Abstract

The consumer welfare standard is a hotly debated issue in antitrust enforcement. Some present it as an obstacle that prevents antitrust from being more responsive to pressing social issues and non-economic interests. Others defend it. While polarized, those discussions often share a common feature: they are intelligent design narratives. Still, arguments have also been made that much of antitrust results from more evolutionary, uncoordinated adaptations. In consequence, antitrust might not be easily changed by political fiat. This article investigates such a more organic way of looking at antitrust and asks what it may mean for attempts to change antitrust. It identifies possible ‘workability’ factors steering decision-makers towards a specific shape of antitrust. It argues, however, that while evolutionary developments may have an impact on antitrust, the specific course of those evolutionary movements is affected by the subjectivity of decision-makers. This subjectivity can be influenced by the general climate of opinion, cultural capture, and narrative preference. The article concludes that ideology should not be discarded as a force impacting antitrust, and that workability together with subjectivity-affecting factors can be seen as producing ‘antitrust memes’—something that at a given time people know they should spread.

1. INTRODUCTION

There is nothing more powerful than an idea whose time has come.1 In antitrust, this idea was once the consumer welfare standard. Its time came in the 1970s—it contributed to the Chicago revolution in antitrust and determined the evolution of enforcement for the next few decades. As of today, however, it is strongly contested.2 It is argued that it curtailed antitrust to the point of near irrelevance, that the philosophy associated with it has been ‘misguided’, and that it prevents addressing pressing issues of the modern day.3 This may concern typical areas of economic activity but also protecting special values such as sustainability, labour welfare, media pluralism, free speech, and privacy.4 In short, aside from more orthodox enforcement, it is claimed that, among its many alleged sins, antitrust is not doing enough from the point of view of what can be called the ‘moral sentiments’ of society.5 From this angle, antitrust is in a deep crisis or at least in need of change.6 A more recent criticism is also that while in the USA major antitrust projects are considered, it is allegedly ‘incremental change’ that is ‘still the order of the day’ in Europe.7

To find support for antitrust reform, the original goals of antitrust are considered once again (insofar as it is believed that the goals of antitrust are constant but that their interpretation has been wrong).8 Furthermore, new sources of legitimacy for an updated version of antitrust policy are investigated (insofar as it is believed that antitrust goals are dynamic and may adapt over time).9 Those attempts often end up with proposals that the consumer welfare standard should be dropped or reimagined.10 Under this narrative, the Chicago School is also often blamed for hijacking antitrust and reshaping it in accordance with its own ideological preferences.11 From this angle, antitrust becomes a product of intelligent design: antitrust was once shaped to fit a specific vision and serve a specific goal, which can now be easily changed. If this is done, a broad range of socio-economic concerns could be better addressed.12

This, however, is not the only way of looking at the dynamics that drive antitrust. Within the current antitrust debate, some have argued that the turn towards Chicago-style enforcement was not simply ideologically motivated but followed from practical considerations that gave rise to a certain set of antitrust limits.13 As opposed to intelligent design, this perspective is, implicitly, more evolutionary: guided by an invisible hand, antitrust drifted towards a certain way of operating because this is what worked in practice. Antitrust enforcers and judges (decision-makers) address, on an ongoing basis, practical challenges that were not decided at the level of legislative acts; and they need to do this in a way that works. This can be called the workability impediments of antitrust. From this point of view, many attempts to reconceptualize antitrust may be futile. They focus on idealized visions of what antitrust could do, yet they ignore that what antitrust does in practice comes not so much from any ‘vision of the anointed’ but from limits and limitations that are inherently interwoven into the fabric of legal rules and institutions that enforce them. Tampering too much and too quickly with this complex system is risky.

The claim that antitrust develops in a more organic and evolutionary way, producing a set of antitrust limits, is not insignificant. For ‘reformers’, this would mean that their attempts might face additional obstacles, requiring additional work to bypass them; for ‘sceptics’, the argument offers an additional reason to believe that the reformers are wrong, providing also a kind of re-assurance that most radical reforms will not succeed.14

The goal of this article is to explore, in theoretical terms, to what extent antitrust might be bound by such practicality (workability) factors that emerge bottom-up. The claim that there are some natural limits to antitrust is interesting, and a better understanding of how those limits come into existence should contribute to a better understanding of how changes in antitrust take place. If changes are determined by practical considerations, then ideology can be expected to matter less, as even if it manages to initiate policy shifts, the ‘system’ will sooner or later erase them, trying instead to ensure workability, which under this interpretation remains the main concern. Conversely, if those are ideological considerations that are of primary importance, then to understand antitrust, one should attach utmost interest to what happens around antitrust. Basic intuition might suggest that the truth lies somewhere in the middle. Still, such general knowledge is not entirely satisfactory: basic intuition also says that if something is thrown into the air, it will eventually fall—yet what is actually interesting are the mechanics and specific forces behind such processes. This article seeks to map them out.

The perspective provided in this article is that of an active enforcer. The point of view is generally European but the overall outlook is transatlantic and aimed at re-evaluation. In consequence, the discussion offered in this article tries to abstract away from specific developments in the USA and the European Union (EU), attempting instead to frame them in more general terms. Furthermore, while the question is often how antitrust should change under some intelligent design perspective (a normative and dogmatic issue), this article asks how antitrust may be changing (a factual and realist issue).

To fulfil the task outlined above, the article is divided into four parts. First, it provides an overview of the current antitrust debate, discussing how the intelligent design and evolutionary perspectives seem to be implicitly, and sometimes more explicitly, present in the debate (Section 2). The discussion then moves to workability factors that may be relevant to decision-makers, and which—under the more evolutionary perspective—can be expected to influence antitrust enforcement, giving rise to what some authors call the ‘limits’ of antitrust (Section 3). A short theoretical exercise is proposed to see whether the workability side of antitrust always needs to work against a broader conception of enforcement—‘non-economic interests’ are used as a testing device and a more extreme kind of development, but—by extension—the discussion remains relevant to more moderate types of antitrust reform. The article suggests that while workability matters, it is not the only driving force behind antitrust evolution and that ideology might have a greater influence on antitrust than some assume (Section 4). With this descriptive work done, the last substantive part of the article (Section 5) argues that changes in antitrust can be seen as a more complex, ‘memetic’ process—it suggests what this may mean for three groups active in the current antitrust debate: the reformers, the sceptics, and the more neutral observers and participants.

2. ON THE ORIGIN OF LIMITS

To situate the issue outlined in the introduction, this section provides an overview of some of the features of the current antitrust debate. It explores the underlying intelligent design and evolutionary perspectives present in arguments that are currently made. Taking into account that the level of tension present in antitrust for the past few years has contributed to large research output, the intention here is not to go through all arguments that have been made—this would exceed the scope of a single article. Still, given this considerable research output, a summary of certain characteristics of the current debate should be of use both from the point of view of full-time academic researchers and, even more so, practitioners who observe this debate and try to form their own opinions about it.

Surface level: standards

At the surface level, much of the current antitrust debate is about the consumer welfare standard, which determined the dynamics of antitrust enforcement in the past few decades. It is undisputed that the consumer welfare standard was vigorously promoted by the Chicago School, in particular Bork, and that it reshaped the way antitrust operates. Part of this process, in particular in the USA, was an argument that the legislative intent behind antitrust had been the maximization of consumer welfare.15 Bork himself saw consumer welfare as a shorthand for market efficiency (ie total welfare) and thus, using Adam Smith’s language, ‘merely another term for the wealth of the nation’.16 One of the effects of the Chicago revolution has been that broader goals of antitrust and non-efficiency considerations have fallen out of grace.17 To keep with Adam Smith’s writing style, moral sentiments became a non-issue in antitrust.18 The consumer welfare standard, which originated from the USA, soon rose to prominence also in Europe, in the form of the ‘more economic approach’, which some called ‘Chicago-light’.19

This is now contested. It is argued that the consumer welfare standard was not originally intended for antitrust and that it fails to properly identify market problems.20 Other proposals are put forward. To keep this overview concise, three points seem most relevant. First, it is argued that antitrust has a greater role to play than just concern for the welfare of consumers.21 Secondly, antitrust enforcement should be expanded.22 Thirdly, the consumer welfare standard should be dropped or modified.23 The gist is thus that antitrust should change—both in relation to its economic side and its relationship with wider social goals.

As signalled in the introduction, all those positions can be called ‘intelligent design’ narratives.24 It is argued that the legislature had a specific intent and that for this reason antitrust should operate in a given way. Or that there are some higher goals that should be followed by antitrust decision-makers, and there is a specific way for antitrust to be enforced. This intelligent design attitude is not unnatural. In legal arguments, there is an understandable tendency to support one’s argument with the original intent of the legislature (‘these are not my personal views, this is what the legislature wanted’). Furthermore, making a proposal requires specifying a solution that is designing something.

However, this is not necessarily how antitrust works—this becomes clearer when one looks beneath the surface of the current debate.

Beneath the surface: the antitrust standards paradox

When President Biden presented his executive order aimed at reinvigorating antitrust enforcement in the USA, he pointed at Robert Bork as one of the architects of a failed experiment in antitrust.25 Indeed, Bork’s The Antitrust Paradox remains the central text advocating for the consumer welfare standard. From this angle, the consumer welfare standard can be taken as ‘intelligent design’ by Congress (insofar as Bork was a supporter of originalism and argued that the focus on consumer welfare follows from the legislative intent which he merely discerned) and by Bork himself (insofar as he advocated for specific methods of antitrust analysis).

Yet, what prevailed as the applicable way of resolving cases in most jurisdictions is notoriously not the consumer welfare standard advocated by Bork.26 Assistant Attorney-General Jonathan Kanter’s speech, which was delivered not long after President Biden’s, is noteworthy in that regard.27 In his speech, Kanter argued that the consumer welfare standard requires calculating the welfare effects of market conduct to determine whether they are anti-competitive or not. He therefore called it the ‘central-planning standard’. Likewise, in Europe, some practitioners have argued that the consumer welfare standard is dead and that the idea of quantification is a fallacy.28 Yet, the whole idea of quantification was specifically what Bork wanted to avoid.29

In consequence, beneath the surface level of policy debates—in the second stage of untangling the complex web of antitrust dynamics—there is typically an acknowledgement that the nature of antitrust is more nuanced. Thus, some authors have argued at length that modern antitrust is a complex enterprise relying on a double helix of Chicago and Harvard ideas.30 Others have made calls to better inform decision-makers that the issue of the consumer welfare standard is more difficult than it may seem.31 Within the current debate, AAG Kanter himself has arrived at a conclusion that there are in fact so many definitions of the consumer welfare standard that each lawyer will likely present a different one.32 Indeed, even some of the proponents of the consumer welfare standard admit that the consumer welfare standard may mean at least three things: (i) a strict standard that requires proof of actual price effect; (ii) a soft standard that works as a guide to formulate legal rules of liability or procedure; (iii) a loose standard that works as a priority-setting device.33 All of that does not yet negate the intelligent design perspective but challenges possible arguments of antitrust being a product of solely the Chicago School. At this stage, the picture remains relatively static: antitrust is more complex, its shape is not just a product of Chicago, but it is not apparent what the origins of antitrust limits are.34

Recent discussions in some international fora, such as the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD), have the potential to further illuminate this issue, making it less static. The OECD has suggested bringing more clarity to the problem of assessment standards by segregating and (broadly) defining them.35 It has proposed to distinguish: (i) goals; (ii) standards; and (iii) rules of evidence.36 If standards are broadly (loosely) defined and it is recognized that the consumer welfare standard may use various kinds of presumptions, also structural ones, a jurisdiction may end up with identical results using nominally different standards of assessment. For instance, the competition protection standard is supposed to be more concerned with the process of competition rather than actual effects.37 However, the consumer welfare standard may equally well operate under an assumption that competition should be protected using stricter rules of evidence, for example broad presumptions of anticompetitive effects.38 This can be called an antitrust (standards) paradox.39 The source of this paradox is the fact that decision-makers (judges, enforcers at administrative agencies) have much influence over how evidence and liability are assessed. For example, in the USA, the courts effectively decide over what constitutes a per se violation, which cases are subject to the rule of reason, and how this rule works. In the EU, there are for example ‘by object’ and ‘by effect’ infringements, but the decision-makers decide under which category a violation falls; there is also the concept of appreciable restriction, appreciable effect on trade, and a myriad of technical tests. While there is no full commensurability of the US and EU situation, the point is that by making adjustments at the seemingly least relevant, bottom level, one can obtain a much different shape of antitrust.

Thus, when one looks beneath the surface, it turns out that, in a way, the consumer welfare standard does not exist—not in the sense of some ‘intelligently designed’ core of antitrust that was once adopted top-down and that can be easily removed and replaced by something else.

Depths: the invisible hand of antitrust enforcement

With the intelligent design narrative weakened, it becomes tempting to ask whether maybe antitrust is subject to a much different process. A standard alternative to intelligent design is evolution, with Darwin’s On the Origin of Species being a classic reference for the underlying idea. Darwinian evolution can be understood in two ways: (i) incremental changes and (ii) no focus on any intended design—the latter is in fact more relevant, providing grounds to arguments that complex arrangements may arise without any grand plan.40 In legal and political theory, a descendant of this view is known as an invisible hand explanation—its gist is that an outcome arises as a byproduct of decentralized actions.41

In antitrust, this kind of argument has been recently made by Petit.42 The argument has been that the Neobrandeisians (and some more moderate commentators) overestimate the ideological influence of the Chicago School. Instead, much of how antitrust looks is supposed to follow from practical considerations.43 Those practical considerations are resolved by decision-makers and give rise to certain antitrust limits that cannot be easily changed by ‘political fiat’.44 In the USA, in particular, the law evolved following an incremental and slow process, contributing to those limits.45 Under this argument, practicality becomes the basis for a ‘theory of antitrust limits’ which, in turn, suggests that antitrust needs to respond to the level of uncertainty in a given jurisdiction.46

The practicality argument can also be phrased more indirectly. For example, Hovenkamp argues that antitrust moved away from its ‘movement’ roots with vague slogans towards a more technical perspective focused on practicality, and with decision-makers creating a patchwork of legal tests, often choosing Harvard over Chicago.47 On the other side of the debate, Wu makes a comment in passing that the consumer welfare standard was reinforced by intrinsic features of the court system: judges preferred the consumer welfare standard as it provided them with a simple solution.48 He observes that the Chicago School has ‘given the judiciary an excuse not to do their jobs’ and criticizes this: judges should do their work and make value judgments, not abdicate from their role of judging.49 Yet, at the fundamental level, the point remains similar: practicality won. Judges, led by an invisible hand, started to apply the method of making assessments that allowed them to achieve their goals best. This is a problematic hypothesis from the point of view of antitrust reformers: if the reformers themselves speculate that the judiciary, as a collective, just does not want to ‘do their jobs’, that is, if there is some non-ideological characteristic about the judicial profession that pushes it towards a more Chicagoan perspective, this indicates additional obstacles for antitrust reform.

A theory of antitrust memetics?

On a common sense basis, the invisible hand explanation is not without logic: on the dogmatic level, antitrust can be argued to have certain goals; yet on the practical level, judges and enforcers can be expected to optimize and pursue their own goals as well—this has been part of the legacy of legal realism, including the law and economics movement.50 Thus, to paraphrase Easterbrook, one could say that there is no intelligent design of antitrust, there are only evolutionary outcomes.51 What follows is that since it can be argued that at the basic level, the primary goal of decision-makers is to keep the whole system running, workability becomes an issue. The life of an enforcer and judge is a different life than that of an advocate or academic. Market reality is complex, facts are imperfect, information is costly, the level of uncertainty is high, bizarre cases happen, decision A in case X may have implications for an actual case Y and a hypothetical case Z, cases need to be resolved in a realistic timeframe, etc. From the point of view of reforming antitrust, workability gains therefore a more distinct character: it is not just that a certain vision of antitrust should be workable in the sense of a normative claim, but that it needs to be workable to survive and actually be utilized by decision-makers.

However, doubts can be cast over the invisible-hand explanation as well. For example, if one looks at the developments in the EU in the 1990s from the point of view of the invisible hand theory, this becomes questionable, because the more economic approach was implemented top-down by the European Commission without any apparent ‘invisible’, incremental, evolutionary interaction.52 Likewise, if one takes Petit’s theory of antitrust limits, which focuses on practicality and resolving the issue of uncertainty, the EU part of antitrust history also does not seem entirely persuasive: it does not seem that the EU decision-makers were resolving any uncertainty issue, but rather simply aligned the EU system with that already in place in the USA. Technically, this does not falsify any claim in relation to the USA, but it weakens the aforementioned theories as a more general explanation.

The remaining part of this article reconstructs this picture in a way that addresses those deficiencies, resolving also the tension between the workability argument and the widespread belief that the Chicago School exerted a strong ideological influence on antitrust. The article also suggests to reformulate what has been called by Petit the ‘theory of antitrust limits’, proposing a different focus for future research. Since effectively the question here is about the relationship between intelligent design and invisible hand explanations—both of which come down to imitating someone (ie either imitating the author of a design, or decision-makers imitating each other, while choosing the most practical arrangement in a process of iterated interactions)—the description provided further is provisionally called a ‘theory of antitrust memetics’.53 This is to highlight that imitation might play a more important role in antitrust than one could assume. A short methodological note seems appropriate here. In empirical sciences, some have argued that one of the main features of a theory is the process of its falsification and its predictive value.54 In social sciences (law, economics, political sciences) this causes controversy, due to inherent problems with testability.55 However, even in natural sciences, the classic claim concerning the ability to falsify a theory weakened over time.56 With this caveat in mind, this article uses the word ‘theory’ in a derivative form, related to the claims that have already been made in antitrust scholarship.57 It is thus mostly a discursive device aimed at describing how antitrust changes.58

To do so, Section 3 discusses what ‘workability’ may mean for decision-makers. To see whether workability inevitably leads to an approximation of Chicago antitrust proposals, it is explored whether a non-economic interest can find a way into antitrust analysis, even assuming a more evolutionary, ‘invisible’ dynamic of antitrust. Section 4 provides further comments on what might impact the perception of workability, and Section 5 restates the entire argument, discussing what it may mean for various members of the antitrust community. Section 6 concludes.

3. ANTITRUST IDEALS AND REALITY

Workability is where the antitrust ideals of an intelligent design meet the harsh reality of everyday enforcement. Without resorting to a full-blown sociological study investigating what enforcers and judges consider workable, one can try to discern the parameters of ‘workability’ with enough degree of precision based on existing literature and reasonable prediction. After doing so, this section discusses five areas in which decision-makers can move certain elements to alter antitrust through incremental changes.

Parameters

Workability appears explicitly in Easterbrook’s 1980s writing, with the Chicago School being called the ‘Workable Antitrust Policy School’ that relies on scepticism towards the ability of decision-makers to administer economic models and improve market outcomes, given the difficulties in appraising what business practices do.59 While Easterbrook does not define workability, his meaning of the term appears to come down to performance tests: Chicago is workable, because it eliminates the most controversial practices, leaving more ambiguous ones to be eliminated by the market, due to their inefficiency.60 Bork, in turn, mentions administrability and internal consistency as important factors.61 Arguments were also made that antitrust would never produce a workable standard, unless it dropped its constitutional mode of interpretation in favour of ordinary statutory interpretation, which would remove disagreements between the Chicago, post-Chicago, and populist sentiments in antitrust, ensuring at the same time predictability and consistency.62

The situation is not much different today. Hovenkamp, for example, speaks about antitrust problems in terms of administrability and avoiding difficult trade-offs.63 Predictability is still present in the discussions.64 Predictability provides a justification for ‘scientific rigour’ in antitrust, with science being seen as ‘objective’ and value-free.65 The argument by Petit, mentioned in Section 2, puts more emphasis on practicality understood as solving the problem of uncertainty in the institutional context in which the decision-maker operates (eg decentralized court system and private enforcement in the USA, as opposed to more centralized, administrative system in Europe, with much less private enforcement).66

The OECD, in turn, has used five criteria to assess various antitrust standards: (i) predictability; (ii) social welfare enhancing; (iii) ease of administrability; (iv) political sustainability; (v) minimizing the risk of errors.67 They concern both more abstract benchmarking (eg social welfare enhancing), which is of more interest from the point of view of intelligent design, and more practical issues that might be of much interest to individual decision-makers (eg administrability).

Making a list of relevant factors involves much discretion, but given the overview above, this article suggests the following factors as possibly of interest: (i) retrospective consistency; (ii) simplicity and administrability; (iii) predictability; (iv) prospective consistency. They focus on the practical dimension of decision-making (as opposed to normative and ‘philosophical’ considerations), and can be explained in the following way.

Retrospective consistency

The decision-maker can be expected to prefer sticking with what has been already said, and thus rendering a decision based on a rule that fits earlier case law. This is because in such a case: (i) no explanation is needed for taking a different decision; (ii) old reasoning can be replicated; (iii) the likelihood of annulment is smaller. Retrospective consistency contributes to slow, incremental changes in enforcement.

Simplicity and administrability

The decision-maker can be expected to have a preference towards making a decision based on a rule which is simple and administrable. This is because: (i) a simple rule means a simple explanation to outside actors and (ii) a simple and administrable rule means less effort and requires less resources (eg time, money, and information).

Predictability

The decision-maker can be expected to prefer making a decision based on a rule which can be explained to external actors in a sufficiently clear way, that is one that offers predictability. This is because: (i) predictability shows that the decision was not arbitrary and is thus easier to defend and (ii) predictability allows external actors to adjust their future behaviour thus possibly preventing new cases from appearing.

Prospective consistency

The decision-maker can be expected to prefer making a decision based on a rule which can reasonably be anticipated not to cause problems with future cases.68 Doing so reduces the costs of future decision-making. At the same time, prospective consistency might be less concerning for the decision-maker than retrospective consistency: the former is a deferred future problem and the latter is more immediate. To conclude, while retrospective consistency is about ensuring that a new decision fits what has already been said in case law, prospective consistency is about ensuring that a new decision will not affect future decisional practice in a negative way.

To be sure, it is possible to have an enforcer or judge with a preference for complex analysis or a need for extravagant reasoning and for breaking away from old cases, and thus ‘making history’ (eg a politically motivated enforcer, or a newly appointed judge who follows a different philosophy than older colleagues, like judges Bork and Easterbrook). Indeed, the Chicago approach in the 1970s can be seen as going against retrospective consistency, albeit one should note that the Chicago School made sure to provide decision-makers with a feeling that the past is not lost (the re-discovery of the true original legislative intent by Bork).69 Still, looking at long-term processes and large numbers, there seems to be no reason for decision-makers to discard those factors; their presence makes the life of a decision-maker easier, bringing more utility.

In this context, the next subsection looks into how decision-makers may end up expanding the scope of enforcement by incremental changes that do not instantly tear apart the old order, but may ultimately lead to a far different place than the starting point.

Moving elements

The language of both US and EU antitrust law is notoriously open-textured, creating room for evolutionary movements initiated by decision-makers.70 This subsection identifies five areas in which decision-makers have a large enough margin of appreciation to address non-economic interests and thus start a process of change, possibly without ever dropping (at least not explicitly) the consumer welfare standard (and thus satisfying the need to ensure retrospective consistency, mentioned earlier as the first factor that they may feel is important to observe). To avoid a back-and-forth between various non-efficiency interests, further discussion uses free speech as an example. Free speech in antitrust was one of the early concerns of the Neobrandeisians, which so far has not led to any spectacular policy changes or enforcement developments—this makes it more interesting to investigate.71

Priority-setting

Decision-makers have much leeway in defining their priorities.72 Merely focusing on a certain social issue, for example free speech, does not create much risk of violating any of the factors mentioned earlier. Even sticking to a very narrow idea of the consumer welfare standard, enforcers may simply start expressing interest in certain sectors. Still, new non-standard cases sooner or later invite new theories of harm.

Quality

Decision-makers cannot be expected to easily incorporate a non-efficiency interest into antitrust analysis by political fiat.73 This would violate the need for retrospective consistency. One can see that in European merger control. In the Polish national-level Orlen/Polska Press merger, the authority was asked (by third parties) to block a merger due to free speech concerns.74 The authority refused, and the court concurred with the authority upon appeal: free speech is not antitrust. However, if one argues that free speech and media pluralism are part of product ‘quality’ and thus consumer welfare, there is more room for change.75 This is not without controversy but creates an entry point at the level of substantive law.76

Uncertainty

Quality causes much controversy, as it is difficult to assess.77 This leads back to the issue of dealing with uncertainty in antitrust as one of the possible factors that, under arguments made by other authors, affect the final shape of antitrust.78 Decision-makers may relatively easily move around between two extremes: exact quantification and probability.79 This is possible without cutting all ties with the general idea of following the consumer welfare standard, thus ensuring more retrospective consistency.80 Since probability-based judgments typically need to rely on proxies and presumptions, they may also contribute to simplicity and administrability, even if quality is difficult to measure; in practice, decision-makers often rely on heuristic arguments in relation to quality.81

Risk

An issue connected with uncertainty is attitude towards risk. Risk–attitude depicts how an actor tends to react to uncertainty. The comments about uncertainty above can be taken as a decision made by a risk-neutral actor. Yet, decision-makers may also be risk-averse (less likely to accept high uncertainty) or risk-loving actors (more likely to accept uncertain results). Attitude towards risk is a highly subjective issue, yet its impact on the perception of workability might be high. What seems ‘unworkable’ to a risk-averse enforcer might seem perfectly ‘workable’ to another enforcer. To a Chicagoan, structuralism is illogical and inconsistent, and thus unworkable: this is mostly because the Chicagoan believes that the risk of actual competition restriction is low, while the risk of competition chilling is high. For a structuralist, it is the other way around. The 1945 Associated Press case, provides another example.82 The case concerned an anti-competitive agreement among newspapers. The issue was whether the press industry, which plays a special role from the point of view of free speech, should be treated like other markets.83 As pointed out by one of justices, since the role of free speech is special, this market should not be assessed the same way as ‘peanuts and potatoes’.84 In other words, the attitude here was risk-averse. In a world of perfect knowledge, there is a ‘right’ answer to this question. Yet, decision-makers who actually develop their idea of workability do not have perfect knowledge. Attitude towards risk may further contribute to establishing presumptions and simple rules of assessment (including heuristic ones), thus enhancing simplicity and administrability, and further predictability.

Time-preference

Time preference is about choosing immediate or deferred results. The problem of innovation is a good example of time-preference issues.85 Compulsory licencing may lead to more consumer welfare today; however, it may weaken incentives to innovate and thus lower consumer welfare in the future. Furthermore, the more we speak about the future, the more probabilistic must be reasoning, since the future is unknown. There is also a ‘justice’ element in this regard that goes beyond economics since the group of actual consumers who enjoy some welfare today might be a different group than in the future. As there is no clear legislative prescription on how decision-makers should approach the issue of time, the assessment of workability becomes more dependent on the subjective judgments made by decision-makers.86

Subjectivity

The previous two subsections discussed what workability might mean for decision-makers, and how they may start paying attention to non-efficiency interests, even if they do not ever drop their commitment to the consumer welfare standard explicitly. How is it then that non-efficiency interests have not been taken into account on a large scale in the past few decades? Is it that at the end of the day workability needs to work towards the Chicago ideal and away from a broader conception of antitrust?

One hypothesis might be that the evolutionary perspective outlined in the subsection ‘Depths: the invisible hand of antitrust enforcement’ is inherently wrong—there was simply no ‘intelligent designer’ who would impose a design favourable to broad antitrust enforcement. However, this might be a too hasty conclusion, since we also saw that decision-makers may have both their own incentives to act and means to alter the shape of antitrust. Another hypothesis might be that non-efficiency interests ultimately fail with regard to prospective consistency, which was covered in the subsection ‘Parameters’, but was the only factor not present in the subsection ‘Moving elements’. Decision-makers may anticipate that even if they, for example take the ‘quality route’, it will be a slippery-slope towards lack of prospective consistency, since even if they create simple and administrable rules to address the problem of assessing quality, sooner or later the whole system will become unworkable.87 However, one could argue the same in relation to purely economic antitrust: economic analysis invites in a further step economic quantification, and once quantification starts, it might become a slippery-slope towards ‘economic extravaganza’ that ultimately makes antitrust unworkable—Jonathan Kanter’s ‘central-planning standard’. In a way, every antitrust project carries the seeds of its own destruction.

A yet different explanation might be that workability itself is affected by subjectivity: indeed, if we look through the factors mentioned above, they involve subjectivity, which cannot be easily avoided.88 The next section looks therefore at possible sources shaping this subjectivity.

4. THE SWAY OF OPINION

Sections 2–3 outlined first the reasons and then areas which may cause antitrust to adapt in a more evolutionary way, rather than by intelligent design decreed top-down. As it was discussed, such an evolutionary perspective on the applicable antitrust standard of assessment can be seen as a distant relative of invisible hand explanations known from legal and political theory. However, as it was shown in the previous section, the perception of workability involves a degree of subjectivity. The discussion below further explores this issue, mapping out possible sources of this subjectivity and means of changing it.

Society: intellectual climate of opinion

On the common sense level, one could argue that each epoch is driven by its own climate of opinion that people tend to share and take as something that is simply ‘known’. The climate of opinion can potentially influence how people perceive the world; a change in the climate of opinion may thus also change the perception of antitrust. In that sense, the climate of opinion impacts also the scope of Overton’s Window, and thus options available to decision-makers with regard to factors discussed in the subsection ‘Moving elements’.89

The belief that there is a phenomenon that people living in a specific time period are driven by a certain truth is so strong that it gained its own name: the zeitgeist.90 While Bork once claimed that antitrust is a microcosm in which larger movements of the society are reflected, one could say that the intellectual climate of opinion would be the macrocosm influencing antitrust.91 Cardozo called this eloquently ‘the total push and pressure of the cosmos’ that decision-makers cannot escape and which ‘determine where choice shall fall’.92

Generally, if one looks through literature, and authors from diverse fields, writing in different time periods, there seems to be a common theme when it comes to the climate of opinion and how it changes.93 First, economic conditions affect people’s philosophical attitudes and people’s attitudes affect economic conditions.94 Secondly, since those changes require time, a swing in the climate of opinion may require a period longer than a generation, with younger generations and non-conforming outsiders attacking old dogmas, only to establish a new consensus which becomes attacked when its intellectual rigour deteriorates.95 Dicey’s perspective is noteworthy in that regard because there is a connection between his views and the Chicago School, and thus indirectly also antitrust—this is because Dicey had a profound impact on Milton Friedman.96 Dicey, an English legal theorist, speculated on how the public opinion influences legislation; he observed that: ‘A change of belief arises, in the main, from the occurrence of circumstances which incline the majority of the world to hear with favour theories which, at one time, men of common sense derided as absurdities, or distrusted as paradoxes’.97 The lesson that Chicago seemingly drew from Dicey was that the key to success is persistence in a long process of large opinion shifts.98

One may also look at the climate of opinion in a narrower perspective, that is through the lens of antitrust scholarship. Andriychuk, for example, argues that the momentum for the intellectual dominance of every antitrust doctrine eventually disappears, which leads to the emergence of a new one.99 This can be seen as part of a perpetual dialectical movement.100 Likewise, when it comes to shifts in the general climate of opinion in the context of generational changes, some Neobrandeisians appear to be supportive of an argument that part of the reason for the Chicagoan drift in antitrust policy was rooted in demography.101

The point about long-cycles and demography has much appeal: a person raised during the Great Depression and one raised during the post-war economic boom can be expected to have vastly different experience of markets. This can be compared to Max Planck’s observation that: ‘a new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing its opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it’, commonly known as: ‘science progresses one funeral at a time’.102 Planck’s observation is formalized by Kuhn.103 Like Dicey, Kuhn seems to had impact on Friedman.104 Generally, Kuhn’s argument is that a scientific community (in his case, physicists) continuously goes through two periods of activity: ‘normal science’ and paradigm shifts, with a crisis taking place in between.105 During the periods of normal science, individuals operate and think in accordance with a set of rules defined by a paradigm.106 During the periods of paradigm shifts, the entire world seems to change.107 Kuhn highlights that a strong force in accepting new paradigms are generational changes in the scientific community, as its new members are often less committed to older paradigms.108

Overall, if one applies the perspective outlined above to the current times, it is noticeable that the current antitrust debate takes place in the context of a possibly new climate of opinion that might be emerging due to a generational change and developments in the world outside antitrust. This includes large structural changes following the 2008 financial crisis, the 2010s being further marked with the growth of Big Tech (and thus disruption of old power structures), and the 2020s being a highly visible beginning of strong geopolitical tensions.109 For such a process to fully affect the subjectivity of decision-makers may require time; however, it can be taken as at least partial explanation of the current state of the debate and possibly also an indication of its further trajectory.

Antitrust community: cultural capture

The second layer of exerting influence over decision-makers’ subjectivity may go beyond the society as such. It can be associated with the concept of cultural capture. Generally, regulatory capture theories rose to prominence in the 1970s.110 In turn, the theory of cultural capture has been formulated in relation to financial regulators.111 More recently, the theory has been discussed in the context of antitrust.112

In antitrust, the argument is that in the process of representing their clients, private practitioners may—intentionally or unconsciously—adopt the views of their clients, which may then further be acquired by decision-makers.113 This process can be further strengthened by what some authors call the ‘epistemic capture’ and ‘academic capture’, ie unproportionate exposure of experts to arguments and information coming from a specific interest group.114

It is admitted that this kind of capture is difficult to detect and there is no ‘smoking gun’ indicating that cultural capture takes place.115 Also, the proponents of these arguments acknowledge that many of such interactions are natural and impossible to remove.116 Furthermore, assuming that cultural capture between undertakings and decision-makers is possible, one could also assume that the same type of capture could take place between, for example, the academia and decision-makers. While arguments are made today that business makes efforts to influence the academia, in the 1940s, and still at the time when the Chicago School was popularizing its worldview, there was a common argument that ‘intellectuals’ have strong impact on policy-making and that they tend to drift towards more market regulation.117

For the purpose of this article, however, what is more relevant is that it can be reasonably assumed that decision-makers do not operate in a vacuum and that their subjectivity can be influenced by outside actors. Factors such as group identification or overexposure to certain arguments may over time impact the attitude of decision-makers to those elements of ‘antitrust machinery’ that they can move without directly going against recent precedents, yet still in a direction that slowly changes the shape of antitrust enforcement. The theory of cultural capture contributes to explaining adaptive changes in antitrust.118

Individual impact: never let a good story go to waste

While the two previous subsections dealt with large-scale processes, this subsection will explore a more micro-level way in which preferences with regard to factors mentioned in the subsection ‘Moving elements’ may come into being. This micro-level process is storytelling.

It is argued that storytelling might have developed by providing a fitness benefit to individuals or groups.119 That humans crave good stories is recognized in legal research within the Law and Literature movement, with White arguing, for example, that: ‘the fundamental characteristic of human life is that we all tell stories, all the time, about ourselves and others, both in the law and out of it’.120 From this angle, law becomes a cultural practice also at the linguistic level. Storytelling may include the use of metaphors, whose role was subject to discussion in both philosophy of science and legal research.121 It is argued that on the cognitive level, metaphors have a strong impact on how humans perceive reality.122

A good example of how an interesting story impacts the perception of law comes from the area of free speech, which in the subsection ‘Moving elements’ served as a point of reference for workability. Free speech is often explained by the metaphor of the ‘marketplace of ideas’, associated with (but not explicitly mentioned by) Justice Holmes’s opinion in Abrams.123 While free speech can be justified in many ways, the market parallel proved to be highly captivating and thus having an impact on the perception of free speech.124 It is subject to serious analysis in free speech scholarship how various metaphors influence the development of case law.125

Antitrust is not much different. Earlier in the subsection ‘Moving elements’, this was present in the narrative concerning the proper approach to analysing free speech in antitrust cases: free speech is not ‘peanuts and potatoes’. Indeed, it is not—and this narrative is possibly more captivating than any abstract argument.126 A broader review of such metaphors was conducted by Boudin, who observed: ‘metaphor … is often a kind of “invisible hand” that guides events from afar without detection’ and that ‘after case citations and market share figures have faded from memory, the judge or lawyer who has read an antitrust opinion is likely to remember, if anything, a metaphor’.127

In EU antitrust law, the room for telling powerful worldview-changing stories is more limited. The Court of Justice of the European Union (CJEU), in particular in antitrust, typically delivers rather succinct grounds for its rulings.128 Yet, the EU system also relies on the opinions of Advocates-General. Here, one can indeed identify opinions which might significantly change decision-makers’ perception on issues where the margin for subjectivity is larger.

Advocate-General Kokott’s opinion in T-Mobile is a good example of that.129 Generally, the Chicago perspective provided a narrative that prohibition of business conduct with unclear effects is a great evil in antitrust; in the post-Chicago enforcement, this story further led to the adoption of an approach that puts much emphasis on the quantification of harm.130 In T-Mobile, Advocate-General Kokott was asked for an opinion on ‘by object’ restrictions. Rather than focus on purely abstract discussion, she made a simple yet impactful parallel: legal systems commonly use straightforward rules that deal with risk. Thus, for example, drunk-driving is prohibited, irrespective of consequences. Indeed, law introduces much inefficiency. Traffic rules are supposed to promote safe but speedy travel, yet one rarely finds it justified to cross the street when the light is red, even if there is no traffic. The idea of people standing and looking at the red light when the road is clearly empty is inefficiency writ large.131 Looked at from this perspective, the story about uncertainty and risk in antitrust is a much different story than that of chilling competition.132

Such storytelling may also take place outside case law, for example, as a political slogan, in court letters, or legal writing. Joanathan Kanter’s reference to the consumer welfare standard as the ‘central-planning standard’ may serve as an example, radically changing the possible perception of the idea of quantification in antitrust.133 The phrase ‘protecting competition, not competitors’ became an antitrust cliché, even despite the fact that its original meaning might have been more ambiguous than is often assumed (as if in some cases protecting competitors could not serve as a means of protecting competition).134 Google introduced the ‘competition is one click away’ slogan.135 Margrethe Vestager became known for emphasizing ‘fairness’ in her communication—and was criticized for doing so and introducing ‘romance’ into antitrust.136 Arguing for a ‘competitive process standard’, Wu relies on a metaphor of market competition as football, and decision-makers as referees overseeing the process, not the outcome, and thus ‘fan welfare’.137 Stucke and Ezrachi, in turn, discuss how undertakings hijacked competition language to promote their own interests and influence decision-makers.138 Waller, on the other hand, emphasizes the importance of pop culture narratives in shaping the perception of antitrust enforcement.139 This variant of influence is likely closest to the usual, not merely academic, meaning of ‘making memes’.

As in other parts of this article, it should be stressed that the point here is not whether this way of making arguments is objectively correct or not. One could argue that in every powerful story there is much room for heuristics, which itself can be criticized.140 Yet, the point here is not about right or wrong, but how changes in antitrust actually happen.

5. ANTITRUST IS A STRANGE LOOP

Is antitrust memetic?

This article started with two views on the origin of changes in antitrust: intelligent design and a more evolutionary perspective. The former attaches much weight to ideological considerations, the latter wants to see the shape of antitrust as a relatively ideology-free outcome, primarily based on practical considerations. It was suggested in the introduction that basic intuition suggests that the truth may lie in the middle, with the actually interesting question being the mechanics of changes in antitrust. The discussion in Sections 2–4 formalizes this basic intuition into a more comprehensive framework, in which both the role of ideological and practical considerations are accounted for. From this point of view, to believe that antitrust changed merely because of Chicago’s ideological influence oversimplifies the problem: Chicago must have offered something that was practical enough—at that time it was the focus on economic arguments. However, it would also be an error to ignore the fact that the perception of ‘practicality’ (workability) can be influenced, to some extent, by external factors. The construction here becomes a loop: external factors influence antitrust, but they are themselves influenced by socio-economic conditions, which is the output of antitrust enforcement, resulting from the practical choices of decision-makers.141

The framework that has been sketched so far is by no means complete. However, it offers a different way of looking at a number of arguments that have been made in antitrust in the past few years. To give a few examples: Wu’s simplified observations about decision-makers become more formalized and substantiated in this framework. The framework is compatible and further extends arguments by Hovenkamp and by Kovacic about the Chicago–Harvard synthesis (Chicago was instrumental to changing the paradigm by doing the work discussed in Section 4, but was less successful with the work in Section 3).142 Under this framework, cultural capture theories (Lancieri, Posner, Zingales, and Broulík) are one of the movers of changes in antitrust, yet not exclusively, highlighting the impact of tacit knowledge acquired through the climate of opinion. The framework can also be seen as supplementing Ezrachi’s metaphor of antitrust as a ‘sponge’ by providing a more dynamic view of why and how this sponge changes its shape. Finally, this framework—provisionally called ‘a theory of antitrust memetics’ in Section 2—questions more directly a different theory that was proposed earlier by Petit, that is the theory of antitrust limits. This article suggests that the ‘limits’ are less objective and less predetermined than one could see them under Petit’s theory.143 This memetic account of antitrust sits also better with the developments in the EU in the 1990s, moving the focus of evolutionary changes from the level of case law to the level of cultural changes, and from the problem of dealing with uncertainty to instead of fitting the socio-economic context.

While it is difficult to provide a full exposition of a theory in a single article, the theory of antitrust memetics seems apt for further investigation in future research.144 Taken more broadly, memetics concerns itself with the study of how ideas spread, and predicting which ideas have more chances of success.145 Memetics received some attention in complexity studies.146 Complexity as such has already caught the attention of antitrust researchers.147 Against this backdrop, an additional complexity-focused research approach could be to enhance the understanding of not just legal and economic concepts within antitrust, but of the antitrust community itself. At this time though, a shorter prescriptive discussion based on the findings of this article is appropriate.

Reformers

Since 2021, the arguments of the reformers, mostly the Neobrandeisians, have enjoyed highly favourable conditions due to personnel changes in top US antitrust institutions. This, however, neither needs to last forever, nor it guarantees success in terms of policy implementation. The framework outlined in this article invites therefore a question of what the reformers seem to do right, and what else could be done to increase their chances of success.

When the reformers started making their arguments, some commentators complained that it was not clear what different way of enforcing antitrust should follow from the reformers’ arguments.148 The main target of the Neobrandeisian critique was the consumer welfare standard. In retrospect, this strategy might have been more effective than some might have hoped for. From the point of view of the framework outlined in this article, attacking the consumer welfare standard corresponds to the measures that are taken to affect the subjectivity. Had the consumer welfare standard been overturned, antitrust would have changed. Still, even if this had not succeeded, the discussion around the consumer welfare standard could change the status quo.149 Within the framework presented in this article, the reformers did lay solid foundations for successfully shaping the subjectivity of decision-makers.

However, what still seems to be lacking are proposals of practical implementation. The reformers may hope for ‘things to unfold themselves organically’ after the decision-makers acquire a different ‘taste’ for solving cases (ie that they would come up with ‘some’ approach by merely interacting between themselves within the logic of the process outlined in Section 3). Still, practitioners look for practicality—and the less they are concerned with ideological issues, the more they can be concerned with just having an approach that allows them to keep the system running without too many headaches. This might also serve as a warning for every group of reformers: one may be successful, like Chicago, with shaking the old paradigm to then see the new paradigm being built around something else than advocated by those who became known as the architects of change. When it comes to practical implementations, the European example seems to provide, at this point, better results such as, for example, a slow correction of the abuse of dominance case law so that it provides room for ‘competition on the merits’ arguments, and not merely a narrow effects-based approach.150

Sceptics

Some sceptics have observed that even today, antitrust cases are argued in terms of consumer harms.151 Yet, this seems to miss the point: if one recognizes (as it was done in the subsection ‘Beneath the surface: the antitrust standards paradox’) that the consumer welfare standard is a flexible concept, one may very well still apply the consumer welfare standard, while the trajectory of changes might already be different.152 A more realistic assessment seems to be that the antitrust debate has developed not necessarily to the sceptics’ advantage—claims that were once unthinkable and marginalized are now subject to serious debate. This is not the outcome that the sceptics might have hoped for before 2020.

From the point of view of the sceptics, the discussion provided in this article—primarily in relation to the role of subjectivity—might serve as an encouragement to revisit arguments about the causes of social changes, both in scientific research and politics. Kuhn’s argument, referred to earlier, provides a comprehensive account of how changes in such a seemingly ‘objectivity-driven’ communities as that of natural sciences involve much subjectivity, cognitive biases, and how paradigms rise and fall.153 Dicey’s and Cardozo’s arguments might supplement this from the point of view of political and legal theory, with Dicey having impact on Friedman, and thus indirectly on the success of Chicago. The ‘memetic’ part of the argument presented above might also be useful: when a paradigm loses its strength, competition between ideas starts anew—the memetic theory, in turn, investigates what makes ideas more attractive.154 The discussion provided in this article highlights also that the sceptics should not feel overconfident about ‘practicality’ always working towards their advantage.

Silent majority?

Aside from the reformers and sceptics, there are also those who can be called ‘neutrals’, such as academic researchers who do not believe there are any strong objective indicators of an optimal shape of antitrust, indifferent practitioners who treat antitrust merely as a tool to be mastered, and career government officials whose main responsibility is to effectively carry out government policies.

From the point of view of this group, the argument discussed in this article can be taken as redirecting the focus from ‘who is right?’ towards looking at antitrust as a complex process of change. From this angle, the question becomes how to manage this process effectively. For example, taking into account the continuous nature of the process outlined in this article, a useful approach could be to develop enforcement strategies that would make ongoing adaptation to changing circumstances easier.155 Another example might be that one of the side-effects of deconstructing a paradigm is less consensus within a community—in antitrust, this can be associated with the polarization of the current debate. This, in turn, affects the legitimacy of antitrust enforcement: until a new paradigm forms, there is a greater chance that there will always be one large social group strongly dissatisfied with how antitrust is enforced (ie either the reformers being dissatisfied with antitrust not changing, or the sceptics dissatisfied with antitrust being changed).

A possible role for a neutral in this context might be that of a ‘translator’. Kuhn, for example, notes that when a paradigm falls, a scientific community effectively starts to behave as two different language groups.156 In this context, he argues that translating one theory into the language of another theory (and the other way around) stimulates reaching a new scientific consensus.157 To put it in antitrust perspective, the exercise which was suggested in Section 3 shows an example of translating a non-economic value (free speech) into the consumer welfare standard paradigm (free speech as quality).158 One should be realistic here though: such a simple exercise is not a cure to all problems—differences will remain. Yet, it is a starting point for consensus-building and mending a schism.

Another area of interest for the neutrals might be antitrust institutions (agencies, courts). The reasoning here might be the following: (i) antitrust involves subjectivity, which however remains largely similar when a paradigm emerges; (ii) however, when a paradigm weakens, there is more disunity and in consequence, legitimacy suffers; (iii) to better navigate this difficult period, antitrust institutions need to be responsive to those developments. Responsiveness does not necessarily mean that antitrust needs to change specifically the way it is argued by the proponents of a new approach. Conversely, as mentioned earlier, such responsiveness might include the role of a translator and facilitator of a new consensus. Against this backdrop, one could question whether it is an optimal arrangement to allocate policy decisions to courts. Courts hear cases deciding on issues that are formally presented as legal arguments, without much room to manoeuvre on what issues and when they are going to comment on. Furthermore, courts hear specific cases—reviewing broad ranges of issues or examples within the framework of a single case is unrealistic. Other issues have been covered, at least in the USA, within the discussion about the Chevron doctrine.159 While the Chevron doctrine originates from the USA, the tension that underlies it (the role of courts versus agencies) remains relevant also from the European point of view.160 The Chevron doctrine is now supported by the reformers, making it a more difficult area to discuss by those who wish to remain neutral.161 Still, from a European perspective, which is less concerned with internal political divisions in the USA, what might be of interest in the Chevron-related debate is further research into how administrative agencies might better handle changes in antitrust—this includes: strengthening the legitimacy of independent technocratic agencies, designing participatory mechanisms, and ensuring good governance.162

6. CONCLUSION

This article explored a different way of looking at antitrust than is usually the case. It started with two perspectives: intelligent design and a more evolutionary approach, which in political theory is associated with invisible-hand explanations. In antitrust, such an invisible-hand explanation would mean that much of how antitrust looks comes from bottom-level practical considerations aimed at making its enforcement workable. This would also mean that attempts to change antitrust by political will alone would encounter a serious obstacle. The aim of the article was thus to provide a better description of how changes in antitrust take place by looking closer at this hypothesis.

The discussion above offers a more nuanced account of what might be driving changes in antitrust. This more nuanced explanation has been provisionally called a ‘memetic’ view on antitrust. As argued in this article, a more bottom-up, evolutionary outlook of antitrust enforcement should not be completely dismissed. There are compelling reasons—rooted both in common sense and legal realism—to believe that decision-makers may be motivated by different considerations than those of any ‘designer’ of a perfect antitrust system. Having a margin of appreciation in both deciding cases and defining practical rules of adjudication, they may alter the shape of antitrust from the bottom-up to an appreciable extent. However, this article also provided a more critical account of how the subjectivity of decision-makers might be shaped by external factors. This, in turn, means that the movement of antitrust under the more evolutionary, practicality-oriented, perspective should not be taken as pre-determined and always leading to the same result, for example a narrow Chicago-style enforcement. This point should be relevant to the antitrust reformers, sceptics, and also those more neutral in the current antitrust debate; however, each group may find it important for different reasons, as outlined earlier.

More generally, what may ultimately follow from the exercise conducted in this article is that given that there is always room for evolutionary changes in antitrust resulting from decentralized actions taken by decision-makers, one may have far less agency over the final product than one could wish. And as ‘time has upset many fighting faiths’, the main conclusion from this discussion might be that antitrust will keep changing and probably no antitrust project will last forever.163 Antitrust passions do not fade; they are driven by ever-changing antitrust memes.

Footnotes

1

While the origins of this observation are unclear, it is often attributed to Victor Hugo.

2

See eg Lina Khan, ‘Amazon’s Antitrust Paradox’ (2017) 126 Yale LJ 710; Tim Wu, ‘After Consumer Welfare, Now What? The “Protection of Competition” Standard in Practice’ (2018) Competition Policy Intl 1; Marshall Steinbaum and Maurice Stucke, ‘The Effective Competition Standard: A New Standard for Antitrust’ (2019) 86 U Chicago L Rev 595; Sandeep Vaheesan, ‘The Profound Nonsense of Consumer Welfare Antitrust’ (2019) 64 The Antitrust Bulletin 1; Sanjukta Paul, ‘Recovering the Moral Economy Foundations of the Sherman Act’ (2021) 131 Yale LJ 175.

3

For ‘misguided’ see: Joseph Biden, ‘Remarks by President Biden at Signing of An Executive Order Promoting Competition in the American Economy’ (9 July 2021) <https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefing-room/speeches-remarks/2021/07/09/remarks-by-president-biden-at-signing-of-an-executive-order-promoting-competition-in-the-american-economy> accessed 7 September 2024. For more orthodox ‘pressing issues’, see generally references in (n 2). For ‘pressing issues’ beyond orthodox antitrust topics, see eg Kati Cseres, ‘Feminist Competition Law’ (2024) Amsterdam Law School Research Paper No 2023-43 <http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.4682906> accessed 7 September 2024; Bennett Capers and Gregory Day, ‘Race-ing Antitrust’ (2023) 121 Michigan L Rev 523. See also further (n 4).

4

On sustainability, see eg Anna Gerbrandy, ‘Solving a Sustainability-Deficit in European Competition Law’ (2017) 40 World Competition 539; Giorgio Monti and Jotte Mulder, ‘Escaping the Clutches of EU Competition Law: Pathways to Assess Private Sustainability Initiatives’ (2017) 42 Eur L Rev 635; Oles Andriychuk, ‘The Concept of Sustainability in EU Competition Law: A Legal Realist Perspective’ (2021) 14 YB Antitrust and Regulatory Studies 11. On labour, see eg Sanjukta Paul, ‘The Enduring Ambiguities of Antitrust Liability for Worker Collective Action’ (2016) 47 Loyola U Chicago LJ 969. On media pluralism and free speech, see eg Maurice Stucke and Allen Grunes, ‘Antitrust and the Marketplace of Ideas’ (2001) 69 Antitrust LJ 249; Gregory Day, ‘Monopolizing Free Speech’ (2020) 88 Fordham L Rev 1315; Jan Polański, ‘The Marketplace of Ideas and EU Competition Law: Can Antitrust Be Used to Protect the Freedom of Speech?’ (2022) YSEC YB Socio-Economic Constitutions. On privacy, see eg Christophe Carugati, ‘The antitrust privacy dilemma’ (2023) 19 Eur Competition J 167. See also: Ioannis Lianos, ‘Polycentric Competition Law’ (2018) 71 Current L Problems 161.

5

For ‘moral sentiments’, see Section 2.

6

For crisis narratives, see eg Daniel Crane, ‘The New Crisis in Antitrust (?)’ (2020) 83 Antitrust LJ 253.

7

Rana Foroohar, ‘The Great US-Europe Antitrust Divide’ (Financial Times, 5 February 2024) <https://www.ft.com/content/065a2f93-dc1e-410c-ba9d-73c930cedc14> accessed 25 January 2025. See also: Matt Stoller, ‘Europe’s antitrust record is a matter of embarrassment, not pride’ (Financial Times, 15 February 2024) <https://www.ft.com/content/e5837a46-6f8d-4e3f-9dda-d212a4ec1372> accessed 25 January 2025; Olivier Guersent, ‘Europe has an unrivalled record on antitrust’ (Financial Times, 7 February 2024) <https://www.ft.com/content/80ae2bed-1471-4082-aefd-8cb5b7343495> accessed 25 January 2025.

8

See eg Paul (n 2); Vaheesan (n 2).

9

See eg Rutger Claassen and Anna Gerbrandy, ‘Doing Good Together: Competition Law and the Political Legitimacy of Interfirm Cooperation’ (2018) 28 Business Ethics Q 401 (arguing that corporations have democratic accountability and that antitrust can accommodate changing democratic expectations).

10

See (n 2). See also: Cseres (n 3) 18–22 (gender); José van Dijck and others, ‘Reframing Platform Power’ (2019) 8 Internet Policy Rev 1 (citizen wellbeing). More broadly, see: OECD, ‘Consumer Welfare Standard: Advantages and Disadvantages Compared to Alternative Standards’ (2023) OECD Competition Policy Roundtable Background Note <https://one.oecd.org/document/DAF/COMP(2023)4/en/pdf> accessed 25 January 2025.

11

See eg Vaheesan (n 2) 6 (‘Bork substituted his personal ideology for the vision of the drafters of the antitrust laws’); Lina Khan, ‘The Ideological Roots of America’s Market Power Problem’ (2018) 127 The Yale LJ Forum 960.

12

With antitrust operating ‘as if the sky was the limit’, see: Nicolas Petit, ‘A Theory of Antitrust Limits’ (2021) 28 George Mason L Rev 1399, 1400.

13

See, primarily Petit (n 12). However, see also, eg William Kovacic, ‘The Chicago Obsession in the Interpretation of US Antitrust History’ (2020) 87 U Chicago LR 459 (arguing against portraying antitrust as merely shaped by Chicago ideology); Herbert Hovenkamp, ‘Whatever Did Happen to the Antitrust Movement?’ (2019) 94 Notre Dame L Rev 583 (arguing that antitrust changed in a long process of maturing as a discipline).

14

It is difficult to classify various voices in the current antitrust debate. This article uses ‘reformers’ and ‘sceptics’ as approximations. ‘Reformers’ denote the Neobrandeisians and other advocates who argue for more far-going changes in antitrust (eg more emphasis on non-economic values). ‘Sceptics’ denote those who are less enthusiastic about such broad reforms, although not necessarily against all types of reforms.

15

Robert Bork, ‘Legislative Intent and the Policy of the Sherman Act’ (1966) 9 J Law and Economics 7.

16

Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War With Itself (Bork Publishing 2021) 89.

17

Bork, ibid 446 (‘non-economic goals are the proper subjects of other laws’).

18

Aside from the Wealth of Nations, Adam Smith also authored The Theory of Moral Sentiments. On antitrust and moral content, see eg Herbert Hovenkamp, ‘Antitrust Violations in Securities Markets’ (2003) 28 J Corporation L 607, 609 (‘antitrust has no moral content’); Herbert Hovenkamp, ‘Antitrust and Innovation: Where We Are and Where We Should Be Going’ (2011) 77 Antitrust LJ 749, 750 (‘Neither antitrust nor intellectual property law has any moral content’). For both moral content and direct references to moral sentiments in antitrust, see: Thibault Schrepel, ‘Antitrust Without Romance’ (2020) 13 New York UJL & Liberty 326, 327 (‘the effectiveness of antitrust authorities should be enhanced by applying reason to antitrust law rather than fears, feelings, or sentiments’); 418 (‘several aspects of antitrust law are particularly susceptible to corruption by moral concepts. Closing the door to such a possibility requires a refocusing of antitrust law on the use of scientific, quantifiable and amoral concepts’); 426 (‘antitrust law is an instrument for protecting trade, commerce, and free competition. It facilitates exchanges without cherry picking which ones should be legal based on moral sentiments’).

19

Anne Witt, The More Economic Approach to EU Antitrust Law (Hart Publishing 2019); Anne Witt, ‘Technocrats, Populists, Hipsters, and Romantics—Who Else Is Lurking in the Corners of the Bar?’ (2019) 2 Antitrust Chronicle 1, 3.

20

See n 2.

21

Thus, eg it is argued that it has a role in ensuring citizen welfare, supporting democracy, and other interests, see generally n 3 and n 10.

22

eg be more responsive to labour issues.

23

See n 10.

24

See also Filippo Lancieri and others, ‘The Political Economy of the Decline of Antitrust Enforcement in the United States’ (2023) 85 Antitrust LJ 441, 443 (using a similar term: ‘enlightened technocratic narrative’, albeit in a somewhat different context, see the subsection ‘Antitrust community: cultural capture’).

25

President Biden’s remarks during the signing of the executive order were not his first encounter with Bork. In the 1980s, Biden, then a senator, took part in Bork’s (failed) confirmation procedure to the US Supreme Court.

26

See eg Barak Orbach, ‘The Antitrust Consumer Welfare Paradox’ (2011) 7 J Competition Law & Economics 133; Steven Salop, ‘Question: What Is the Real and Proper Antitrust Welfare Standard? Answer: The True Consumer Welfare Standard’ (2010) 22 Loyola Consumer LR 336.

27

Jonathan Kanter, ‘Remarks at New York City Bar Association’s Milton Handler Lecture’ (18 May 2022) <https://www.justice.gov/opa/speech/assistant-attorney-general-jonathan-kanter-delivers-remarks-new-york-city-bar-association> accessed 25 January 2025.

28

Cristina Caffarra, ‘“Consumer Welfare Is Dead”: What Do We Do Instead? – A Perspective from Europe’ (ProMarket, 27 April 2023) <https://www.promarket.org/2023/04/27/consumer-welfare-is-dead-what-do-we-do-instead-a-perspective-from-europe> accessed 25 January 2025.

29

Bork (n 16) 118, 125, 129 (on ‘economic extravaganza’ and direct measurement). For similar views, see Frank Easterbrook, ‘Workable Antitrust Policy’ (1986) 84 Michigan L Rev 1696, 1701, 1711 (scepticism about economic models and measurement).

30

William Kovacic, ‘The Intellectual DNA of Modern U.S. Competition Law for Dominant Firm Conduct: The Chicago/Harvard Double Helix’ (2007) Columbia Business L Rev 1.

31

Orbach (n 26) 136.

32

Kanter (n 27).

33

For proponents, see eg Petit (n 12) 1403. For other arguments see also: Orbach (n 26); Maurice Stucke, ‘Reconsidering Antitrust’s Goals’ (2012) 53 Boston College L Rev 551, 577 (‘no consensus on what the term actually means or who the consumers are’); Eleanor Fox, ‘“Consumer Welfare” and the Real Battle for the Soul of Antitrust’ (ProMarket, 19 April 2023) <https://www.promarket.org/2023/04/19/consumer-welfare-and-the-real-battle-for-the-soul-of-antitrust> accessed 25 January 2025 (‘there is no such thing as THE consumer welfare standard’); Oles Andriychuk, ‘Dialectical Antitrust: An Alternative Insight into the Methodology of the EC Competition Law Analysis’ (2010) 31 Eur Competition L Rev 155, 160 (‘consumer welfare test is essentially an amorphous concept’).

34

For ‘antitrust limits’, see the next subsection.

35

OECD (n 10).

36

ibid, paras 18–26.

37

See Wu (n 2).

38

See eg OECD (n 10) paras 24, 58, 138; Petit (n 12), discussing probabilistic approach; Jan Polański, ‘A Positive Program for Antitrust? Enforcement in Times of Political Tides’ (2022) 45 World Competition 237, 255 (pointing out that general rules are not incompatible with the more economic approach).

39

This is a conclusion of one of the agencies that took part in the OECD roundtable, see: OECD, ‘Advantages and Disadvantages of Competition Welfare Standards—Note by Poland’ (2023) DAF/COMP/WD(2023)34 <https://one.oecd.org/document/DAF/COMP/WD(2023)34/en/pdf> accessed 25 January 2025, para 12.

40

Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (University of Chicago Press 2012) 170–71.

41

Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Basic Books 2013) 18–22; Edna Ullmann-Margalit, ‘Invisible-Hand Explanations’ (1978) 39 Synthese 263; Robert Nozick, ‘Invisible-Hand Explanations’ (1994) 84 American Economic R 314; Adrian Vermeule, ‘The Invisible Hand in Legal and Political Theory’ (2010) 96 Virginia LR 1417, 1418–23 (‘The invisible-hand explanation substitutes for an explanation from design, based upon the intentional action of some designer(s)’). On the invisible hand, see also text to n 127.

42

Petit (n 12).

43

To avoid misrepresenting Petit’s point, his own summary of the argument is: ‘this article … proposes that (1) ideology is a lazy answer; (2) the present limits in US and EU antitrust law rest mostly on practical considerations; and (3) the question of setting better limits is ultimately empirical and context dependent. The point is that besides ideology, practicality matters. The limits of antitrust stem from practical choices made more or less consciously by institutions tasked with applying statutes designed to curb monopoly power’. Petit is somewhat vague about his account of the role of ideology: on the one hand, he contests it and does not analyse it; on the other hand, introducing his argument, he says ‘besides ideology’ which seemingly implies that ideology has some role, which however is not discussed in his argument.

44

Petit (n 12) 1419.

45

ibid 1420 (introducing the US perspective, and noting ‘incremental, slow, and uncertain process of the common law’).

46

Petit (n 12) 1452, 1460.

47

Hovenkamp (n 13) 589, 619–23, 636–37 (arguing that the consumer welfare standard was more administrable and required no difficult trade-offs). Petit (n 12) 1401 points at Herbert Hovenkamp and Fiona Scott Morton, ‘Framing the Chicago School of Antitrust Analysis’ (2020) 168 U Pennsylvania LR 1844, 1871 as arguing that the Chicago influence was essentially ideological. There seems to be no contradiction here, since in Hovenkamp (n 13) the argument is generally about antitrust, and in the article co-authored with Morton, the focus is Chicago itself.

48

Tim Wu, The Curse of Bigness: Antitrust in the New Gilded Age (Columbia Global Reports 2018) 91. See, however, Eleanor Fox, ‘Consumer Beware Chicago’ (1986) 84 Michigan L Rev 1714, 1718 (‘Both Chicago and its critics support some rules that are clear and support other rules and inquiries that are more complex’); see also Section 4 that might provide further explanation on why sometimes simple tests matter and sometimes not.

49

Wu (n 2) 6–7. Generally, Wu’s opinion about the decision-makers does not seem particularly good—elsewhere, he observes: ‘lawyers and judges are anxious people, unusually desperate for respectability. Bork and his allies offered a way to decide cases that offered the appearance of rigour and even scientific certainty’, see: Tim Wu, The Curse of Bigness: How Corporate Giants Came to Rule the World (Atlantic Books 2020) 116.

50

On this topic, see also: Schrepel (n 18), who however provides a rather grim picture of what, according to him, motivates enforcers. Note that when Schrepel speaks about antitrust officials, he means also political actors; instead, when speaking about decision-makers, this article refers primarily to career staff (technocrats) and judges. On legal realism, see Andriychuk (n 4) 21–28.

51

Frank Easterbrook, ‘Statutes’ Domains’ (1983) 50 U Chicago L Rev 533, 547.

52

At least not if one looks at this process narrowly. See the subsection ‘Is antitrust memetic?’, which reconciles the EU developments with intelligent design and invisible hand perspectives.

53

The word ‘memetics’ comes from Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (OUP 2016) 245, who speculated that ‘memes’ might be the counterpart of ‘genes’ in relation to ideas, and that practical ideas are copied in a complex process of imitation. The word ‘meme’ comes from Greek ‘mimesis’, with eg Plato criticizing mimetic (imitative) art in his Republic. See also: Susan Blackmore, The Meme Machine (OUP 2000); Daniel Dennett, From Bacteria to Bach and Back (Penguin 2018) 205–47.

54

Falsification is primarily associated with Karl Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Routledge 2002). See also: Carlo Rovelli, Anaximander and the Nature of Science (Allen Lane 2023) 114; Martijn Hesselink, ‘A European Legal Method? On European Private Law and Scientific Method’ (2009) 15 Eur LJ 20, 24–27 (discussing Popper).

55

Some of those issues are also visible in Petit (n 12) 1405, who formulates his theory of antitrust limits, tries to test it, but nonetheless needs to admit that ‘our test is thus more semantical than lexical. We look for impressionistic strokes. Subjectivity is inevitable’.

56

Kuhn (n 40) 143–46, Hesselink (n 54) 25–27, Rovelli (n 54) 103–19; Paul Feyerabend, Against Method (Verso Books 2010).

57

Petit (n 12).

58

However, a theory of the kind sketched further in this article might be of interest to more empirical researchers, see n 146.

59

Easterbrook (n 29) 1701.

60

cf Petit (n 12) 1452–59 (questioning Easterbrook’s premises); Fox (n 48), questioning Chicago’s claims over workability.

61

Bork (n 16) 68–69.

62

Thomas Arthur, ‘Workable Antitrust Law: The Statutory Approach to Antitrust’ (1988) 62 Tulane L Rev 1163, 1236.

63

Hovenkamp (n 13) 589 (‘this principle has a powerful administrative advantage: it does not require courts to compute welfare “tradeoffs”, because there is nothing to trade off’), 620. cf Rebecca Allensworth, ‘The Commensurability Myth in Antitrust’ (2016) 69 Vanderbilt LR 1; Fox (n 48) 1718. For references to administrability see also Nicolas Petit and others, ‘Situating Dynamic Competition: An Evolution Beyond Chicago’ (2024) Dynamic Competition Initiative (DCI) Working Paper 1-2024 <http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.4689177> accessed 7 September 2024; Kovacic (n 13) 475.

64

Jan Broulík, ‘Predictability: A Mistreated Virtue of Competition Law’ (2024) 12 J Antitrust Enforcement 362; Hovenkamp (n 13) 620 (‘maximize predictability’).

65

Predictability became an important factor for the Chicago School, with economics and ‘scientific rigour’ eliminating arbitrariness, see Bork (n 16) 6–7 (economics, science, and law); Wu (n 49) 116 (critically about Bork); Schrepel (n 18) 418 (scientific concepts); Andriychuk (n 4) 21 (decline of ‘scientific’ approach). An argument is often made that the success of hard sciences motivated quantitative assessments in government—Porter offers a different explanation, arguing that predictability based on quantification insulated bureaucratic institutions from being pre-empted or overruled by outsiders, see Theodore Porter, Trust in Numbers (Princeton University Press 1995) 8, 194–95.

66

Workability is also mentioned by Schrepel (n 18) 418–21. However, Schrepel does not define it and does not discuss it from the point of view of decision-makers, rather normative claims over how decision-makers should proceed. He concludes that legal certainty should be ensured in antitrust and refers to the OECD’s criteria for legality tests, which are: accuracy, administrability, applicability, consistency, objectivity, transparency.

67

OECD (n 10).

68

An example of this care for future decision-making can be Justice White’s opinion in Sylvania 433 US 36 (1977). As pointed out by Amato, overruling Schwinn 388 US 365 (1967) based on reasons presented by the majority put the very per se illegality of vertical price-fixing in danger, prompting Justice White to voice his concerns, see: Giuliano Amato, Antitrust and the Bounds of Power (Hart Publishing 1997) 26.

69

This turned out to be enough to change the paradigm, but unattractive in terms of practical implementations, leaving room for the Chicago–Harvard synthesis, see: Rebecca Allensworth, ‘The Influence of the Areeda-Hovenkamp Treatise in the Lower Courts and What It Means for Institutional Reform in Antitrust’ (2015) 100 Iowa L Rev 1919, 1925 (‘most of the Chicago School’s ideas were too far afield from existing antitrust law—and perhaps too politically extreme—for easy judicial adoption. Enter the Areeda-Turner treatise, which grafted economic thinkingonto existing antitrust doctrinein a way that was both more moderate andmore workablethan the scholarly proposals offered by professors like Bork and Posner’); Kovacic (n 30); Hovenkamp and Morton (n 47) 1871 (‘In choosing technical rules, the Supreme Court has almost always looked to the Harvard School’).

70

On the open-textured nature of antitrust, see eg Daniel Crane, ‘Antitrust Antitextualism’ (2021) 96 Notre Dame L Rev 1205.

71

Makan Delrahim, ‘Remarks at the Open Markets Institute Event: Antitrust and the News’ (12 June 2018) <https://www.justice.gov/opa/speech/assistant-attorney-general-makan-delrahim-delivers-remarks-open-markets-institute-event> accessed 25 January 2025. More broadly on antitrust and free speech, see: Stucke and Grunes (n 4); Day (n 4); Polański (n 4); Hillary Greene, ‘Antitrust Censorship of Economic Protest’ (2010) 59 Duke Law Journal 1037; Evelyn Douek, ‘The Rise of Content Cartels’ (Knight First Amendment Institute, 11 February 2020) <https://knightcolumbia.org/content/the-rise-of-content-cartels> accessed 25 January 2025; Neil Chilson and Casey Mattox, ‘[The] Breakup Speech: Can Antitrust Fix the Relationship between Platforms and Free Speech Values?’ (Knight First Amendment Institute, 5 March 2020) <https://knightcolumbia.org/content/the-breakup-speech-can-antitrust-fix-the-relationship-between-platforms-and-free-speech-values> accessed 25 January 2025; Jan Polański, ‘Antitrust Shrugged? Boycotts, Content Moderation, and Free Speech Cartels’ (2023) 19 Eur Competition J, 334; Jan Polański, ‘Limits, Limitations, and Outer Boundaries of Antitrust: Censorship, Free Speech, and Dominance’ (2023) 7 Market and Competition L Rev 95.

72

On prioritization, see: Or Brook and Katalin Cseres, ‘Policy Report: Priority Setting in EU and National Competition Law Enforcement’ (29 September 2021) <https://ssrn.com/abstract=3930189> accessed 25 January 2025; Or Brook and Katalin Cseres, ‘Priority Setting as the Blind Spot of Administrative Law Enforcement: A Theoretical, Conceptual, and Empirical Study of Competition Authorities in Europe’ (2024) 87 Modern L Rev 1209.

73

Petit (n 12) 1419 (sceptically about ‘political fiat’ tendencies).

74

Cezary Banasiński and Marcin Rojszczak, ‘The Role of Competition Authorities in Protecting Freedom of Speech: The PKN Orlen/Polska Press Case’ (2022) 18 Eur Competition J 424.

75

Stucke and Grunes (n 4); Polański, ‘Antitrust Shrugged’ (n 71); Polański, ‘Limits’ (n 71).

76

This controversy is well-illustrated by an exchange between Nicolas Petit, Herbert Hovenkamp, and Lazar Radic on the one side, and Ioannis Lianos and Stavros Makris on the other, see: Nicolas Petit (Twitter, 24 June 2023) <https://twitter.com/CompetitionProf/status/1672651808840220673> accessed 25 January 2025. The exchange started with Petit asking whether ‘beauty’ (seemingly understood as a moral value, not physical appearance) can be an antitrust ‘goal’, and Radic (sarcastically) commenting that there is no reason not to benchmark beauty against prices and innovation. The issue is that once it is accepted that prices and output are not the only characteristics of consumer welfare, there are indeed many product features that can be taken into account in antitrust analysis.

77

Ariel Ezrachi and Maurice Stucke, ‘The Curious Case of Competition and Quality’ (2015) 3 J Antitrust Enforcement 227.

78

Petit (n 12).

79

This applies in particular to EU antitrust law, with EU lawyers operating in the civil law tradition which does not use formal levels of proof, relying instead on holistic case assessment and the decision-maker ‘just being’ more persuaded to one story than the other, see: Fernando Castillo de la Torre and Eric Gippini Fournier, Evidence, Proof and Judicial Review in EU Competition Law (Edward Elgar Publishing 2017) 34–36, 79–86.

80

Some sceptics, eg Schrepel (n 18) 421, look therefore with distrust at probabilistic ‘potential effects’ arguments, seeing them as opening the door to ‘antitrust romance’. Still, ‘potentiality’ does not go against the consumer welfare standard, which even the sceptics seem to admit, see Petit (n 12) 1403 (recognizing more probabilistic interpretations of the standard).

81

On heuristics, see: Ezrachi and Stucke (n 77) 228; cf Thibault Schrepel, ‘Heuristic Antitrust’ (Network Law Review, 19 August 2019) <https://www.networklawreview.org/heuristic-antitrust> accessed 25 January 2025.

82

Associated Press 326 US 1 (1945).

83

More broadly on the case context, see: Daniel Crane, ‘Collaboration and Competition in Information and News During Antitrust’s Formative Era’ (Knight First Amendment Institute, 29 June 2020) <https://knightcolumbia.org/content/collaboration-and-competition-in-information-and-news-during-antitrusts-formative-era> accessed 25 January 2025, 12–15; Daniel Crane, ‘Antitrust as an Instrument of Democracy’ (2022) 72 Duke LJ Online 21, 30–31.

84

cf Bork (n 16) 50.

85

See eg Sandeep Vaheesan, ‘The Twilight of the Technocrats’ Monopoly on Antitrust?’ (2018) Yale LJ Forum 980, 986–87 (short-term and long-term interests); Andriychuk (n 33) 161 (preference for short-term interests); Lianos (n 4) 175, 179–85 (on current and future consumers).

86

On time (and various other commensurability problems), see also: Allensworth (n 63) 20–22.

87

This can be compared to Ezrachi’s ‘sponge’ losing its shape completely, see Ariel Ezrachi, ‘Sponge’ (2017) 5 J Antitrust Enforcement 49.

88

See also Allensworth (n 63) for numerous commensurability myths. While the factors discussed earlier involve much subjectivity, this is not to say that there are no circumstances of a more objective nature that may incentivise decision-makers to act in a specific way. For example, if statutory procedural rules of a jurisdiction (which may be less open-textured than substantive antitrust provisions) allocate the burden of proof in a specific way, this might become a more objective factor. Another example may be the institutional setting, discussed by Petit (n 12). For instance, if a decision-maker has more control over the performance of the entire antitrust law system (eg the system leaves less room for private enforcement, ensuring that a specialized administrative agency exerts stronger influence over the development of case law), one could assume that this more objective factor will have an impact on how the decision-maker approaches prospective consistency as a factor or uncertainty as a moving element (eg the decision-maker might be less concerned about harmful case law developments, because the decision-maker will have more control over what becomes case law).

89

On Overton Window in antitrust, see Robert Lange, ‘Antitrust Ideas that Progressives Should Resurrect: Conglomerate Merger Legislation, No-Fault Monopolization, and Merger Incipiency’ (2024) 53 U Baltimore LR 481, 513–14. This is in line with Radin’s: ‘Law is what courts and partly irresponsible administrative agencies will do or say within the limits set by statutesand public opinion’, see Max Radin, ‘Legal Realism’ (1931) 31 Columbia LR 824.

90

For a brief mention of zeitgeist in antitrust scholarship, see: Douglas Ginsburg, ‘Bork’s “Legislative Intent” and the Courts’ (2014) 79 Antitrust LJ 941, 944 (‘Though it is, of course, possible that other changes in the zeitgeist made Bork’s thesis more appealing to the Court, the attribution to Bork both by the Ninth Circuit and by Justice White leave little reason to doubt that Bork’s work was the proximate cause of the paradigm shift in the Court’s jurisprudence’). The notion of ‘zeitgeist’ shows resemblance to Foucault’s ‘episteme’ by which he means ‘the totality of relations’ that govern discursive practices in a given period, setting the limits of what can be done. For a brief discussion, see: Rik Peters, ‘The Episteme and the Historical A Priori’ (2021) 29 J French and Francophone Philosophy 109, 111–13. The term was originally used in Michel Foucault, The Order of Things (Routledge 2002). See also: Case C-23/14 Post Danmark [2015] EU:C:2015:343, Opinion of AG Kokott, para 4 (‘the Court should not allow itself to be influenced so much by current thinking (“Zeitgeist”) or ephemeral trends’).

91

Bork (n 16) 8.

92

Benjamin Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process (Yale University Press 1921) 12. cf Wu (n 49) 116 (speculating about more negative reasons for decision-makers’ conduct). See, however, also n 113.

93

See eg following perspectives: history and philosophy—Bertrand Russell, History of Western Philosophy (Routledge 2004); economic (Chicago)—Milton Friedman and Rose Friedman, ‘The Tide in the Affairs of Men’ (1 April 1989) <https://fee.org/articles/the-tide-in-the-affairs-of-men> accessed 25 January 2025, which was itself influenced by a legal/sociological perspective—Albert Dicey, Lectures on the Relation between Law and Public Opinion (Liberty Fund 2008); modern financial investment—Ray Dalio, Principles for Dealing with the Changing World Order (Simon & Schuster 2021).

94

Russell, ibid 2; Friedman and Friedman, ibid, observing: ‘a major change in social and economic policy is preceded by a shift in the climate of intellectual opinion, itself generated, at least in part, by contemporaneous social, political, and economic circumstances’.

95

See in particular: Friedman and Friedman (n 93); see also: Thomas Sowell, Knowledge and Decisions (Basic Books 1996) xi–xii (discussing dynamics of social movements); Dalio (n 93) 43–55 (discussing his theory of big cycles and mentioning how ‘values change from generation to generation’).

96

Angus Burgin, The Great Persuasion (Harvard University Press 2015) 218–22. Based on archival research, Burgin recounts that Friedman’s interest in Dicey dated back to 1951 and was expressed both publicly and in private correspondence. In a way, Dicey’s observations became a blueprint for Friedman on how to initiate policy changes. In 1989, when the neoliberal project was already firmly established, Milton and Rose Friedman authored an article reminding about Dicey’s ideas, and warning about a possible reversal of the neoliberal successes, see: Friedman and Friedman (n 93). To put it further in perspective, Aaron Director (Rose Friedman’s brother) also quoted Dicey in his rather scarce written research, see Aaron Director, ‘The Parity of the Economic Market Place’ (1953) 2 U Chicago L School Record. Bork (Director’s student) mentions Dicey in The Antitrust Paradox, see Bork (n 16) 439.

97

Dicey (n 93) 18.

98

David Leonhardt, ‘“Wreak yourself upon the world”‘(Yale Alumni Magazine, Jan/Feb 2024), noting: ‘Bork and Friedman believed they were playing the long game … Bork and Friedman expected that the economy would fall into a new crisis, and public opinion might shift’. The ‘long game’ and focus on shaping the climate of opinion also applied to Hayek, which he admitted in an interview with Bork, see: Shoshana Zuboff, The Age of Surveillance Capitalism (Profile Books 2019) 520.

99

Oles Andriychuk, The Normative Foundations of European Competition Law (Edward Elgar Publishing 2017) 51. See also: Bork (n 16) 181 (discussing how a change in the ‘intellectual climate of opinion’ initiates policy shifts).

100

On dialectics, see: Andriychuk (n 33); Andriychuk (n 99) 143–57.

101

Matt Stoller, Goliath (Simon & Schuster 2019) 337–38 (‘A new generation was entering politics, one that had, since the 1950s, been taught an entirely different story …’).

102

Max Planck, Scientific Autobiography and Other Papers (Williams & Norgate 1950) 33–34.

103

Kuhn (n 40) 150.

104

Burgin (n 96) 218.

105

Kuhn (n 40). On crisis in antitrust, see Crane (n 6). Against this backdrop, Gramsci’s description of the crisis seems more than fitting: ‘the crisis consists precisely in the fact that the old is dying and the new cannot be born; in this interregnum a great variety of morbid symptoms appear’, see: Gilbert Achcar, ‘Morbid Symptoms: What Did Gramsci Really Mean?’ (2021) 1 Notebooks: Journal for Studies on Power 379.

106

See, in particular, Kuhn (n 40) 37 (noting eg that ‘one of the things a scientific community acquires with a paradigm is a criterion for choosing problems … To a great extent these are the only problems that the community will admit as scientific … Other problems, including many that had previously been standard, are rejected as metaphysical, as the concern of another discipline … A paradigm can, for that matter, even insulate the community from those socially important problems that are not reducible to the puzzle form’).

107

Kuhn (n 40) 111.

108

ibid 150–51

109

See eg Barak Orbach, ‘Antitrust Populism’ (2017) 14 New York UJ Law & Business 1, 7 (arguing that historically, technological changes, economic crises, and demographic shifts were conducive to populism, ie opinion swings); Jonathan Baker, ‘Not a Simple Story of Big Business Capture: An Essay on the Political Economy of Antitrust’ (2023) 85 Antitrust LJ 521, 533 (about intellectual climate); Cristina Caffarra, ‘Antitrust and the Political Economy’ (CEPR, 5 January 2024) <https://cepr.org/voxeu/columns/antitrust-and-political-economy-part-1> accessed 25 January 2025 (‘polycrisis’); Thibault Schrepel, ‘The Expected Impact of “Great Power Competition” on Antitrust Policy’ (Network Law Review, 17 May 2023) <https://www.networklawreview.org/great-power-competition> accessed 25 January 2025 (geopolitics).

110

George Stigler, ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation’ (1971) 2 Bell J Economics and Management Science 3.

111

James Kwak, ‘Cultural Capture and the Financial Crisis’ in Daniel Carpenter and David Moss (eds), Preventing Regulatory Capture (CUP 2013).

112

Jan Broulík, ‘Cultural Capture of Competition Policy: Exploring the Risk in the US and the EU’ (2022) 45 World Competition 159. See also: Lancieri and others (n 24); Ezrachi (n 87) 70–71.

113

As argued, this may be caused by decision-makers seeing private practitioners as having higher status. This fits Wu (n 49) 116, who speculates that some decision-makers might be anxiety-ridden and seek validation. cf n 92.

114

Cass Sunstein, ‘Stigler’s Interest-Group Theory of Regulation: A Skeptical Note’ (ProMarket, 16 April 2021) <https://www.promarket.org/2021/04/16/george-stigler-theory-regulation-capture-cass-sunstein> accessed 25 January 2025; Filippo Lancieri, ‘The Mechanisms of Regulatory Capture’ (ProMarket, 15 June 2022) <https://www.promarket.org/2022/06/15/new-ebook-revisits-george-stiglers-theories-of-regulatory-capture-50-years-later> accessed 25 January 2025. See also: Ezrachi (n 87) 70.

115

Lancieri and others (n 24) 519.

116

Broulík (n 112) 185.

117

Friedrich Hayek, ‘The Intellectuals and Socialism’ (1949) 16 U Chicago L Rev 417; Sowell (n 95) 331–68 (on intellectuals exerting power).

118

In some variants, when capture is intentional, this theory can further be compared to ‘hidden-hand explanations’, which are ‘the opposite of invisible-hand ones, tend toward ruling-class (or, more extremely, conspiracy) theories’, see: Nozick, ‘Invisible-Hand’ (n 41) 316.

119

For a review of arguments, see eg Lucas Bietti and others, ‘Storytelling as Adaptive Collective Sensemaking’ (2019) 11 Topics in Cognitive Science 710.

120

James White, Heracles’ Bow: Essays on the Rhetoric and Poetics of the Law (University of Wisconsin Press 1985) 169, quoted in Pauline Phoa, ‘Narratives in Flux: Legal Language, Digital Technologies, and the Climate Crisis’ (2023) 2 Comparative L and Language 1.

121

Richard Boyd, ‘Metaphor and Theory Change: What is “metaphor” a Metaphor for?’ in Andrew Ortony (ed), Metaphor and Thought (CUP 1993); Thomas Kuhn, ‘Metaphor in science’ in Andrew Ortony (ed), Metaphor and Thought (CUP 1993). For legal scholarship, see eg Lon Fuller, Legal Fictions (Stanford University Press 1967) 24 (‘Metaphor is the traditional device of persuasion. Eliminate metaphor from the law and you have reduced its power to convince and convert’); Jonas Ebbesson, ‘Law, Power and Language: Beware of Metaphors’ (2008) 53 Scandinavian Studies in Law 259.

122

George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Metaphors We Live By (University of Chicago Press 2003) 145 (‘Much of cultural change arises from the introduction of new metaphorical concepts and the loss of old ones’; see, however, the entire argument in the book), 190 (on Plato, Aristotle, Hobbes, and Locke).

123

Abrams 250 US 616 (1919).

124

It also attracted Chicago scholars, see Director (n 96).

125

See eg Morgan Weiland, ‘First Amendment Metaphors: The Death of the “Marketplace of Ideas” and the Rise of the Post-Truth “Free Flow of Information”’ (2022) 33 Yale J Law & the Humanities 366.

126

See also: Alec Klein, ‘A Hard Look at Media Mergers’ (The Washington Post, 29 November 2000) <https://www.washingtonpost.com/archive/business/2000/11/29/a-hard-look-at-media-mergers/d8380c2d-92ee-4b1b-8ffd-f43893ab0055> accessed 25 January 2025 (Pitofsky mentioning ‘lumber’ instead). Ironically, some of the sceptics seem to be well-aware of the power of storytelling, see Schrepel (n 18) 419 (‘Emotionally compelling anecdotes are a more effective form of communication than calculus and graphs’).

127

Michael Boudin, ‘Antitrust Doctrine and the Sway of Metaphor’ (1986) 75 Georgetown LJ 395, 396.

128

Pauline Phoa, EU Law as a Creative Process (Europa Law Publishing 2021) 18 (‘ECJ cases usually make for dry reading’); Petit (n 12) 1426.

129

Case C-8/08 T-Mobile Netherlands [2009] EU:C:2009:110, Opinion of AG Kokott, para 47.

130

See the subsection ‘Beneath the surface: the antitrust standards paradox’ .

131

For a surprising parallel, see: Sowell (n 95) 137–38 (‘traffic laws, like all other arbitrary rules, imply such social “inefficiencies”arbitrary, categorical or “bureaucratic” rules in general cannot be criticised as wrong merely because some individual consequences are sometimes nonsensical’).

132

Another example might be the opinion of Advocate-General Bobek in Budapest Bank. The opinion attracted much attention because of its fish metaphor explaining what makes a case fishy enough to analyse it as a ‘by effect’ infringement, see: Case C‑228/18 Budapest Bank [2020] EU:C:2019:678, Opinion of AG Bobek, para 51.

133

Kanter (n 27). Some note that ‘consumer welfare’ itself has great rhetorical power, see Orbach (n 26) 135; Herbert Hovenkamp, The Antitrust Enterprise: Principle and Execution (Harvard University Press 2006) 31.

134

Kovacic (n 30) 56–59 provides an account of the popularization and misrepresentation of the term. See also: Petit and others (n 63) 20 (accepting occasional protection of inefficient rivals).

135

Kim Hart, ‘Mr Schmidt goes to Washington’ (Politico, 20 September 2011) <https://www.politico.com/story/2011/09/mr-schmidt-goes-to-washington-063989> accessed 25 January 2025.

136

Schrepel (n 18). cf Polański (n 38) 263 (about realistic romantism); Crane (n 70) 1247 (about American romantism). In the past, Neelie Kroes was also criticized for using metaphors, see: Nicolas Petit, ‘The Limits of Antitrust Metaphors’ (Chillin’Competition, 22 January 2010) <https://chillingcompetition.com/2010/01/22/the-limits-of-antitrust-metaphors> accessed 25 January 2025.

137

Wu (n 2) 9. On how such ‘X is Y’ (eg ‘argument is war’, ‘time is money’) metaphors have strong impact on the understanding of reality, see Lakoff and Johnson (n 122) 3–6, 46–51, 139–46.

138

Maurice Stucke and Ariel Ezrachi, Competition Overdose (Harper Business 2020) 121–61.

139

Spencer Waller, ‘A Pop Culture Guide to Antitrust’ (2022) 36 Antitrust 60.

140

See eg Schrepel (n 81). See also: Herbert Hovenkamp, ‘Rhetoric and Skepticism in Antitrust Argument’ (1986) 84 Michigan L Rev 1721 (criticizing rhetoric in late Chicago arguments).

141

See text to n 94. Given this ‘loop’, the title of this section rephrases Douglas Hofstadter, I Am a Strange Loop (Basic Books 2008). Hofstadter is one of popularisers of memetics.

142

See, in particular, text to n 69.

143

As mentioned in n 88, this does not necessarily mean that there are no ‘limits’ of more objective nature that could be investigated in future research. For example, Petit discussed how different institutional settings in the US and the EU may affect the practical choices of decision-makers, and thus shape antitrust. From the EU perspective, a further area of research could be to investigate to what extent the perception of workability factors discussed in Section 3 is shaped by eg the amount of resources available to decision-makers (with the European Commission and EU courts typically having more resources at their disposal than at the level of individual member states, possibly providing national decision-makers with stronger incentives to ensure that the applicable approach is simple). Those types of issues could be studied more systematically and compared across jurisdictions.

144

Aside from this article, memes have also attracted the attention of other antitrust authors, who however discussed them from a different point of view, see: Richard Langlois, ‘Memes and Myths of Antitrust’ (2024) Mercatus Working Paper Series <http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.4898032> accessed 25 January 2025.

145

See n 53.

146

Francis Heylighen and Klaas Chielens, ‘Evolution of Culture, Memetics’ in Robert Meyers (ed), Encyclopedia of Complexity and Systems Science (Springer 2009) 3218 (‘The theory of memetics and cultural evolution holds out great promises for a better understanding, anticipation and control of fundamental social problems that depend on the propagation of ideas and behaviors’).

147

See eg Nicolas Petit and Thibault Schrepel, ‘Complexity‑minded Antitrust’ (2023) 33 J Evolutionary Economics 541.

148

Daniel Crane, ‘How Much Brandeis Do the Neo-Brandeisians Want?’ (2019) 64 Antitrust Bulletin 531.

149

Using Heylighen and Chielens (n 146) 3215–16 criteria for successful memes, the Neobrandeisian did well with eg novelty (in the late 2010s, the Neobrandeisian claims were fresh to a large group of listeners who had not taken part in the forming of the Chicago–Harvard paradigm in the 1980s) and repetition (the more the Neobrandeisians were ridiculed by the sceptics, the more publicity they received).

150

See eg Case C-377/20 Servizio Elettrico Nazionale [2022] EU:C:2022:379.

151

See an exchange between Nicolas Petit, Thibault Schrepel, and Herbert Hovenkamp, commenting on Cristina Caffarra’s claims: Nicolas Petit (X, 9 May 2024) <https://x.com/CompetitionProf/status/1788486845493371386> accessed 25 January 2025.

152

In fact, this is what Caffarra seems to have meant, contrary to how Petit, Schrepel, and Hovenkamp interpreted her article.

153

Kuhn’s argument is also noteworthy in the context of claims that antitrust should be ‘scientific’ and ‘objective’, see eg Bork (n 16) 6–7, Schrepel (n 18) 418. There seems to be much confusion with regard to antitrust, science, quantification, and ‘objectivity’—for clarifications, see eg Kuhn (n 40); Rovelli (n 54) 103–30; Porter (n 65); Lakoff and Johnson (n 122) 185–237.

154

On paradigms, see Kuhn (n 40) 24 (which paradigm wins), 111 (revolutions), 144 (competition), 147 (‘competition between paradigms is not the sort of battle that can be resolved by proofs’). As regards memetics, Heylighen and Chielens (n 146) 3215–16 argue, for instance, that memes that include an element of novelty have more power. To put it in antitrust perspective, recently some of the sceptics have shown much interest in dynamic competition and complexity theory, presenting them as going beyond Chicago, see eg Petit and others (n 63). While the reformers could ask whether those are actual upgrades or a rebranding under Lampedusa’s ‘Everything must change so that everything can stay the same’, this nonetheless might be a more effective strategy than defending the old paradigm.

155

Thus, one option could be to systematically map out areas in which enforcement can be adjusted more easily (including possible sub-strategies for each of such areas), see eg Polański (n 38). See also eg: Stavros Makris, ‘EU Competition Law as Responsive Law’ (2021) 23 Cambridge YB Eur L Studies 228 (discussing how antitrust oscillates between openness and integrity, and how the indeterminacy of antitrust can be handled); Andriychuk (n 4), on what role legal realism may play in antitrust.

156

Kuhn (n 40) 200–01. A more literary version of this problem is discussed in the widely acclaimed 1961 Solaris by Lem. In Solaris, a scientific community tries to establish communication with Solaris, which seems to be a planet-size living organism. With further failed attempts to establish communication, and ever-new scientific positions and subdisciplines in the field of study now known as ‘Solaristics’, scholars themselves become unable to communicate with one another. This leads one of the scholars to finally ask: ‘how can you communicate with the planet, if you are not even able to communicate with each other anymore?’. It turns out that the problem is not so much Solaris/antitrust, but those who try to understand it.

157

Kuhn (n 40) 201.

158

In fact, this is also what happened with ‘sustainability’ at the EU level, with EU enforcers integrating sustainability issues into antitrust but within the logic of consumer benefits.

159

See eg Justin Hurwitz, ‘Chevron and Administrative Antitrust, Redux’ (2023) 30 George Mason L Rev 971.

160

See eg Maciej Bernatt, ‘Transatlantic Perspective on Judicial Deference in Administrative Law’ (2016) 22 Columbia J Eur L 275.

161

‘Warren Leads Senate Response to End of Chevron Doctrine’ (23 July 2024) <https://www.warren.senate.gov/newsroom/press-releases/warren-leads-senate-response-to-end-of-chevron-doctrine> accessed 25 January 2025.

162

eg while independence requirements are applicable to national competition authorities, this is less so at the EU level, even despite the fact the European Union has become ‘a more political union’. On increasing legitimacy in antitrust, see eg Anna Gerbrandy, ‘Addressing the Legitimacy Problem for Competition Authorities Taking into Account Non-economic Values: The Position of the Dutch Competition Authority’ (2015) 40 Eur LR 769.

163

For the quotation, see n 123.

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

The views expressed in this text are the author’s own and do not necessarily reflect those of the Polish Office of Competition and Consumer Protection (UOKiK). The author discloses that he was involved in drafting the Polish Competition Authority’s OECD position referred to in this article. The author would like to express his gratitude to two anonymous reviewers who commented on this article in November 2024, and to two anonymous reviewers who had provided comments on an earlier version of this article in March–June 2024. An earlier version of this article had also been presented at the ‘Modern Bigness Conference’, held on 4–5 April 2024, in Utrecht; the author would like to thank all conference participants for their comments, in particular Oliver Budzinski for his comments about philosophy of science. The author would also like to thank Anna Gerbrandy, Pauline Phoa, and Eva Lachnit for the opportunity to discuss various drafts of this article in 2023–24.

This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/), which permits non-commercial reproduction and distribution of the work, in any medium, provided the original work is not altered or transformed in any way, and that the work is properly cited. For commercial re-use, please contact [email protected] for reprints and translation rights for reprints. All other permissions can be obtained through our RightsLink service via the Permissions link on the article page on our site—for further information please contact [email protected].