
Ma
Q
,
De Koninck
Y
.
Normal and abnormal coding of somatosensory stimuli causing pain
.
Nat Neurosci
2014
;
17
:
183
91
.

Rainville
P
,
Duncan
GH
,
Price
DD
,
Carrier
B
,
Bushnell
MC
.
Pain affect encoded in human anterior cingulate but not somatosensory cortex
.
Science
1997
;
277
:
968
71
.

Reardon
S
.
Neuroscience in court: the painful truth
.
Nature
2015
;
518
:
474
6
.

Robinson
CJ
,
Burton
H
.
Somatic submodality distribution within the second somatosensory (SII), 7b, retroinsular, postauditory, and granular insular cortical areas of M
.
fascicularis. J Comp Neurol
1980
;
192
:
93
108
.

Robinson
CJ
,
Burton
H
.
Somatotopographic organization in the second somatosensory area of M
.
fascicularis. J Comp Neurol
1980
;
192
:
43
67
.

Robinson
ME
,
Staud
R
,
Price
DD
.
Pain measurement and brain activity: will neuroimages replace pain ratings?
J Pain
2013
;
14
:
323
7
.

Salmanowitz
N
.
The case for pain neuroimaging in the courtroom: lessons from deception detection
.
J Law Biosci
2015
;
2
:
139
48
.

Salomons
TV
,
Iannetti
GD
,
Liang
M
,
Wood
JN
.
The ‘pain matrix’ in pain-free individuals
.
JAMA Neurol
2016
;
73
:
755
6
.

Schafer
SM
,
Geuter
S
,
Wager
TD
.
Mechanisms of placebo analgesia: a dual-process model informed by insights from cross-species comparisons
.
Prog Neurobiol
2018
;
160
:
101
22
.

Schulz
E
,
May
ES
,
Postorino
M
,
Tiemann
L
,
Nickel
MM
,
Witkovsky
V
et al. .
Prefrontal gamma oscillations encode tonic pain in humans
.
Cereb Cortex
2015
;
25
:
4407
14
.

Schulz
E
,
Zherdin
A
,
Tiemann
L
,
Plant
C
,
Ploner
M
.
Decoding an individual‘s sensitivity to pain from the multivariate analysis of EEG data
.
Cereb Cortex
2012
;
22
:
118
23
.

Schweinhardt
P
,
Bountra
C
,
Tracey
I
.
Pharmacological FMRI in the development of new analgesic compounds
.
NMR Biomed
2006
;
19
:
702
11
.

Segerdahl
AR
,
Mezue
M
,
Okell
TW
,
Farrar
JT
,
Tracey
I
.
The dorsal posterior insula subserves a fundamental role in human pain
.
Nat Neurosci
2015
;
18
:
499
500
.

Seifert
F
,
Maihofner
C
.
Functional and structural imaging of pain-induced neuroplasticity
.
Curr Opin Anaesthesiol
2011
;
24
:
515
23
.

Senn
S
.
Invalid inversion
.
Significance
2013
;
10
:
40
2
.

Shackman
AJ
,
Salomons
TV
,
Slagter
HA
,
Fox
AS
,
Winter
JJ
,
Davidson
RJ
.
The integration of negative affect, pain and cognitive control in the cingulate cortex
.
Nat Rev Neurosci
2011
;
12
:
154
67
.

Sikes
RW
,
Vogt
BA
.
Nociceptive neurons in area 24 of rabbit cingulate cortex
.
J Neurophysiol
1992
;
68
:
1720
32
.

Sporns
O
.
The human connectome: origins and challenges
.
Neuroimage
2013
;
80
:
53
61
.

Sullivan
MD
,
Cahana
A
,
Derbyshire
S
,
Loeser
JD
.
What does it mean to call chronic pain a brain disease?
J Pain
2013
;
14
:
317
22
.

Tetreault
P
,
Mansour
A
,
Vachon-Presseau
E
,
Schnitzer
TJ
,
Apkarian
AV
,
Baliki
MN
.
Brain connectivity predicts placebo response across chronic pain clinical trials
.
PLoS Biol
2016
;
14
:
e1002570
.

Tinnermann
A
,
Geuter
S
,
Sprenger
C
,
Finsterbusch
J
,
Buchel
C
.
Interactions between brain and spinal cord mediate value effects in nocebo hyperalgesia
.
Science
2017
;
358
:
105
8
.

Torebjork
HE
,
LaMotte
RH
,
Robinson
CJ
.
Peripheral neural correlates of magnitude of cutaneous pain and hyperalgesia: simultaneous recordings in humans of sensory judgments of pain and evoked responses in nociceptors with C-fibers
.
J Neurophysiol
1984
;
51
:
325
39
.

Tracey
I
.
Can neuroimaging studies identify pain endophenotypes in humans?
Nat Rev Neurol
2011
;
7
:
173
81
.

Tracey
I
.
Neuroimaging mechanisms in pain: from discovery to translation
.
Pain
2017
;
158
(Suppl 1):
S115
22
.

Tracey
I
,
Mantyh
PW
.
The cerebral signature for pain perception and its modulation
.
Neuron
2007
;
55
:
377
91
.

Treede
RD
,
Kenshalo
DR
,
Gracely
RH
,
Jones
AK
.
The cortical representation of pain
.
Pain
1999
;
79
:
105
11
.

Vessman
J
.
Selectivity or specificity? Validation of analytical methods from the perspective of an analytical chemist in the pharmaceutical industry
.
J Pharm Biomed Anal
1996
;
14
:
867
9
.

Vierck
CJ
,
Whitsel
BL
,
Favorov
OV
,
Brown
AW
,
Tommerdahl
M
.
Role of primary somatosensory cortex in the coding of pain
.
Pain
2013
;
154
:
334
44
.

Wager
TD
,
Atlas
LY
,
Botvinick
MM
,
Chang
LJ
,
Coghill
RC
,
Davis
KD
et al. .
Pain in the ACC?
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA
2016
;
113
:
E2474
5
.

Wager
TD
,
Atlas
LY
,
Lindquist
MA
,
Roy
M
,
Woo
CW
,
Kross
E
.
An fMRI-based neurologic signature of physical pain
.
N Engl J Med
2013
;
368
:
1388
97
.

Wager
TD
,
Rilling
JK
,
Smith
EE
,
Sokolik
A
,
Casey
KL
,
Davidson
RJ
et al. .
Placebo-induced changes in FMRI in the anticipation and experience of pain
.
Science
2004
;
303
:
1162
7
.

Wager
TD
,
Scott
DJ
,
Zubieta
JK
.
Placebo effects on human mu-opioid activity during pain
.
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA
2007
;
104
:
11056
61
.

Wall
PD
.
Independent mechanisms converge on pain
.
Nat Med
1995
;
1
:
740
1
.

Wartolowska
K
,
Tracey
I
.
Neuroimaging as a tool for pain diagnosis and analgesic development
.
Neurotherapeutics
2009
;
6
:
755
60
.

Wasan
AD
,
Loggia
ML
,
Chen
LQ
,
Napadow
V
,
Kong
J
,
Gollub
RL
.
Neural correlates of chronic low back pain measured by arterial spin labeling
.
Anesthesiology
2011
;
115
:
364
74
.

Willer
JC
,
Roby
A
,
Le Bars
D
.
Psychophysical and electrophysiological approaches to the pain-relieving effects of heterotopic nociceptive stimuli
.
Brain
1984
;
107
(
Pt 4
):
1095
112
.

Wise
RG
,
Tracey
I
.
The role of fMRI in drug discovery
.
J Magn Reson Imaging
2006
;
23
:
862
76
.

Woo
CW
,
Roy
M
,
Buhle
JT
,
Wager
TD
.
Distinct brain systems mediate the effects of nociceptive input and self-regulation on pain
.
PLoS Biol
2015
;
13
:
e1002036
.

Woo
CW
,
Schmidt
L
,
Krishnan
A
,
Jepma
M
,
Roy
M
,
Lindquist
MA
et al. .
Quantifying cerebral contributions to pain beyond nociception
.
Nat Commun
2017
;
8
:
14211
.

Woolf
CJ
.
Novel analgesic development: from target to patient or patient to target?
Curr Opin Investig Drugs
2008
;
9
:
694
5
.

Woolf
CJ
,
Max
MB
.
Mechanism-based pain diagnosis: issues for analgesic drug development
.
Anesthesiology
2001
;
95
:
241
9
.

Yamamura
H
,
Iwata
K
,
Tsuboi
Y
,
Toda
K
,
Kitajima
K
,
Shimizu
N
et al. .
Morphological and electrophysiological properties of ACCx nociceptive neurons in rats
.
Brain Res
1996
;
735
:
83
92
.

Yarkoni
T
. No, the dorsal anterior cingulate is not selective for pain: comment on Lieberman and Eisenberger (2015) [Internet]. [citation needed] 2015 [cited
2018
Sept 28] Available from: http://www.talyarkoni.org/blog/2015/12/05/no-the-dorsal-anterior-cingulate-is-not-selective-for-pain-comment-on-lieberman-and-eisenberger-2015/

Zambreanu
L
,
Wise
RG
,
Brooks
JC
,
Iannetti
GD
,
Tracey
I
.
A role for the brainstem in central sensitisation in humans. Evidence from functional magnetic resonance imaging
.
Pain
2005
;
114
:
397
407
.

Zubieta
JK
,
Bueller
JA
,
Jackson
LR
,
Scott
DJ
,
Xu
Y
,
Koeppe
RA
et al. .
Placebo effects mediated by endogenous opioid activity on mu-opioid receptors
.
J Neurosci
2005
;
25
:
7754
62
.

This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted reuse, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.